IV. Concerning the Relation of Mind and Medium in Aesthetic Appre- Ciation Little Need Be Said

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

IV. Concerning the Relation of Mind and Medium in Aesthetic Appre- Ciation Little Need Be Said MIND AND MEDIUM IN ARTf. (1V.j BY EDWARD BULLOUGH. I AGREE with Mr Walkley’s criticism of Mr Marriott’s proposal to base an aesthetic theory upon Medium and its technical manipulation. The attempt has been made more than once-the example of Semper has been mentioned by Mr Watt-and has always broken down in the face of objections such as are urged by Mr Walkley-in the last resort because Art is a manifestation of mind and cannot be satisfactorily accounted for by the nature and treatment of the material it employs. The second part of Mr Walkley’s paper rests upon the theory of Benedetto Croce. I am in doubt how far I agree or disagree with him. Croce’s aesthetic theory does not stand by itself, as is far too commonly supposed. It is part of a general philosophical, and in addition monistic, system and is exposed to all the difficulties created by such a depen- dence. I feel doubt about the fourfold division of the activities of the spirit; about the precise limits of the theoretical and practical activities; about the ultimate implications of his general point of view; as regards the aesthetic sphere in particular, about the nature of the ‘intuition’ and the essential ‘lyricism’ of Art, and their consequences. Indeed, I am inclined to agree with the objections recently urged by G. A. Borgese in the Preface to the new edition of his Storia della critica romantica in Italia2. I readily admit that Croce’s conception of intuition as the A contribution to the Symposium presented at the Congress of Philosophy in Oxford, 24-27 September, 1920. “Compiutosi in De Sanctis lo svolgimento della critica cosidett,aromantica, due vie restavano ape&; o attuare ulteriormente e piii risolutamente quells restaurazione del senso classic0 dell’ arte che in Italia paradossalmente si cbiami, romanticismo, 0, traverao quell0 peeudoromanticismo, pervenire ad un romanticismo autentico. I1 Croce s’ avvib, senza notevoli perpleasiti, per questa seconda strada, e sempre pih si raffermb nel considerare 1’ arte come inetinto, come ‘Genie,’ come irreducibile individua- lit&,come ‘hohe Intuition’ anteriore alla logica e alla volont&,come liricith pura, come interiezione, come grido. 11 suo metodo critic0 si and6 sempre pi5 precisando in tre canoni: (1”) negare qualunque continuith di sviluppo nella storia dell’ arte, tutta frantn- mandola nelle monadi senza finestre delle singole individualit& poetiche; (2’) cercare in ogni poeta 1’ opera fondamentale e genuina, generalmente di prima e spontanea gioventh, rifiutando come aovrapposizioni logiche e volitive i suoi pretesi progressi di matiwith; (3”) leggere ogni poeta ed ogni opera come un’ antologia in cui alcuni frammenti lirioi EDWARDBULLOUGH 27 kernel of the artistic attitude, his antagonism to the current treatment of the history of Art and to the sterile discussions of the differences and relative position of the arts, and his insistence on the unity and unique- ness of Art, etc. have rendered immense services to aesthetic studies; yet I cannot but feel a certain sympathy with the complaint of Professor Hosanquet (with whose aesthetic views I otherwise disagree) that Croce’s theory yields little enlightenment on the particular subject now under discussion. Croce’s theory is a philosoghical, not a psychological, statement, and there is much that seems psychologically obscure in it. Moreover, the subject of the present debate is in itself, as a matter of psychological fact, so obscure that its elucidation would appear to me as little furthered by a philosophical treatment which deals with it from an ideal point of view, as by Mr Marriott’s hypothetical illustrations which substitute assumptions for experience. I. What do we actually know about the relation of Mind and Medium in Art? By Medium I assume we mean the material or physical datum which the artist handles: paint and canvas; chalk and paper; marble or bronze; brick or stone or concrete; the tones of an instrument or the human voice; the human body, its gestures and attitudes, whether in actual space as in dancing or acting, or in imaginary space as in the cinematograph film. By Technique I mean the manipulation of these media. The Mind refers, I take it, to the mind of the artist as well as of the spectator or listener (recipient), but chiefly to the former. As regards the term Art, I must beg leave to make one or two more extensive observations. In the first place we would, I believe, all agree that Art represents but a segment of the whole range of aesthetic activity. The aesthetic attitude embraces the appreciation of natural objects as well as of artefacts; it covers certain borderlands of Art such as cere- monial and ritual which have admittedly artistic sanities; it permeates ordinary human intercourse in what we vaguely call ‘ manners.’ As a matter of personal conviction, I hold that there is nothing in the whole range of personal experience from sheer sense-experience to the most abstract thought which may not be the object of aesthetic contemplation. To speak of medium in this case becomes exceedingly difficult, because the medium is, I presume, one’s very self-as, in fact, it is in certain siano artificialmente ricuciti per 1’ illusione extraestetica di raggiungere 1’ unit&. Con particolare evidenze i suoi saggi recenti, specie quello su Goethe, mostrano la volonth di sottoporre quasi ogni dramma, quasi ogni poema all’ analiii disgregatrice che la filologia romantica sperimentb sui poemi omerici.” (pp. xix-xx.) G. A. Borgese, Xtoriu ddla critim romntica in Italia, Treves, Milano. 1920. 28 Mind and Medium in Art types of acting: la plastique de l’cime. Of this vast realm of sometimes most tenuous and elusive experience, the title restricts us to the most condensed-if I may use a contradiction in terms-the most material, but also the most deliberate and most intentional form of the aesthetic state. 11. Further, I believe it to be important to point out the distinction between Art in its static and Art in its dynamic aspect. The distinction is important because, though it is constantly overlooked, it affects the relation between mind and mdumin several particulars, and incidentally also the conception of a history of Art, the interplay of social and individual factors and the continuity of artistic and aesthetic tradition. By Art in its static aspect I mean what I cannot do better than describe as “the objective world of Art,” i.e. the accumulations of art- treasures in our museums and collections, the art-objects as material things, independently of all considerations of their subjective origins, the intentions and ideals of their creators; independently also of our aesthetic attitude to them, regarded merely as objects, as remains of antiquity or illustrations of the past. Art in its dynamic aspect is Art regarded from the point of view of the creative artist or actively appreciating recipient; as an aesthetic object. There is of course a constant interchange between these two conceptions of Art. An art-object which today is dynamic for me, may to-morrow have become static. A picture may one day belong in my eyes to the objective world of Art and the next day may assume a dynamic aspect. To say that as a static object it had no aesthetic exist- ence for me, is of course true-that is precisely the distinction-; yet I knew all along that it was an art-object and was regarded as such by others for whom it had become dynamic. And its claim to become dynamic for me also was there with it and exercised a certain moulding influence upon my aesthetic attitude. This silent, collective and largely anonymous pressure of the “objective world of Art” is probably the most potent agency in the art-education of the individual. It represents in its cumulative force, created by the forgotten but combined verdict of past generations-to whom it also owes its preservation-a tremendous standardising power upon the schooling of appreciation and produces adaptations, expectancies, apperceptions and emotional reactions which in their varying degree of rigidity and durability result in more or less fixed habits of taste. This applies to generations as well as individuals. The “objective world of Art” and dynamic Art are naturally never co- EDWARDBULLOUGIH 29 extensive. For the majority of persons the vast number of art-objects never become dynamic; but the appeal to become so remains and is satisfied in proportion to the powers of imagination, the emotional elasticity and the extension of the organised interests of the individual appreciator. The same standardising pressure is exercised upon the artist. The beginnings of every artist are necessarily imitative. What should he imitate but what was there before him? This necessity is reinforced by the capacity of absorption and of admiration which distinguishes the artist as a psychological type. It is further forced upon him by +he perpetual technical struggle in which every actively creative artist lives. Defeat in this struggle means incapacity or mannerism. Indeed, it is precisely on the technical side that static Art exercises its strongest influence upon the artist, for it represents the continuity of technical development-distinct from, though not unrelated to, the aesthetic discontinuity of Art history-and technique is the one thing in Art that can be taught-up to a certain point. Incidentally static Art acts as a kind of background for the ricochet of general public sentiment and its attitude towards Art upon the artist, and as a reaction both to this sentiment and to the technical teaching beyond the point where in the artist’s development technique ceases to be impersonal, common know- ledge and becomes an intimately personal process interwoven with his artistic imagination, static Art becomes the spring-board of reaction, revolt and revolution.
Recommended publications
  • Walter Pater's Aesthetic Historicism
    Transfigured World · CAROLYN WILLIAMS · Transfigured World · WALTER PATER'S AESTHETIC HISTORICISM · Cornell University Press ITHACA AND LONDON Copyright © 1989 by Cornell University All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book, or parts thereof, must not be reproduced in any form without permission in writing from the publisher. For information, address Cornell University Press, Sage House, 512 East State Street, Ithaca, New York 14850, or visit our website at www.cornellpress.cornell.edu. First published 1989 by Cornell University Press. First printing, Cornell Paperbacks, 2016. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Williams, Carolyn, 1950– Transfigured world: Walter Pater’s aesthetic historicism / Carolyn Williams p. cm. Includes index. ISBN 978-0-8014-2151-8 (cloth : alk. paper) ISBN 978-1-5017-0724-7 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Pater, Walter, 1839–1894—Aesthetics. 2. Pater, Walter, 1839–1894— Knowledge—History. 3. Historicism. I. Title. PR5138.A35W5 1989 824'.8—dc20 89-42883 The text of this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ For Cecil Lang Contents Acknowledgments ix Abbreviations xi Introduction I Part One • Opening Conclusions II I. "That Which Is Without" 14 2. "The Inward World of Thought and Feeling" 18 3. Aestheticism 26 4. Answerable Style 37 5. Iiistoricism 46 6. Aesthetic Iiistoricism and "Aesthetic Poetry" 57 7. The Poetics of Revival 68 Part Two • Figural Strategies in Th e Renaissance 79 I. Legend and Iiistoricity 82 2. Myths of Iiistory: Th e Last Supper 94 3. The Iiistoricity of Myth 103 4.
    [Show full text]
  • AH 302: the Idea of the Aesthetic Syllabus Course Description Texts
    Fall 2020 AH 302: The Idea of the Aesthetic Syllabus The schedule of classes/readings is subject to change. Registered students should consult the syllabus on Google Classrooms, which will be kept updated. Instructor: Katalin Makkai Course times: Monday and Wednesday 15:45-17:15 Email: [email protected] Office hours: TBA Office: P98 004 Course description “Aesthetics” and “aesthetic” are terms that are often taken for granted inside as well as outside academic discourse. We speak of aesthetic experiences and judgments and qualities, and we employ “aesthetics” to designate the study of such matters. Although their root is taken from the Greek, the now-familiar terms (in their now-familiar usages) are, however, comparatively new. They are commonly regarded as having been introduced into the philosophical lexicon in the eighteenth century—a few hundred years ago. This course studies some of the texts that were key to the discovery, or perhaps the invention, of the “aesthetic”. What work was the idea meant to do? How did its evolution retain or reconfigure its original senses and purposes? Is the idea of the aesthetic problematic, ideological, or chimerical? Do we need an idea of the aesthetic to think about art? Texts All readings will be provided during the semester electronically and are to be brought to class as printouts. Electronic devices Students may not use any electronic devices (laptop, tablet, mobile phone) in the classroom, unless an accommodation letter has been issued. Requirements ACADEMIC INTEGRITY ​ ​ ​ Bard College Berlin maintains the staunchest regard for academic integrity and expects good academic practice from students in their studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ethical Significance of the Aesthetic Experience of Non-Representational Art Taylor Rogers Oberlin College
    The Ethical Significance of the Aesthetic Experience of Non-Representational Art Taylor Rogers Oberlin College May, 2011 I. Introduction II. Key Terms III. Key Features of Aesthetic Experience: Attention & Distraction IV. Delicacy & Distance V. The Ethical Significance of Perceptual Delicacy VI. Ethico-Aesthetic Properties VII. Delicacy and Representational Art VIII. Conclusion Bibliography 1 I. Introduction This paper‟s aim is to give an account of the distinctive ethical significance of the aesthetic experience of non-representational art. I hope to demonstrate how perceptual skills necessary for such engagement prove to be ethical as well as aesthetic skills. First, I will offer some background on the nature of aesthetic experience, before adopting Noël Carroll‟s content- oriented account for my own investigation. After clarifying my use of “aesthetic experience,” I explain my focus on non-representational art, illustrating the way in which it more accessibly fosters pure aesthetic experience, as opposed to art that is representational. By employing the terms „non-representational‟ and „representational,‟ I will be referring to paradigm cases of each sort of art as a way of circumventing the need for an account of when and how art represents. Mitchell Green in “Empathy, Expression and What Artworks Have to Teach” asserts, “Some forms of engagement with works of art…either convey or activate a skill1.” In light of this assertion, I analyze how one‟s aesthetic engagement with non-representational art distinctly cultivates the skill of sensitive perception, or, „delicacy,‟ which allows one to perceive all of the aesthetically relevant features present in a work of art, no matter how subtle.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 585: Emotions in the Arts Spring 2009 Professors Paul Guyer and Elisabeth Camp
    Philosophy 585: Emotions in the Arts Spring 2009 Professors Paul Guyer and Elisabeth Camp Contact Information Paul Guyer Office: 421 Cohen Hall Office Hours: Thursdays 2-4 and by appointment Email: [email protected] Elisabeth Camp Office: 426 Cohen Hall Office Hours: Thursdays 1:30 to 3 and by appointment Email: [email protected] Course Description This course will investigate historical and contemporary philosophical views on the role of the emotions in the arts. Do we have genuine emotional responses to works of art – to fiction? paintings? music? If so, what are the conditions under which we do and don't have such emotional responses? When are such responses appropriate? In particular, does an appropriate aesthetic attitude require emotional distance from the object of the artwork? Is it inappropriate to respond emotionally to morally depraved artworks? How do formal devices induce, constrain, and otherwise alter our emotional responses to art? Readings will be drawn from philosophers including Jean-Baptiste Du Bos, David Hume, Edmund Burke, Moses Mendelssohn, Henry Home Lord Kames, Arthur Schopenhauer, Edward Bullough, R.G. Collingwood, Tamar Szabo Gendler, Richard Moran, Kendall Walton, and others. Course Requirements Everyone registered for the course will be expected to lead discussion for one meeting; auditors are strongly encouraged to do so as well. We hope you can do this in pairs. Your main task is to bring out the philosophical issues in play, and specifically to locate the readings in relation to each other; raising questions for discussion is much more important than summarizing. You should also prepare a handout, no more than 2 pages long, which can easily be reviewed in class, to help coordinate the discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Accepts That the Traditional Definition of Abstrac- Tion Does Apply to Some
    9781405169226_4_00A.qxd 12/8/08 7:50 PM Page 107 A abstraction Artworks are abstract, we might accepts that the traditional definition of abstrac- think, when they do not represent: abstraction tion does apply to some paintings. The prob- is simply the absence of representation. After all, lem is that it does not apply to most of those we there is a natural contrast between abstract think of as abstract. and representational painting; and music, at We can flesh out the second difficulty by least in its “absolute” (i.e., abstract) form, does considering either abstract painting or music. not clearly represent at all. Absolute music, It is hardly plausible that these never make like abstract painting, expresses feelings and any reference to things beyond themselves. perhaps thoughts, but, we suppose, expression The idea that they express emotions and ideas and representation are different. is intended to concede as much, without rein- However, there are two difficulties with tak- troducing representation. But is it clear that ing this to capture the nature of abstraction. expression is not simply another form of repre- First, on closer inspection it excludes art that sentation? Of course, it differs from some kinds intuitively counts as abstract; and second, the of representing – from the depiction that con- definition is only as clear as the rather murky cerns Wollheim, for instance, or from describing notion of representation itself. things in language. But the notion of represen- To illustrate the first difficulty, consider tation is both highly general and resists easy Richard Wollheim’s argument (1987: ch.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Art : an Introduction Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    THE PHILOSOPHY OF ART : AN INTRODUCTION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Theodore Gracyk | 284 pages | 20 Dec 2011 | Polity Press | 9780745649160 | English | Oxford, United Kingdom The Philosophy of Art : An Introduction PDF Book It makes centralized list management across all your devices simple. Many great works of painting and sculpture , for example, were created to glorify a deity and not, insofar as can be ascertained , for an aesthetic purpose to be enjoyed simply in the contemplation of them for their own sake. In the seventies and the eighties two excellent readers saw the light: George Dickie and Richard J. Do we have free will? This will help you develop your critical reasoning and argumentative skills more generally. This process still continues today. Google Scholar. If you acquire expensive pieces, insure them against theft and disasters. Download pdf. Give Feedback External Websites. It takes time to curate the perfect collection for your interests, tastes and passions. What Happened to Aesthetics? For the purposes of further, more advanced introductory reading, I have confined suggestions to two books that have appeared since the first edition was published the Routledge Companion to Aesthetics and the Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, both of which are accessible, comprehensive and authoritative. Martin's Press, Originally published Not surprisingly, every new movement is accompanied by a theoretical discourse to justify its premises. Inhalt Introduction. Over that long period a number of important answers have been developed and explored, and the purpose of this book is to introduce newcomers to the field of aesthetics and art theory to both the problems and their resolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychical Distance As a Factor in Art and An
    VOLUMEV JUNE, 1912 PART2 ‘PSYCHICAL DISTANCE ’ AS A FACTOR IN ART AND AN AESTHETIC PRINCIPLE, BY EDWARD BULLOUCH. I. 1. Meaning of the term ‘ Distance.’ 2. Distance as a factor in Art. 3. Diutunce as an aesthetic principle. 11. 1. Distance describes a personal relation. 2. The antinomy of Distance. 3. The variability of Distance. 4. Distance as the psychological formulation of the anti- realism of Art : naturalistic ard idealistic Art. 5. Distance UB applied to the antithesis ‘ sensual’ and ‘ spiritual.’ 6. Distance as applied to the antithesis individualistic’ and ‘ t9pical.’ 111. Distance as an aesthetic principle : 1. as a criterion between the agreeable adthe beautiful. 2. as a phase of artistic production : falsity of the theory of ‘self-expression of the artist.’ [3. Distance and some recent aesthetic theorbs.] 4. Distance as a fbndamentd principle of the ‘aesthetic cmciousness.’ I. 1. THE conception of ‘ Distance ’ suggests, in connexion with Art, certain trains of thought hy no means devoid of interest or of specu- lative importance. Perhaps the most obvious suggestion is that of actual spatial distance, i.e. the distance of a work of Art from the spectator, or that of represented spatial distance, i.e. the distance repre- sented within the work. Less obvious, more metaphorical, is the J. of Psych. v 7 88 Psychical Distance meaning of temporal distance. The first was noticed already by Aristotle in his Poetics; the second has played a great part in the history of painting in the form of perspective; the distinction between these two kinds of distance assumes special importance theoretically in the differentiation between sculpture in the round, and relief-sculpture.
    [Show full text]
  • Download (7Mb)
    A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of Warwick Permanent WRAP URL: http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/136077 Copyright and reuse: This thesis is made available online and is protected by original copyright. Please scroll down to view the document itself. Please refer to the repository record for this item for information to help you to cite it. Our policy information is available from the repository home page. For more information, please contact the WRAP Team at: [email protected] warwick.ac.uk/lib-publications The Myth o f Psychical Distance in Aesthetic Experience Jacqueline H.M. Bazin Submitted for the Degree of Ph.D. University of Warwick Department of Philosophy October 1997 TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements 1 Summary 2 PART ONE The Concept of ‘Distance’ in Aesthetic Experience Chapter I Introduction to the Concept of ‘Aesthetic Experience’ 3 Chapter II An Account of Psychical Distance in Aesthetic Experience 9 Introduction 9 Edward BULLOUGH’s theory of ‘Psychical Distance’ 10 Conclusion 35 PART TWO An Investigation into Modes of Aesthetic Experience Chapter III The Aesthetic Experience of Natural Beauty 40 Chapter IV A Comparative Analysis of Craftsmanship and Art 58 Chapter V Genius in Creative Art 71 PART THREE Art and Symbolic Expression Chapter VI 80 1. The Concept of ‘Expression’ in Art 80 2. LANGER’s Theory of Symbolic Art 94 Introduction 94 Symbolic Agency in Art 101 Implementation of Symbolic Agency in Art 108 Representational Symbolism in Literature 117 A View of ‘Psychical Distance’ in Aesthetic Experience
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Fall 2018 AH302 the Idea of the Aesthetic Course Description
    Fall 2018 AH302 The Idea of the Aesthetic provisional syllabus (likely to be updated during the semester; registered students should consult the latest syllabus on google classrooms ) Seminar leader: Katalin Makkai Course times: Tuesday and Thursday 17:30-19:00 Email: [email protected] Office hours: Tuesday 15:00-17:00, and by appointment Office: P98 004 Course description “Aesthetics” and “aesthetic” are terms that are often taken for granted inside as well as outside academic discourse. We speak of aesthetic experiences and judgments and qualities, and we employ “aesthetics” to designate the study of such matters. Although their root is taken from the Greek, the now-familiar terms (in their now-familiar usages) are, however, comparatively new. They are commonly regarded as having been introduced into the philosophical lexicon in the eighteenth century—a few hundred years ago. This course studies some of the texts that were key to the discovery, or perhaps the invention, of the “aesthetic”. What work was the idea meant to do? How did its evolution retain or reconfigure its original senses and purposes? Is the idea of the aesthetic problematic, ideological, or chimerical? Do we need an idea of the aesthetic to think about art? Course texts All readings will be provided during the semester in printed form and/or electronically. Any reading that is provided only electronically must be printed out and brought to class as a printout. Electronic devices Students may not use any electronic devices (laptop, tablet, mobile phone) in the classroom. Requirements ACADEMIC INTEGRITY Bard College Berlin expects good academic practice from students in their studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter- VI Aesthetic Attitude, Experience and Judgement
    Chapter- VI Aesthetic Attitude, Experience and Judgement 'Psychical Distnnce' A major question is whether aesthetic experience is to be thought of as depending on certain qualities or features of objects, or on a special attitude towards or way of perceiving things or on some sort of conjunction of the two. Bell's theory of significant form is an example of the view that it is certain qualities of an object that furnish logically necessary conditions of aesthetic experience. Schopenhauer's theory is an example of the view that a certain attitude of will - less ness is its logically necessary condition. These two theories of aesthetic experience, in common with others such as Aristotle's and Kant's, seem to require both a detachment and an involvement: a detachment from practical or utilitarian aspects of the object and, as a result, a contemplative involvement with its essential being. Reflection on those two features of detachment and Involvement suggests that a distinction may be drawn betyveen an aesthetic attitude and an aesthetic experience, the aesthetic attitude being a certain kind of stance or approach required as a necessary condition of aesthetic experience. Form this we may be tempted to think of the experience as a whole as a temporal, psychological process in which one is first rid of one's individual will and then, in consequence and if all goes well, enjoys an aesthetic experience of some sort. But this can lead to misunderstanding and error. For to think of Schopenhauer's account only as a description of a psychological process is to obscure the philosophical point for which he argues, namely, that denial of the individual will is the logically necessary condition for the impersonal knowledge of Idea, that, for him, characterizes aesthetic experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Opte As an Aesthetic Experience Introduction
    Barrett G. Lyon The Opte Project 2005 Opte as an Aesthetic Experience This paper outlines why the images available at http://www.opte.org/ are works of art, and it reviews the philosophical foundations of the images, touching tangentially on the technology behind the images. This paper could be expanded on, but the skeletal ideals and arguments are conveyed here. Introduction When I began the Opte Project in the fall of 2003, I was an undergrad student working as a consultant for a small network security company. While having lunch with my colleagues, we discussed the Internet Mapping Project of William Cheswick1 and Hal Burch2. Their mapping project collects data from the Internet and visualizes it into maps that look somewhat like a pile of feathers. The maps they created became known as a “peacock map”. Although I was impressed by these images (I have their poster hanging in my house), I was not convinced that their project was serving the greatest good. Cheswick and Burch produce images, but the images alone do not seem to be very useful, nor do they release the code for their project to allow the images to be functional for the rest of the world. I am a very big proponent of free software, and having something that people could use to image their networks seemed to be a useful endeavor. During lunch, I commented that, "I can write a program that can map the entire net in a single day." That comment was challenged by my colleagues, and I met the challenge with a fifty-dollar bet.
    [Show full text]