Neoliberalism's Uneven Revolution: Reflections on Wendy Brown's Undoing the Demos

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Neoliberalism's Uneven Revolution: Reflections on Wendy Brown's Undoing the Demos Neoliberalism's Uneven Revolution: Reflections on Wendy Brown's Undoing the Demos Patchen Markell Theory & Event, Volume 20, Number 2, April 2017, pp. 520-527 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/655784 Access provided by Hunter College Libraries (30 Jul 2018 16:38 GMT) Neoliberalism’s Uneven Revolution: Reflections on Wendy Brown’s Undoing the Demos Patchen Markell endy Brown’s Undoing the Demos1 tells a big, ambitious, and unfamiliar story about what neoliberalism is, and about Wwhat its ascent means for us. Unlike a lot of lesser books and articles on the subject, its sweep does not come at the cost of being vague, hasty, or gestural. It is, to the contrary, theoretically precise, deliberately paced, and carefully rooted in rich and detailed accounts of our present and our recent past. And, most of all, it is a book that is more than the sum of its individual arguments: to read it is to be drawn into a space and a perspective that will change how you look at the world. In that, I think it is a masterpiece of political theory. The questions and comments posed here about Undoing the Dem- os are meant to be internal to its space—that is, they are meant to be questions and comments of the kind that, on my reading anyway, the book means to provoke or invite. Before posing these questions, then, I need to say something about how I understand Brown’s rhetorical stance in Undoing the Demos, which, if I’m right, may also help avoid a possible misunderstanding of the book. One of the striking features of Undoing the Demos is its deliberate refusal of the rhetorical form of the programmatic political manifesto: as Brown says, the book is “an effort to comprehend the constitutive elements and dynamics of our condition,” which “does not elaborate alternatives to the order it illu- minates and only occasionally identifies possible strategies for resist- ing the developments it charts” (28). Another striking feature of the book, and particularly of its first and last chapters, is its use of lan- guage that could be characterized as “totalizing”—though, I hasten to add, that word implies a criticism that I actually mean to deflect rather than to press. Neoliberal rationality, Brown says, configures human be- ings “always, only, and everywhere as homo oeconomicus” (31); neolib- eralism is the “rationality through which capitalism finally swallows humanity” (44); neoliberalism replaces democracy’s unruliness by “a form of governing that is soft and total” (208); neoliberalism “conse- crates” and “deepens” a general “exhaustion and despair in Western civilization” (222). Theory & Event Vol. 20, No. 2, 520–527 © 2017 Johns Hopkins University Press Markell | Reflections on Wendy Brown’s Undoing the Demos 521 Someone might respond to these features by charging that they amount to defeatism—that the book forecloses the very possibility of elaborating an alternative precisely because it trades so heavily on the ominousness of its sweeping picture of the present as thoroughly and uniformly colonized by neoliberal rationality.2 But this would be a seri- ous misreading. Not least because such a charge would attend only to a handful of sentences from the framing chapters of the book, while ig- noring the detailed central chapters, which show again and again that Brown knows perfectly well that neoliberalism’s effects are neither seamless nor uniform across a social space riven by, for example, divi- sions between the advanced capitalist economies of the Euro-Atlantic world and those of the Global South (20), or by gendered divisions of labor (106). Nor would it be right simply to conclude that the book con- tradicts itself, offering sweeping pictures of neoliberalism that are un- dermined by its own acknowledgment that neoliberalism is (as Brown puts it at one point) “inconstant, differentiated, unsystematic, impure” (20). Instead, I take these two characterizations of neoliberalism to be meant to work together in a specific way. The apparently “totalizing” language captures a real tendency in neoliberal rationality’s reconfig- uration of the world; it captures the sense of inescapability that is one of its symptoms (and also one of its instruments); and in provoking the protest that this picture is or must be too simple, the book activates and mobilizes a desire for an alternative that—since Brown refuses the genre of the programmatic manifesto—can only be pursued by attend- ing more carefully to, and following the example of, the detailed inves- tigations Brown offers of neoliberalism in its “inconstancy and plastici- ty” (21). In short, this is not a contradiction: it’s a way of summoning the desire for, and providing some of the rudiments of, an education in our present—an education of the kind Brown so eloquently defends in chapter 6, one that aims less at providing “career bang for the buck” than at cultivating a “people” that is “modestly knowing” about the “enormously complex global constellations and powers” that affect it, that has “capacities of discernment and judgment in relation to what it reads, watches or hears about a range of developments in the world,” and that is “oriented toward common concerns and governing itself” (198–200). If, rather than tell her readers what to do, Brown invites her read- ers to share the burden of identifying alternatives to or routes out of the neoliberal present, and if she invites us to do so (as indeed she herself does) partly by complicating some of Undoing the Demos’s most sweep- ing characterizations of that present, then my questions and comments here can be understood as taking up that invitation. I begin with the question of the historical novelty of neoliberalism, understood as a “new form of governmental reason” (9) that has become hegemonic 522 Theory & Event in the Euro-Atlantic world over roughly the last three decades. One of the things about neoliberalism that is decisively new, Brown argues, is that it goes beyond simply reconceiving the proper relationship or re- locating the appropriate boundary between politics and the economy, as earlier forms of liberalism did, but reconceives the nature of both of these in a way that collapses any remaining difference between them. In its classical and liberal versions, the picture of the human being as homo oeconomicus presupposed the parallel existence of homo politicus: Aristotle’s free man ruled over a household whose unfree labor freed him for citizenship; Smith’s agent of commerce was not reducible to his trucking and bartering and remained subject to the sovereignty of a state that was still distinct enough from the economy to intervene in it. But neoliberalism’s version of homo oeconomicus, as an individual subject responsible for maintaining and maximizing its “portfolio val- ue in all domains of its life” (35), is a figure of the human being that no longer presupposes or respects fundamental divisions among those domains. Thus, neoliberalism does not just subordinate politics to economics but refigures it, like every other sphere, in the image of an economics that has itself been newly refigured along neoliberal lines. That erasure of every language, every domain, and every figure of the person that might in some way prove irreducible to and therefore po- tentially “disharmonious with capitalism” (111) is the real tendency the book’s totalizing formulations are rightly meant to capture. But exactly how novel, how distinctive to the neoliberalism of the last three decades, is this tendency? Reading Brown’s analysis of Obama’s 2013 State of the Union, for example, I was convinced by the claim that Obama’s invocations of jobs, skills, competition, invest- ment, stimulus, and so on, were not just moves in a political competi- tion with the GOP, but evidence of “the way that economic growth has become both the end and legitimation of government” and the way that “the state’s table of purposes and priorities has become indistin- guishable from that of modern firms” (26–27). Yet I also heard power- ful resonances between that speech and the recasting of growth, pros- perity, and consumption as both the substance and the instruments of “freedom” in the American political imaginary of the early Cold War.3 Similarly, as a Berkeley alumnus from late in the era of $600-a-semester tuition and generous-enough Pell Grants, I’ve watched the eviscera- tion of liberal arts education in public universities that Brown traces so powerfully here with acute distress. Yet I also wanted to hear more about the material basis of the public university in its twentieth-cen- tury heyday, and also about the conception of education that helped sustain massive state and federal funding for campus construction, research, and teaching, which was not only a conception of education as “a medium for egalitarianism and social mobility” (184), but also a conception of education as a way of providing appropriately creden- Markell | Reflections on Wendy Brown’s Undoing the Demos 523 tialed white-collar labor and research for the technocratic amalgama- tion of government agencies and private corporations that made up the wartime and postwar defense-industrial complex.4 (By the same token, a few generations earlier, leaders of West Coast land grant schools like Berkeley had justified the public provision of liberal arts education, as opposed to utilitarian agricultural research, by tying it to the project of opening Far Eastern markets and ruling what they proudly referred to as its racially inferior populations.5) To recall this is not at all to deny the democratic and democratizing accomplishments of public higher education in the liberal arts, but it may be to emphasize, more strongly than Brown does, that these accomplishments have always stood in a fraught, even antagonistic relationship to their institutional and mate- rial matrices.
Recommended publications
  • 1 Judgment and Imagination in Habermas's Theory of Law Thomas Fossen Institute for Philosophy Leiden University the Final Ve
    Judgment and Imagination in Habermas’s Theory of Law Thomas Fossen Institute for Philosophy Leiden University The final version of this paper was published in Philosophy & Social Criticism: psc.sagepub.com/cgi/doi/10.1177/0191453714566485 Abstract: Recent debates in political theory display a renewed interest in the problem of judgment. This article critically examines the different senses of judgment that are at play in Jürgen Habermas’s theory of law. The paper offers (a) a new critical reading of Habermas’s account of the legitimacy of law, and (b) a revisionary interpretation of the reconstructive approach to political theory that underpins it. Both of these are instrumental to (c) an understanding of what is involved in judging the legitimacy of law that is richer than has been recognized thus far by both critics and defenders of Habermas. Keywords: Habermas, law, legitimacy, judgment, imagination, reconstruction, communicative action, deliberative democracy, agonistic politics Acknowledgments: I am grateful to Joel Anderson, Bert van den Brink, and Patchen Markell for critical discussions and inspiration, and I’ve also benefited from feedback from Wout Cornelissen, J.J. McFadden, Daniel Gaus, David Owen, Martine Prange, Herman Siemens, an anonymous referee, and an audience at the Dutch Research School for Practical Philosophy, especially discussant Stefan Rummens. Thanks also to Ciarán Ó Faoláin for his careful copy-editing. Work on this paper was funded by a grant from the Dutch Organization for Scientific Research (NWO), entitled “Between Agonism and Deliberation: Rethinking Conflict and its Relation to Law in Political Philosophy.” 1 1. Introduction What is involved in judging the legitimacy of law? Much of the philosophical debate about legitimacy focuses on the content and justification of principles of legitimacy in light of which law (or political authority more broadly) ought to be considered legitimate or illegitimate.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moment Has Passed Power After Arendt
    4 THE MOMENT HAS PASSED Power after Arendt Patchen Markell “America’s Tahrir Moment”: that’s the title of an Adbusters blog entry from early September 2011. Nobody Can Predict the Moment of Revolution: the title of a short documentary video about Occupy Wall Street produced by some of its participants. “Transforming Occupy Wall Street from a Moment to a Movement”: the headline of a widely circulated article urging the occupiers to organize themselves behind a series of specific progressive demands.1 It’s not hard to understand the appeal of the language of the “moment” as a way of capturing the political rhythms of the past two years, whether in Sidi Bouzid, Oakland, Cairo, London, or lower Manhattan. Against the background of a feeling of political stuckness, of being in a rut you can’t see how to break out of, or of being subject to something—whether it’s an authoritarian dynasty or an economic system—that you feel powerless to contest, political aspiration can take the form of the desire for a moment of radical transformation, of the sudden appearance of new possibilities. Against the same background, promising moments can prove disappoint- ing precisely in their momentariness as old patterns and entrenched powers reassert themselves. Yet the notion of politics as a matter of the sudden and dramatic interruption of ordinary life, whose transformative effects must somehow be made durable without sacrificing what is radical and new in them, comes with significant costs. It has helped to anchor problematic conceptions of the authority of the political theorist: problematic because they fit poorly with the antihierarchical political principles in whose name they are often articulated and problematic because they help to reproduce 113 114 Patchen Markell subtly disempowering pictures of the very things—political power and political agency—that theory often promises to secure.
    [Show full text]
  • Tu 3–5 Pm Or by Appointment HANNAH
    Patchen Markell 2-8057, [email protected] Pick Hall 412 Office hours: Tu 3–5 pm or by appointment HANNAH ARENDT’S THE HUMAN CONDITION Political Science 24500 / 34500 / Fundamentals 22212 Spring Quarter 2014 Mondays, 1:30–4:20 pm Wieboldt 408 This seminar will be devoted to a reading of Hannah Arendt’s The Human Condition (1958), one of the most influential works of political theory written in the twentieth century. Topics include: the meaning and function of Arendt’s distinctions among “public,” “private” and “social” and among “labor,” “work,” and “action”; the significance and prospects of human activity, including especially political activity, in modernity; the relation between philosophy and politics in and beyond Athens; the significance of the scientific revolution for modernity; the meanings of work, leisure, and consumption in postwar capitalism; the nature and basis of political power and freedom; the relations between art and politics; and many others. In addition to The Human Condition, we’ll read some supplementary material, which includes work by some of the thinkers with whom Arendt was more or less explicitly in conversation; work by other writers from her era that will help us to situate Arendt in the larger contexts of twentieth-century intellectual life; and more recent writing that will give us different angles on some of the issues in Arendt’s book. This is a limited-enrollment, by-consent seminar, open to advanced undergraduates and to graduate students; in the event of a scarcity of places, some priority may be given to undergraduates. TEXTS: The primary text for the course is Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago, 1958, 2nd ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucerne Master Class 2016 with Prof
    Graduate School of Humanities and Social Sciences Lucerne Master Class 2016 With Prof. Dr. Axel Honneth Jack C. Weinstein Professor for the Humanities, Columbia University (New York) Professor of Social Philosophy, Goethe University (Frankfurt) Towards a Critical Theory of Markets 2–6 May 2016, University of Lucerne Course Location: Hotel Seeburg, Lucerne Contents: Welcome! 4 Organisation 5 Preparation 6 Axel Honneth & Towards a Critical Theory of Markets 7 Programme Overview 8 Detailed Programme 9 Monday 9 Tuesday 10 Wednesday 11 Thursday 12 Friday 12 Participants & Projects 13 Bader, Daniel 14 Dijkstra, Lizabeth 16 Heiland, Heiner 18 Knobbe, Sonja 20 Léger, Alexandre 22 Niazi, Nahyan 24 Overwijk, Jan 26 Peter, Lukas 28 Møller Stahl, Rune 30 Schmieden, Susanne 32 Teixeira, Pedro 34 Tunderman, Simon 36 Vogel, Tobias 38 Waitkus, Nora 40 Wienhues, Anna 42 3 Welcome! Dear Participants We are pleased to welcome you in Lucerne, Switzerland for the third Lucerne Master Class en- titled Towards a Critical Theory of Markets from 2–6 May 2016! Running annually from 2015–2019 under the general theme The Culture of Markets, the Graduate School of Humanities and Social Sciences (GSL) at the University of Lucerne will be offering one- week Master Classes, which will offer the opportunity to analyse the variety of virulent problems in the market through a range of scientific perspectives. We wish you all an inspiring and pleasant time at the University of Lucerne and we are looking forward to spending this week with you. Yours sincerely Prof. Dr. Martin Hartmann Professor of Philosophy, Chair for Practical Philosophy at the University of Lucerne.
    [Show full text]
  • Government 4000/6816 Cornell University Fall
    Government 4000/6816 Professor Patchen Markell Cornell University Office hours: Tuesdays, 2–4pm Fall 2021 or by appointment, White Hall 311 [email protected] SEMINAR: ARENDT Mondays, 11:20am–1:50pm, location TBA COURSE DESCRIPTION: This is a seminar on the political thought of Hannah Arendt, meant for advanced undergraduates and graduate students in Government and related fields in the humanities and humanistic social sciences. Prior familiarity with Arendt’s work is not necessary, but some prior work in political theory is required (e.g., Government 1615, for undergraduates). One source of Arendt’s enduring interest as a political theorist lies in the fact that she seemed to understand the meaning of “politics” very differently from many of her contemporaries and predecessors. But if politics is not essentially about the distinction between friends and enemies; or the possession of the legitimate means of violence in a territory; or who gets what, when, and how; or who does what to whom; or the rule of reason in the city and the soul—then what was politics, from Arendt’s perspective? Why did it matter? Was there such a thing as doing politics well or badly? What were the prospects for politics as a distinctive human practice in the post-World War II world? In this seminar we will pursue these and other questions via a slow, chapter-by-chapter reading and discussion of Arendt’s 1958 book The Human Condition, along with a number of other, shorter works of Arendt’s from from the 1940s through the 1970s. These readings will be supplemented by selections from the works of philosophers with whom Arendt was tacitly or explicitly engaged; selections from the writings of some of Arendt’s contemporaries, which will help us situate her work in the political and intellectual landscapes of the postwar world; and a few more recent readings that will give us different angles on some of the subjects Arendt addressed.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Candace A. Vogler Department of Philosophy the University of Chicago 1115 East 58Th Street Chicago, IL 60637
    Curriculum Vitae Candace A. Vogler Department of Philosophy The University of Chicago 1115 East 58th Street Chicago, IL 60637 Academic Appointments David B. and Clara E. Stern Professor of Philosophy, University of Chicago Chair of Virtue Theory, Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues & Fellow, Royal Institute of Philosophy, May 2018-May 2021 Fulbright Distinguished Visiting Professor, University of Notre Dame Australia, August- September 2017 Chair, Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 2011-2014 Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 2007-2010 Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 2000-2007 Co-Director, Masters of Arts Program in the Humanities, University of Chicago, 2000-2007 Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1994-2000 Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1992-1994 Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Los Angeles, 1992 Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Davis, 1991 Instructor, Department of Philosophy, Chatham College, 1989 Teaching Fellow, Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 1988-1990 Education University of Pittsburgh (1985-1992), Ph.D., Philosophy, 1994 Ph.D. certificate, Program for the Study of Culture, 1992 Mills College (1978-1981; 1984-1985), B.A. in Philosophy, Honors, 1985 Fellowships and Awards Fulbright Specialist World Learning Roster (2017-present) Distinguished Visiting Faculty, Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues, University
    [Show full text]
  • Recognition and Responsibility
    religions Article Recognition and Responsibility Hille Haker Department of Theology, Loyola University Chicago, Chicago, IL 60660, USA; [email protected] Abstract: While the concept of responsibility is a cornerstone of Christian ethics, recognition theory still lacks a thorough theological–ethical analysis. This essay seeks to fill the gap and develop normative ethics of recognition and responsibility. The first part provides a systematic analysis of the conceptual elements of recognition, emphasizing the need to focus on misrecognition as a heuristic tool and ethical priority. While recognition coincides with responsivity and attentiveness in the encounter of self and other, responsibility adds to this the moral accountability for acts, practices, structures, and institutions, rendering recognition and responsibility interrelated but also distinct principles of morality. This normative analysis is then correlated to the hermeneutical, narrative ethics of Christian ethics. The founding narrative of biblical ethics, the Cain and Abel narrative in Gen 4, is interpreted as a dialectic of recognition and responsibility. Both exegesis and ethics profit from this interdisciplinary and correlative approach between philosophical and biblical ethics. Finally, the ethics of recognition and responsibility, which emerges from the Frankfurt School critical theory, is confronted with exemplary indigenous approaches focusing on mutual responsibility as the foundation of ecological ethics. Christian ethics of recognition and responsibility resonates with
    [Show full text]
  • UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC San Diego UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title The sources and limits of political enthusiasm Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/7x24v971 Author Poe, Andrew Publication Date 2010 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO The Sources and Limits of Political Enthusiasm A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science by Andrew Poe Committee in charge: Professor Tracy Strong, Chair Professor Fonna Forman-Barzilai Professor Harvey Goldman Professor Patchen Markell Professor Philip Roeder 2010 Copyright Andrew Poe, 2010 All rights reserved The dissertation of Andrew Poe is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: ______________________________________________ ______________________________________________ ______________________________________________ ______________________________________________ ______________________________________________ Chair University of California, San Diego 2010 iii DEDICATION For Alivia, especially for beginning everything by mistakenly saying “I know you!” iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page....................................................................................................................iii Dedication...........................................................................................................................iv
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Political Freedom Between
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO POLITICAL FREEDOM BETWEEN ARENDT AND FOUCAULT A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY JOHN U. NEF COMMITTEE ON SOCIAL THOUGHT BY DAWN HERRERA HELPHAND CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE 2018 TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgments iii Abstract v Chapter One: Liberal Conceptions of Political Freedom: Property, Sovereignty, State 1 Chapter Two: Freedom Between Arendt and Foucault: Problematics and Possibilities 48 Chapter Three: Freedom as Practice 118 Chapter Four: The Free Subject in Play 153 Chapter Five: State, Race, Violence 202 Chapter Six: Freedom as Event 248 ii I owe an immense debt of gratitude to the teachers, mentors and friends who have guided me in the completion of this project. I would like to thank my Chair, Nathan Tarcov, for his trust in my capacity, his steadying hand when I myself doubted it, and for the care he has taken with my work; Patchen Markell, whose subtle insight and breadth of knowledge, have been matched only by his profound generosity; and Bernard Harcourt, who from the beginning has directed me straight to the heart of the matter and encouraged me to embrace my vision as my own. Thank you all for challenging and supporting me. I am truly fortunate to have had the opportunity to work with you: your friendship and advice are an inestimable gift. Thank you to the Committee on Social Thought, for providing my colleagues and I with that rarest, most precious scholarly resource: space to think. For helping me find my footing there I am deeply indebted to the late Paul Friedrich, a great soul and a dear friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Goldman CV January 2019
    Loren Goldman Department of Political Science University of Pennsylvania The Ronald O. Perelman Center for Political Science and Economics 133 S. 36th St. Philadelphia, PA 19104-6215 Academic Employment Since 2016. University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA. Assistant Professor of Political Science (tenure track). 2013-2016. Ohio University, Athens, OH. Visiting Assistant Professor of Political Science. 2011-2013. University of California, Berkeley. Mellon Postdoctoral Fellow in the Humanities, Department of Rhetoric. 2010-2011. Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ. Postdoctoral Fellow, Center for Cultural Analysis. Education 2003-2010. University of Chicago. Ph. D. (2010), M.A. (2005), Political Science. Dissertation: “The Sources of Political Hope: Will, World and Democracy.” Committee: Patchen Markell (Chair), Robert Gooding-Williams, John P. McCormick, Robert Pippin. Comprehensive Exams: Political Theory, Comparative Politics (distinction). 2001-2003. University of Oxford. M.Phil., Politics. Thesis: "Organic Analogies and The New Liberalism." Supervisor: Michael Freeden Exams: Contemporary Political Theory, Political Philosophy from Machiavelli to Burke, Political Theories of Hegel and Marx, Political Institutions. 2000-2001. Johann Wolfgang Goethe Universität-Frankfurt, Germany. DAAD Jahresstipendiat, Philosophie, 2000-2001. With Prof. Axel Honneth. 1996-2000. Yale University. B.A., Political Science. Cum laude, with honors in the major. Senior Thesis: “Tending to the Extremes: Aesthetic Epistemology, Mass Culture and the Dialectics of Emancipation in the Work of Theodor W. Adorno.” Research and Teaching Interests Political Theory, History of Political Thought, American Pragmatism, Critical Theory, Democratic Theory, German Idealism, Utopian Thought. Loren Goldman, Curriculum Vitae 2 Publications [Refereed Articles in Journals] -- “Richard Rorty’s ‘Post-Kantian’ Philosophy of History.” Journal of The Philosophy of History 9:3, 2015, 410-443.
    [Show full text]
  • Arendtian Contributions to Liberal Political Theory
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2006 Arendtian contributions to liberal political theory Sarah M. McGrath The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation McGrath, Sarah M., "Arendtian contributions to liberal political theory" (2006). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5251. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5251 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Maureen and Mike MANSFIELD) LIBRARY The University o f Permission is granted by the author to reproduce this material in its entirety, provided that this material is used for scholarly purposes and is properly cited in published works and reports. **Please check "Yes" or "No" and provide signature** Yes, I grant permission >< No, I do not grant permission ______ ~ S. Author's Signature;. — ^ ^ ) Date: ^ ~ ^ - Q£>____________ Any copying for commercial purposes or financial gain may be undertaken only with the author's explicit consent. 8/98 ARENDTIAN CONTRIBUTIONS TO LIBERAL POLITICAL THEORY by Sarah M. McGrath B.S. Grand Valley State University, 2002 B.A. Grand Valley State University, 2003 presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts University of Montana July 2006 Approved by: Chairperson Dean, Graduate School 2 S -o £ Date UMI Number: EP40715 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Theory
    ANDREW DILTS, PH.D. [email protected][email protected] – https://dilts.org/ tel: +1.310.338.5165 / fax: +1.310.338.2356 Loyola Marymount University Department of Political Science 1 LMU Drive, Los Angeles, CA, 90045, USA AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION AREAS OF COMPETENCY Political Theory (modern & contemporary), Critical Carceral American Political Development, Queer Theory, American Studies, Critical Race Theory, Race, Ethnicity, & Politics Political Thought, Feminist Theory, Democratic Theory, Critical Theory, Punishment Theory Ancient & Medieval Political Theory, Philosophy of Law, Public Law & Judicial Politics, Law & Society ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS Loyola Marymount University Associate Professor (tenured), 2017-present. Department of Political Science Bellarmine College of Liberal Arts Assistant Professor, 2011-2017. Los Angeles, CA London School of Economics Visiting Senior Fellow, Spring 2018. Department of Government London, UK Institute for Advanced Study Member, 2016-2017. School of Social Science Princeton, NJ The University of Chicago Collegiate Assistant Professor & Harper-Schmidt Fellow, 2008-2011. Social Sciences Collegiate Division & Society of Fellows in the Liberal Arts Chicago, IL EDUCATION The University of Chicago Doctor of Philosophy, 2008 Division of the Social Sciences, Dissertation: “Excess Punishment: State, Citizens, & Felon Disenfranchisement” Department of Political Science Committee: Patchen Markell (chair), Robert Gooding-Williams, & Bernard Harcourt. Qualifying exams passed in Political Theory and U.S. Politics. Master of Arts, 2004 Masters Thesis: “Being/Becoming Felon: Identity and Felon Disenfranchisement,” Readers: Cathy J. Cohen & Patchen Markell. Indiana University, Bloomington Bachelor of Arts with High Distinction, 2002 College of Arts and Sciences Wells Scholar Class of 1998; Major in Economics with Departmental Honors. London School of Economics Visiting Student, 2000-2001.
    [Show full text]