Philosophical Ethics and the Improvement of Farmed Animal Lives

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophical Ethics and the Improvement of Farmed Animal Lives Feature Article Philosophical ethics and the improvement of farmed animal lives Paul B. Thompson Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI 48823 2004). Clare Palmer’s book Animal Ethics in Context articu- Implications lates an almost fully developed relational ethic in which she explains the basis for differential obligations to wildlife and do- • Philosophers have neglected the relationships that es- mesticated animals. In general, humans do not have positive tablish duties to farmed animals, especially in factory duties to extend care toward wild animals, while bringing an farms. animal into our home establishes duties of care that include • Many philosophers apparently assume that the condi- attending toward the creature’s biological and emotional needs tions in industrial facilities are so horrible that the very (Palmer, 2010). idea of discussing obligations to them is vitiated by the With a number of important exceptions, philosophers have unredeemable nature of the circumstances in which neglected the relationships that establish duties to farmed ani- they live. mals. This neglect is especially evident with respect to philo- • Even when widely read texts accurately describe wel- sophical studies of livestock being raised in concentrated fare deficits, they present a picture which is misleading animal feeding operations (CAFOs), or, colloquially, factory both as to the extent of these problems, and to diffi- farms (Figure 1). culty of making changes in response to them. While, again, there are exceptions, many philosophers ap- • Frequently cited welfare problems in factory farms parently assume that the conditions in industrial facilities are support a case for reform, but it is difficult to see how so horrible that the very idea of discussing obligations to them it would support the claim that what is done to farmed is vitiated by the unredeemable nature of the circumstances in animals is equivalent to torture. which they live. Robert McDowell compares advocacy for ameli- oration of suffering in CAFOs to claiming that Nazi concentra- tion camps would have been “a lesser evil” if only the prisoners Key words: animal welfare, animal integrity, CAFOs, industrial had received a little better treatment prior to being exterminated animal production, quality of life (Cavell et al., 2008, p. 131). The animal in a factory farm is a cast- off, thoroughly instrumentalized, dominated, abject. The humans Introduction who have placed them there cannot fulfill anymoral obligation to them without relieving them of the torturous conditions in Philosophical reflection on human beings’ morally which these animals live. If this is the assumption, however, it is grounded relationships with nonhuman animals has come a almost never articulated explicitly. Instead, the unspeakable na- long way since the animal welfare/animal rights debates of the ture of the lives that factory farmed lives is mentioned in passing, 1970s and 1980s. The basis for granting moral consideration as the author moves on to make more philosophically worthwhile to nonhuman animals expanded far beyond Peter Singer’s dis- points (Thompson, forthcoming). cussion of sentience (Singer, 1975) or Tom Regan’s view that Are animal ethicists right to view industrially housed ani- human obligation’s toward individuals from other species are mals with such disdain that ethical reflection on their quality grounded in their being “subjects of a life” (Regan, 1983). of life is simply not worthy of philosophical attention? The ar- Building on the work of Mary Midgley, a number of authors gument that they are not correct proceeds in stages. First, as have developed relational theories that interpret human obliga- noted, there are philosophers who discuss how CAFOs might tions to animals in terms of the specific relationships that we be changed to improve animals’ quality of life. A brief survey bear to them (Donovan, 1990; MacKinnon, 2004; Anderson, of some key themes in this literature brings the possibility for an alternative perspective into view. Next, the alternative per- © Thompson spective can be contrasted with claims by well-known animal This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), ethicists. Finally, these better known and highly influential which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any views can be rebutted through a detailed examination of ways medium, provided the original work is properly cited. that the lives of industrially farmed animals can be improved, doi: 10.1093/af/vfz054 even if improvement falls short of a full moral justification. January 2020, Vol. 10, No. 1 Figure 1. Sows in gestation crates in an indoor swine production system. Philosophy of Improving the Lives of Farmed recognized obligations to individual animals as opposed to Animals maximizing welfare (hence, he has a rights view), but he argues that we derive these obligations from an understanding of an It cannot hurt but to begin with the observation that ad- animals’ telos, which we understand as the needs and behav- vances since the Singer and Regan era notwithstanding, many ioral drives that are typical of creatures from a given species if not most academically employed philosophers still seem to (Rollin, 1991). In later work, it became clear that Rollin views fall into one of two camps. Reflection on nonhumans takes one telos as determined by an animal’s genetic constitution. While camp all the way to vegetarianism, while those in the other camp it is wrong to treat animals in ways that fail to respect their have so little interest in animal ethics that they are barely cogni- telos, there is nothing wrong with changing an animal’s genetics, zant of the developments in the field. It is, perhaps, natural to whether through breeding or genetic engineering, unless doing conclude that if you are already committed to vegetarianism, so leads to persistent suffering (Rollin, 1995a, 1998). there cannot be much reason to think about the condition of Rollin also carried out a sustained attack on the industrial animals being raised for food production (Olynk, 2012). Even conditions under which farmed animals were being raised among the “don’t care” camp, the stridency with which CAFOs (Rollin, 1995b). He argued that the growth in CAFOs was are condemned leads many to seek animal products from pre- the result of a conceptual shift in agricultural and veterinary sumably more humane sources: cage-free eggs, free-range or research. Where researchers had once stressed husbandry, a pasture-raised meats, organic producers, or family farms. Here concept with implicit ethical commitments, they shifted to- as with the vegetarians, these mildly proanimal types reach a ward animal science, adopting a positivist, value-free attitude stopping point. They have no reason to go on and think about toward their research subjects, who were, of course, animals the quality of life for animals being raised under the increas- capable of feeling, emotion and better, or worse states of well- ingly prevalent industrial conditions. Yet no relations of logical being (Rollin, 2004). Rollin’s work became influential in the entailment support such inferences. No relational theorist has animal and veterinary sciences, where the lack of fit between presented an argument showing that just because you person- an animal’s telos and the housing or husbandry began to be ally have no interest in eating animals, you therefore are dis- used as a guiding approach to applied animal behavior science charged of any reason or obligation to consider how their lives (Fraser, 1999; Rollin et al., 2012). might be improved (Thompson, 2015). Quite a few European philosophers have joined Rollin in In fact, a significant subgroup of philosophers writing in helping to determine how the lives of farmed animals might animal ethics do consider the questions that arise in efforts to be improved. Peter Sandøe has argued that Singer’s em- improve the lives of farmed animals. Contemporaneous with phasis on sentient experience can be a guide for husbandry the work of Singer and Regan, Bernard Rollin developed his (Lassen, Sandøe and Forkman, 2006) and animal breeding adaptation of Aristotelean telos as a criterion for evaluating (Sandøe et al., 1999). Others have advocated for animal integ- the quality of animal lives in a variety of settings, including rity. Like Rollin’s notion of telos, animal integrity is intended industrial livestock production. Rollin argued for a view that to convey the sense that each individual animal has status or 22 Animal Frontiers nature that derives from being the member of a species. It uni- When mainstream philosophers do mention industrial fies the animal’s cognitive experience of pain or pleasure with animal production, the pattern is a sentence or two noting more complex relationships that situate the individual within horrific conditions with at most a mention of the general pro- an evolutionary history. Unlike telos, integrity is meant to in- duction system, such as caged layers or gestation stalls for clude relationships that derive from the history of domestica- pigs. Description of these systems that link their elements to tion by humans and the association with human caregivers, animal welfare deficits are rare. Mainstream philosophers have as well as adaptive fit between genetics and the environments certainly read Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation, which was re- in which farmed animals have been
Recommended publications
  • Lands of the Lakota: Policy, Culture and Land Use on the Pine Ridge
    1 Lands of the Lakota: Policy, Culture and Land Use on the Pine Ridge Reservation Joseph Stromberg Senior Honors Thesis Environmental Studies and Anthropology Washington University in St. Louis 2 Abstract Land is invested with tremendous historical and cultural significance for the Oglala Lakota Nation of the Pine Ridge Indian Reservation. Widespread alienation from direct land use among tribal members also makes land a key element in exploring the roots of present-day problems—over two thirds of the reservation’s agricultural income goes to non-Natives, while the majority of households live below the poverty line. In order to understand how current patterns in land use are linked with federal policy and tribal culture, this study draws on three sources: (1) archival research on tribal history, especially in terms of territory loss, political transformation, ethnic division, economic coercion, and land use; (2) an account of contemporary problems on the reservation, with an analysis of current land policy and use pattern; and (3) primary qualitative ethnographic research conducted on the reservation with tribal members. Findings indicate that federal land policies act to effectively block direct land use. Tribal members have responded to policy in ways relative to the expression of cultural values, and the intent of policy has been undermined by a failure to fully understand the cultural context of the reservation. The discussion interprets land use through the themes of policy obstacles, forced incorporation into the world-system, and resistance via cultural sovereignty over land use decisions. Acknowledgements I would like to sincerely thank the Buder Center for American Indian Studies of the George Warren Brown School of Social Work as well as the Environmental Studies Program, for support in conducting research.
    [Show full text]
  • Rolston on Animals, Ethics, and the Factory Farm
    [Expositions 6.1 (2012) 29–40] Expositions (online) ISSN: 1747–5376 Unnaturally Cruel: Rolston on Animals, Ethics, and the Factory Farm CHRISTIAN DIEHM University of Wisconsin, Stevens Point In 2010, over nine billion animals were killed in the United States for human consumption. This included nearly 1 million calves, 2.5 million sheep and lambs, 34 million cattle, 110 million hogs, 242 million turkeys, and well over 8.7 billion chickens (USDA 2011a; 2011b). Though hundreds of slaughterhouses actively contributed to these totals, more than half of the cattle just mentioned were killed at just fourteen plants. A slightly greater percentage of hogs was killed at only twelve (USDA 2011a). Chickens were processed in a total of three hundred and ten federally inspected facilities (USDA 2011b), which means that if every facility operated at the same capacity, each would have slaughtered over fifty-three birds per minute (nearly one per second) in every minute of every day, adding up to more than twenty-eight million apiece over the course of twelve months.1 Incredible as these figures may seem, 2010 was an average year for agricultural animals. Indeed, for nearly a decade now the total number of birds and mammals killed annually in the US has come in at or above the nine billion mark, and such enormous totals are possible only by virtue of the existence of an equally enormous network of industrialized agricultural suppliers. These high-volume farming operations – dubbed “factory farms” by the general public, or “Concentrated Animal Feeding Operations (CAFOs)” by state and federal agencies – are defined by the ways in which they restrict animals’ movements and behaviors, locate more and more bodies in less and less space, and increasingly mechanize many aspects of traditional husbandry.
    [Show full text]
  • Bob Fischer's CV
    BOB FISCHER [email protected] Department of Philosophy bobfischer.net Texas State University orcid.org/0000-0001-9605-393X 601 University Drive 512.245.2403 San Marcos, TX 78666 EMPLOYMENT Texas State University: Associate Professor of Philosophy 2019-present Texas State University: Assistant Professor of Philosophy 2013-2019 Texas State University: Senior Lecturer 2011-2013 EDUCATION University of Illinois at Chicago, Ph.D., Philosophy 2006-2011 Dissertation: Modal Knowledge, in Theory Director: W. D. Hart State University of New York at Geneseo, B.A., English & Philosophy 2001-2004 PUBLICATIONS BOOKS AUTHORED What Do We Owe Other Animals? Under contract with Routledge. (w/ Anja Jauernig) Wildlife Ethics: Animal Ethics in Wildlife Management and Conservation. Under contract with Blackwell. (w/ Christian Gamborg, Jordan Hampton, Clare Palmer, and Peter Sandøe) Animal Ethics — A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge, 2021. The Ethics of Eating Animals: Usually Bad, Sometimes Wrong, Often Permissible. New York: Routledge, 2020. Modal Justification via Theories. Synthese Library. Cham: Springer, 2017. BOOKS EDITED A 21st Century Ethical Toolbox, 5th Edition. Under contract with Oxford University Press. (w/ Anthony Weston) Ethics, Left and Right: The Moral Issues That Divide Us. New York: Oxford University Press, 2020. College Ethics: A Reader on Moral Issues That Affect You, 2nd Edition. New York: Oxford University Press, 2020. (1st Edition: 2017) The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics. New York: Routledge, 2020. Modal Epistemology After Rationalism. Synthese Library. Cham: Springer, 2017. (w/ Felipe Leon) The Moral Complexities of Eating Meat. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015. (w/ Ben Bramble) ARTICLES & BOOK CHAPTERS “Animal Agriculture, Wet Markets, and COVID-19: A Case Study in Indirect Activism.” Food Ethics, forthcoming.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Ethics
    Animal ethics Palmer, Clare; Sandøe, Peter Published in: Animal welfare Publication date: 2011 Document version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (APA): Palmer, C., & Sandøe, P. (2011). Animal ethics. In M. C. Appleby, J. A. Mench, I. A. S. Olsson, & B. O. Hughes (Eds.), Animal welfare (2. ed., pp. 1-12). CABI Publishing. Download date: 30. Sep. 2021 Danish Centre for Bioethics and Risk Assessment This is a post-print version of a chapter in Animal Welfare. 2nd edition by CABI For more articles on animal ethics, see www.animalethics.net 1 Chapter 1: Animal Ethics Clare Palmer (Texas A&M University, USA), Peter Sandøe (University of Copenhagen, Denmark) Abstract This chapter describes and discusses different views concerning our duties towards animals. First, we explain why it is necessary to engage in thinking about animal ethics and why it is not enough to rely on feelings alone. Secondly, we present and discuss five different kinds of views about the nature of our duties to animals. They are: contractarianism, utilitarianism, the animal rights view, contextual views, and a respect for nature view. Finally, we briefly consider whether it is possible to combine elements from the presented views, and how to make up one’s mind. 1. Introduction: The need to give reasons for one’s ethical views This chapter describes and discusses different views on right and wrong in our dealings with animals. What might be right or wrong is not a factual question, and therefore cannot be settled by the same methods as those used in biology and other natural sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Copenhagen, Denmark)
    Københavns Universitet Animal ethics Palmer, Clare; Sandøe, Peter Published in: Animal welfare Publication date: 2011 Document Version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (APA): Palmer, C., & Sandøe, P. (2011). Animal ethics. In M. C. Appleby, J. A. Mench, I. A. S. Olsson, & B. O. Hughes (Eds.), Animal welfare. (2. ed., pp. 1-12). Chapter 1.CABI Publishing. Download date: 11. Dec. 2015 Danish Centre for Bioethics and Risk Assessment This is a post-print version of a chapter in Animal Welfare. 2nd edition by CABI For more articles on animal ethics, see www.animalethics.net 1 Chapter 1: Animal Ethics Clare Palmer (Texas A&M University, USA), Peter Sandøe (University of Copenhagen, Denmark) Abstract This chapter describes and discusses different views concerning our duties towards animals. First, we explain why it is necessary to engage in thinking about animal ethics and why it is not enough to rely on feelings alone. Secondly, we present and discuss five different kinds of views about the nature of our duties to animals. They are: contractarianism, utilitarianism, the animal rights view, contextual views, and a respect for nature view. Finally, we briefly consider whether it is possible to combine elements from the presented views, and how to make up one’s mind. 1. Introduction: The need to give reasons for one’s ethical views This chapter describes and discusses different views on right and wrong in our dealings with animals. What might be right or wrong is not a factual question, and therefore cannot be settled by the same methods as those used in biology and other natural sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • CRITICAL TERMS for ANIMAL STUDIES
    CRITICAL TERMS for ANIMAL STUDIES Edited by LORI GRUEN THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS Chicago and London Contents Introduction • Lori Gruen 1 1 Abolition • Claire Jean Kim 15 2 Activism • Jeff Sebo and Peter Singer 33 3 Anthropocentrism • Fiona Probyn- Rapsey 47 4 Behavior • Alexandra Horowitz 64 5 Biopolitics • Dinesh Joseph Wadiwel 79 6 Captivity • Lori Marino 99 7 Difference • Kari Weil 112 8 Emotion • Barbara J. King 125 9 Empathy • Lori Gruen 141 10 Ethics • Alice Crary 154 11 Extinction • Thom van Dooren 169 12 Kinship • Agustín Fuentes and Natalie Porter 182 13 Law • Kristen Stilt 197 14 Life • Eduardo Kohn 210 15 Matter • James K. Stanescu 222 16 Mind • Kristin Andrews 234 17 Pain • Victoria A. Braithwaite 251 18 Personhood • Colin Dayan 267 19 Postcolonial • Maneesha Deckha 280 20 Rationality • Christine M. Korsgaard 294 21 Representation • Robert R. McKay 307 22 Rights • Will Kymlicka and Sue Donaldson 320 23 Sanctuary • Timothy Pachirat 337 24 Sentience • Gary Varner 356 25 Sociality • Cynthia Willett and Malini Suchak 370 26 Species • Harriet Ritvo 383 27 Vegan • Annie Potts and Philip Armstrong 395 28 Vulnerability • Anat Pick 410 29 Welfare • Clare Palmer and Peter Sandøe 424 Acknowledgments 439 List of Contributors 441 Index 451 INTRODUCTION Lori Gruen Animal Studies is almost always described as a new, emerging, and growing field. A short while ago some Animal Studies scholars suggested that it “has a way to go before it can clearly see itself as an academic field” (Gorman 2012). Other scholars suggest that the “discipline” is a couple of decades old (DeMello 2012).
    [Show full text]
  • CBD Online Forum - Edits to the Proposed List of "Volunteers"
    RE: CBD online forum - edits to the proposed list of "volunteers" Subject: RE: CBD online forum - edits to the proposed list of "volunteers" From: Heath Packard <heath.packard@islandconserva�on.org> Date: 4/18/2017 8:46 PM To: Isabelle Coche <[email protected]>, Delphine Thizy <[email protected]>, Karen Logan <[email protected]>, Aus�n Burt <[email protected]>, Jason Delborne <[email protected]>, Todd Kuiken <[email protected]>, Stephanie James <[email protected]>, Gregg Howald <gregg.howald@islandconserva�on.org>, Camilla Beech <[email protected]>, Hector Quemada <[email protected]>, sco� Shore <sco�@shorebiotech.com>, Royden Saah <royden.saah@islandconserva�on.org>, Sara Kaiser <sara.kaiser@islandconserva�on.org> CC: Hapsa Dia <[email protected]>, Benjamin Robinson <[email protected]>, Olivia Majorin <[email protected]> Hi Isabelle, Today Todd and I briefed the Gene�c Biocontrol steering commi�ee and urged them to get themselves (and other’s from their organiza�ons/networks) nominated for the online forum. You can add these steering commi�ee to your ‘volunteer’ target list and note that they’ve been asked to enlist. Todd’s given them a sample nomina�on le�er, to make that step easier. I’m sure they’d appreciate a more detailed briefing (we only had 15 min.). · Dr. Peter Brown, CSIRO · Dr. Karl Campbell, Island Conserva�on · Dr. John Godwin, NCSU · Dr. Fred Gould, NCSU · Gregg Howald, Island Conserva�on · Dr. Toni Piaggio, USDA · Dr. Paul Thomas, U. of Adelaide · Dr. Dan Tompkins, Landcare Research · Dr. David Threadgill, TA&M · Royden Saah, Island Conserva�on I’ve also a�ached an email that includes the current 172-member roster of the ‘gene�c rescue’ list serve that Revive and Restore (Ryan Phelan) maintains.
    [Show full text]
  • Differential Obligations Towards Others in Need Palmer, Clare
    Astrolabio. Revista internacional de filosofía Año 2013 Núm. 15. ISSN 1699-7549. pp. 242-246 Differential obligations towards others in need Palmer, Clare. Animal Ethics in Context, New York: Columbia University Press, 2010. CRITICAL NOTE ON CLARE PALMER'S ANIMAL ETHICS IN CONTEXT In human ethics, there is a common belief that our moral obligations towards other individuals are not restricted to abstaining from harming them. We should also prevent or relieve a harmful state of affairs for other human beings, whenever it is in our power to do something about it. However, in the animal ethics debate, the idea that we may have reasons not only to refrain from harming animals but also to help them has not been particularly welcome. Animal Ethics in Context constitutes, regardless, a remarkable exception to this tendency by examining the hypothesis of positive obligations to assist animals in need. The book opens by considering the case of 114 horses left starving to death by their owners, in Amersham, Buckinghamshire. If it was in our power to do something to alleviate their suffering, ought we to do it? Would it be wrong to let them to suffer and die if we could otherwise help them? The immediate response to this case is that it failing to assist them would be wrong. But, if this is the case, does it imply that we should assist every animal in a situation of need? What about the animals that live in the wild? Wild animals experience systematic suffering during their lives and have premature deaths. For example, every year there is a massive drowning of wildebeest during their migration from Tanzania to Kenya.
    [Show full text]
  • Animals & Ethics
    83 RECOMMENDED FURTHER READING: Overviews of Animals & Ethics 1. Susan Armstrong & Richard Botzler, eds. The Animal Ethics Reader, 2nd Ed. (Routledge, 2003, 2008) is the only comprehensive anthology of ethics & animals writings currently available. It is less than ideal, however, because the pro-animal theoretical selections are perhaps not ideal (e.g., the selections from Singer and Regan are not the best available; the selections from other pro-animal ethical theoreticians are a bit idiosyncratic); there are few criticisms of pro-animal moral theorizing, little anti-animal ethical theorizing, and few defenses of particular animal uses; furthermore, the selection on animal experimentation is sparse. The strengths seem to be in the areas of wildlife and environmental issues, as those seem to be the editors’ specialties. 2. Tom Regan and Carl Cohen, The Animal Rights Debate (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001) and Tom Regan, Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy (Rowman & Littlefield, 2003) (which is mostly The Animal Rights Debate minus Cohen’s contribution) are great introductions: the latter argues for moral rights for animals (and humans) by examining competing moral theories. Regan’s The Case for Animal Rights (University of California, 1983/2004) was recently reissued as a 20th anniversary edition with an updated preface containing replies to critics. 3. Tom Regan and Peter Singer, eds., Animal Rights and Human Obligations, 2nd ed. (Prentice Hall, 1989). An excellent collection, despite its age, but is very expensive ($75 new, but much cheaper used). 4. Bernard Rollin, Animal Rights and Human Morality, 3rd Ed. (Prometheus, 2006, 1998, 1981). Rollin is a philosopher who has interacted with tens of thousands of people employed in animal agribusiness and experimentation and so has a unique and valuable perspective on the issues.
    [Show full text]
  • Pervasive Captivity and Urban Wildlife
    Ethics, Policy & Environment ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cepe21 Pervasive captivity and urban wildlife Nicolas Delon To cite this article: Nicolas Delon (2020): Pervasive captivity and urban wildlife, Ethics, Policy & Environment, DOI: 10.1080/21550085.2020.1848173 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2020.1848173 Accepted author version posted online: 06 Nov 2020. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cepe21 Publisher: Taylor & Francis & Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group Journal: Ethics, Policy & Environment DOI: 10.1080/21550085.2020.1848173 Pervasive captivity and urban wildlife Nicolas Delon [email protected] New College of Florida Division of Humanities Assistant Professor of Philosophy & Environmental Studies 5800 Bay Shore Rd Sarasota, FL 34243 Abstract. Urban animals can benefit from living in cities, but this also makes them vulnerable as they increasingly depend on the advantages of urban life. This article has two aims. First, I provide a detailed analysis of the concept of captivity and explain why it matters to nonhuman animals—because and insofar as many of them have a (non-substitutable) interest in freedom. Second, I defend a surprising implication of the account—pushing the boundaries of the concept while the boundaries of cities and human activities expand. I argue for the existence of the neglected problem of pervasive captivity, of which urban wildlife is an illustration. Many urban animals are confined, controlled and dependent, therefore often captive of expanding urban areas.
    [Show full text]
  • Wild Justice: the Moral Lives of Animals Free
    FREE WILD JUSTICE: THE MORAL LIVES OF ANIMALS PDF Marc Bekoff,Jessica Pierce | 208 pages | 07 Jun 2010 | The University of Chicago Press | 9780226041636 | English | Chicago, IL, United States Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals - Marc Bekoff, Jessica Pierce - Google книги Sign in Create an account. Syntax Advanced Search. University of Chicago Press Animal Ethics in Applied Ethics. Edit this record. Mark as duplicate. Find it on Scholar. Request removal from index. Revision history. Download options PhilArchive copy. This entry has no external links. Add one. Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server Configure custom proxy use this if your affiliation does not provide a proxy. Configure custom resolver. Chimpanzee Normativity: Evidence and Objections. Simon Fitzpatrick - - Biology and Philosophy 35 4 Animal Morality: What is the Debate About? Simon Fitzpatrick Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals - Biology and Philosophy 32 6 On a Failed Defense of Factory Farming. Simon Fitzpatrick - - EurSafe Newsletter 22 1 Recent Texts in Animal Ethics. Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals Kemmerer - - Ethics, Policy and Environment 16 1 On Wild Animals, Hubris, Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals Redemption. Susan Nance - - Society and Animals 20 4 Clare A. Palmer - - Between the Species 16 1 The Moral Lives of Animals. Michael Bradie - unknown. Aaron Simmons - - Ethics and the Environment 14 1 :pp. The Medical Treatment of Wild Animals. Robert W. Loftin - - Environmental Ethics 7 3 Animal Ethics in Context. Clare Palmer - - Columbia University Press. Matthew Pianalto - - Philosophical Investigations 34 3 Joel MacClellan - - Between the Species 16 1 Chan - - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 18 6 The Reintroduction and Reinterpretation of the Wild.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the View That We Are Normally Required to Assist Wild Animals
    Against the View That We Are Normally Required to Assist Wild Animals Clare Palmer Professor of Philosophy, Texas A&M University doi: 10.7358/rela-2015-002-palm [email protected] In this brief paper, I will defend the position that while sentient animals are morally considerable, we are not normally morally required to assist suffer- ing wild animals, though this does not mean that it is ethically impermissi- ble to do so. I will argue that this position can be defended without denying that we have obligations to assist distant suffering humans, and that it need not rely on the claim that there is something wrong with intervening in human-independent processes (“the wild”). For the purposes of this paper I will just assume that sentient animals are morally considerable. This view is widely accepted and not particularly controversial (see Palmer 2010 for a more substantial defense of this view). What is owed to wild animals in terms of assistance has been relatively little discussed. Understandably, the first priority of those defending sen- tient animals’ moral importance has, historically, been the systematic harms undergone by agricultural and laboratory animals. But most such positions in animal ethics are extensions of approaches to human ethics on which we should, at least to some degree, assist people who are suffering, even distant people whom we have never met. For example: most forms of ethi- cal consequentialism aim at reducing distant suffering as (normally) likely to bring about the best consequences (Singer 1972). And even though on most deontological ethical positions our strongest duties are not to harm, weak positive duties of benevolence are still generally accepted (O’Neill 1986; Pogge 2007).
    [Show full text]