Can the Mind Change the World?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Can the Mind Change the World? I Can the mind change the world? NED BLOCK Hilary Putnam origi nated the idea that mental states are computational states. At first (Putnam, 1960), his view was that although mental states are not identical wit h computational states (or " logical states." as he then called them), there are useful analogies between them. Later (Putnam, 1967). he argued in favor of the identity on the grounds that it was more plausible to suppose mental states are function al states (as he then called them) than that they are behavioral or physical states. This doctrine - funct ionalism - has dominated the philosophy of mind for over twenty years. Shortly after proposing functionalism. Putnam re­ jected it again (J 973), and he has maintained this position ever since (Putnam. 1988). Putnam was my teacher during both my undergraduate and gradu·ate days, and I fear I have absorbed his ambivalence toward functionalism. My teacher has had a habit of changing his mind, but never has he done so within a single essay, and so in this chapter I have surpassed him. My chapter starts out as an argument for functionalism, but it ends up suggesting an argument against it. The issue is whether we ca n avoid epiphenomenalism, which I here understand as the doctrine that what we think or want has no causal relevance to what we do. I propose functionalism as a way of warding off arguments for epiphcnomenalism, but then I argue that functionalism may bring epiphenomenalism in its wake. The orientation of the chapter is toward the sciences of the mind, and their relation to intentional content, that is, what is shared hy the I am graleful for support IO the America n Counci l or Learned Sociclies and lo the Nalional Science Foundation. granl numhcr DTR88 12559. I am also grateful to Jerry Fodor, Paul Horwich, Frank Jackson, Gabriel Segal. and Marianne Talbot for !heir commenls on an earlier draft; to Thomas Nagel, who was the commentaror on the paper on which lhis chapler is based at a conference al Columbia University in December 1988; to Simon Blacktiurn, who was !he commentalor on the paper at Oxford in February 1989; to Martin Davies. Dorothy Edgington. and Oarry Smith for discussion or 1he issues while I was at Birkbeck College. University of London; and to the audiences al a number of philosophy colloquia. .. · · :; 138 NFD ULOCK hclief that grass grows and the desire that grass grows, the that grass model. T grow.~ that buth sraces are directed toward. The question at hand is qucstioni whether the scie nces of the mind prc..:cludc int entional content from useful pt. causal relevance to behavior. One argument that the intentional con­ J think ti tents of our beliefs, thoughts, and the like have no effects on our premise behavior could he put this way: The processors in the head are not The r. sensitive to content, so how could content have any effect on the Turing r outputs or changes of state of the system of processors? And if content such as , can't affect the operation of this system of processors, how could it play sensitive any role in producing behavior? This argument seems formidable Uu1 if 1h whether one thinks of the processors as neural devices reacting lO a gate. h neural inputs or, instead, from the cognitive science point of view, as gates? S computational devices processing representations. ' Jn this chapter, I se ntat io1 confin e myself to the prohlcm as it arises in the cognitive science influcnc• I approach that is dominated by the computer model of the mind. I soning a assume a very specific picture of cognitive science and its relation to the computl commonsense conception of intentional content, namely, the view ac­ mind (c cording to which there is an internal system of representation from assumrn I whose meanings our intentional contents derive (Fodor, 1975; Pylys hyn, My r '. 1984 ). One of my reasons for couching the discussion in terms of this view is that although those who adopt this view are motil'ated by the I. t· aim of showing how our commonsense beliefs about cont ent (including I I. l our belief in content's causal efficacy) are vi ndicated by the computer II model of the mind, the problem of thl' epiphenomenalism of content 111. s arises within this view in an extremely simple and straightforward (and (.' poignant) way. The viewpoint assumed throughout the chapter is that of r a supporter of the computer model in cognit ive science who also would IV . I like to believe that the contents of our thoughts arc indeed ca usally g relevant to what we do. A suht I The problem I have in mind might be put in terms of The Paradox of relcvarn the Causal Efficacy of Content, namely, th<Jt the fo llowing claims all of a lav. seem to be true, yet incompatible: a count I. The intentional content of a thought (or other intentional state) is causally relevant to its behavioral (and other) effects. 11. Intentional conteAt reduces to meanings of internal representa­ tions. The fir: II J. Internal processors arc sensitive to the "syntactic forms" of propL·r1 ·internal representations. not thl'ir meanings. SOllll' a and ge The first claim is meant to he part nf the communscnse view of the name : mind. The third is plausibly taken to be a basic claim of the computer Bureau model of the mind, and the second i~ a useful and plausible way of United thinking how Commonsense rsycholO!-,')' meshes with lhe comruter contc11 1 f i Ct111 rh1· 111i11d change the ll'orld? IJl) c: thar grass ml>Je l. This s<.:eon c.J daim is by for the most conc roversial, hul I won't be at hand is questioning it here. My reasons are that I think it is true. that I see no intent from usdul purpose to dividing meaning and content in this cn11text. and that Jtion al con­ I think the best bets fo r resolving the paradox are to que:-. ti on the third :cts on our premise amt whether the reasoning that leads to the paradox is right. !ad arc not T he reasoning behind the paradox goes so mething li ke this: Any feet on the;: Turing machine can be constructed fro m simple primit ive p rnces~l) r s cl if content such ;.is 1111<1 ga tes. or gates, and the like. (See Minsky, llJC17 .) CJates are :ould it play sen!'> itive to the sy ntactic fo rms of representations, not tl1eir meanings. fo rmiJable But if the meaning 1>f a rcprc:!se nt ation cannot in liuence tl1c behavior of reacting to a ga te. how coulJ iL influence th t.: hehuvior of a computer - a system of of view. as gates? Since intentional content reduces lO meanings of internal rep re­ ; chapter, I sentations, and si nce meanings of internal repre!>t! nt ati ons ca nnot live scie nce inllut.:nce behavior, content cannot influence hehavior t.:it her. The rea­ the minJ. I soning assumes that at least as far as our thinking is con('erneJ, we are lation to the computers. This idea - which is simply the computer model of the he view ac- mind (o ur cognit ive mind, that is) - may he wrong, but I will be ·tation from assum ing it m explore wh ere it leads. '5; Pylyshyn, My plan fo r the chapter involves erms of this •ared by the I. Expl<J ining each premise tt (including II. Examining and rejecting a putative solution based nn a nomolog­ le computer ical conception of causal re le vance 1 of content 111. Suggesti ng a solution based on a functionalist conception of orwan.l (and cont i.; nt and rn caning and a countcrfactual thl my 1>f causal tcr is that of relevance ) also would IV. Discussing a probkm with the proposed solution. one lhat sug- eed causally gests that functionalism actually hreec.Js epiphenomenalism A suhtheme of rh e chapter is that a nomological theory of causal e Paradox of relevance (a theory that explai ns causal relevance in terms of th e not ion g claims all of a law of nature) has more of a problem with epiphenomenal ism than a counterfacwal approach. 1tional state) cts. l . The premises I represent a- The firs! prcmi"c uses Lhe notion of a causally relevanr f"Opl.'rty. Some c forms" of propl'rties of a cause arl' releva nt to the production of an c lfect, and Sllmt: are not. I lurrica111.: EliLa hrokc my window. Elii:1's wi nd speed and geographical path are ca usa lly relevant to the hr ~ aking, bur its view of the name amJ the location of its records in the United ~.ta l es Wea1her he computer Bureau un.: not. 1\ ccord i11 g to th ~ fi rst premise, if my hel ie f that the .siblc way of Unit cu States is a tfangcrous place causes me to leave the country. the le comrn1ter content of the hclid is causally relevant to the behavior; ;i property that 140 NED £31.0CK is not causally relevant to the behavior is the last letter of the name of the city in which the belief was formed. Note that the point is not that beliefs, thoughts, desires, and the like (mental states or events that have content) are causes, for example, of behavior. (I assume that they arc.) Rather, the point is that when mental events have effects, they typically have those effects (rather than different effects) because the mental events have the contents that they have, rather than some other contents.
Recommended publications
  • Is Human Information Processing Conscious?
    CommentaryfVelmans: Consciousness The resistance against a natural-science approach to conscious consciousness is required for it. He considers semantic analysis experience reminds one also of the great debate a century ago of novel word combinations, on-line analysis of speech, learn- between Darwinians and creationists. Darwin's opponents ing, memory, identification, planning and control of complex clearly believed they were attacking not a mere scientific hy- novel action, and others, arguing in each case that these things pothesis, but a conception of human nature that would tear away can be done without consciousnessp. (This survey is the bulk of the last remaining shreds of human dignity. The contemporary his paper.) He concludes that there is no type of information resistance by Velmans and others to a straightforward natural- processing for which consciousnessp is required, and therefore science approach to conscious experience may be driven by a that consciousness plays no causal role in and does not "enter similar anxiety. But Darwin did not deprive us of human into" information processing, and is in that sense dignity; treating conscious experience as a normal topic of epiphenomenal.1 psychology and neuroscience will not do so either. The fallacy of this argument is equally simple. Even if Indeed, one can make the opposite argument: that denial of Velmans is right that consciousnessp is not required for any first-person conscious experience in other people may lead to a particular sort of information processing, it does not follow that profound kind of dehumanization. It comes down to saying that consciousness does not causally enter into information process- other people are not capable of joy or suffering, that as far as the ing.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, XII-2 | 2020 Santayana’S Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy XII-2 | 2020 Democracy as a Form of Life Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered Robin Weiss Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/2138 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.2138 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Robin Weiss, « Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], XII-2 | 2020, Online since 14 December 2020, connection on 15 December 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/2138 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ ejpap.2138 This text was automatically generated on 15 December 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered 1 Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered Robin Weiss 1 Recently, it has become increasingly common to question the extent to which Santayana’s philosophy of mind can and should be identified as a kind of epiphenomenalism, as has traditionally been the case. Most scholars take Santayana’s epiphenomenalism for granted, and either assert or deny that he gives an argument to support it.1 However, others have questioned whether the evident similarities between Santayana’s own views and those of modern-day epiphenomenalists obscure more significant differences. I will argue that, indeed, Santayana’s views are potentially inaccurately captured by the term “epiphenomenalism.” However, I shall argue that this is true for reasons other than other scholars have given for this view. 2 The issue turns on what Santayana means by a “cause” when he denies that ideas are causes of action.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Swinburne's Arguments for Substance Dualism
    Richard Swinburne’s arguments for substance dualism. MA by Research in Theology and Religion David Horner September 2018 Richard Swinburne’s arguments for substance dualism. Submitted by David Horner to the University of Exeter as a dissertation for the degree of MA by Research in Theology and Religion in September 2018 This dissertation is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the dissertation may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this dissertation which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. 1 Acknowledgements. I would like to thank my supervisors, Dr Jonathan Hill and Dr Joel Krueger for their support and encouragement in the writing of this dissertation and for their patience in trying to keep me on the straight and narrow. I want to acknowledge the many conversations, on this and other topics, I have had with my friend and philosopher, Dr Chris Boyne, who sadly died in June of this year. I thank all my other chums at The Bull, Ditchling, for listening to my metaphysical ramblings. And finally, I thank my wife, Linda, for once more putting up with this kind of thing. 2 Abstract This dissertation is a contribution to debates in the philosophy of mind and of personal identity. It presents a critical account of arguments for substance dualism to be found in Richard Swinburne’s Mind, Brain, and Free Will (2013).
    [Show full text]
  • William James's Objection to Epiphenomenalism
    William James’s Objection to Epiphenomenalism Alexander Klein*y James developed an evolutionary objection to epiphenomenalism that is still discussed today. Epiphenomenalists have offered responses that do not grasp its full depth. I thus offer a new reading and assessment of James’s objection. Our life-essential, phenomenal pleasures and pains have three features that suggest that they were shaped by selection, according to James: they are natively patterned, those patterns are systematically linked with antecedent brain states, and the patterns are “universal” among humans. If epiphe- nomenalism were true, phenomenal patterns could not have been selected (because epi- phenomenalism precludes phenomenal consciousness affecting reproductive success). So epiphenomenalism is likely false. 1. Introduction. William James developed an evolutionary objection to epi- phenomenalism that is still regularly discussed today.1 Perhaps because the classic passage where he lays out the objection is so pithy, epiphenomenalists have offered responses that do not, I will argue, grasp its full depth. I begin with a brief history of James’s own encounters with epiphenomenalism. Then I make use of more recent theoretical tools from evolutionary biology to un- pack his worry. *To contact the author, please write to: University Hall 310A, McMaster University, 1280 Main Street West, Hamilton, ON L8S 4K1, Canada; e-mail: [email protected]. yI would like to thank Trevor Pearce and Elisabeth Lloyd for helpful feedback, as well as the US-UK Fulbright Commission, which financially supported this work. 1. More recent advocates of epiphenomenalism have included Jackson (1982) and Rob- inson (2004). An oft-cited successor to James’s argument against epiphenomenalism from evolutionary considerations can be found in Popper and Eccles (1977).
    [Show full text]
  • Santayana's Anticipations of Deleuze: Total Natural Events and Quasi- Pragmatism
    Abstract *O B NPOPHSBQI QVCMJTIFE MBTU ZFBS MJU- FSBSZ UIFPSJTU .BSL /PCMF OPUFT UIBU JO UIF XBZ %FMFV[F VOEFSTUBOET UIF SFMB- UJPOTIJQ CFUXFFO NBUFSJBMJTN BOE TVC- KFDUJWJUZ %FMFV[F iBMTP TPVOET DVSJPVTMZ Santayana’s MJLF4BOUBZBOBw'PSFYBNQMF UIFXPSLPG CPUI QIJMPTPQIFST iMPDBUFT IVNBO WBMVF JOBTPVSDFBUPODFJNNBOFOUBOEBMJFOw Anticipations /PCMFBMTPXPOEFSTiXIFUIFSUIFMFTTPOPG 4BOUBZBOBTPXOOFHPUJBUJPOXJUIIJTUFO- of Deleuze: EFODZUPIVNBOJ[FUIFOPOIVNBOHSPVOE PG FYQFSJFODF BMTP BOUJDJQBUFT UIF UISJMM Total Natural %FMFV[FDIBTFTXIFOQPTJUJOHUIFVOJWPD- JUZPGCFJOHw*OUIFQSFTFOUBSUJDMF *XJMM Events and BUUFNQUUPFMBCPSBUFPOUIJTiBOUJDJQBUJPO w UIFJNQMJDBUJPOTPGXIJDIJODMVEFBHSFBUFS Quasi- BQQSFDJBUJPO PG 4BOUBZBOB PO UIF QBSU PG %FMFV[F FOUIVTJBTUT BO VOEFSTUBOEJOH Pragmatism PG CPUI QIJMPTPQIFST BT 64JOìVFODFE Joshua M. Hall &VSPQFBORVBTJQSBHNBUJTUT BOEBEFDJTJPO JOGBWPSPG.JDIBFM#SPESJDLTSFDFOUJOUFS- QSFUBUJPO PG 4BOUBZBOB BT B iUPUBM OBUVSBM FWFOUwQIJMPTPQIFSPGNJOE Keywords: George Santayana, Gilles Deleuze, Essence, Event, Phantasm, Ghost, Epiphenomenalism, Philosophy of Mind, Pragmatism *O UIF QSFTFOU BSUJDMF * IPQF UP BSUJDV- MBUFUISFFJNQPSUBOUJNQMJDBUJPOTPG.BSL /PCMFTSFDFOUPCTFSWBUJPOUIBU%FMFV[FBU UJNFT iTPVOET DVSJPVTMZ MJLF 4BOUBZBOBw1 'JSTU 4BOUBZBOBQSFEBUFTNBOZPG%FMFV[FT NPTU GBNPVT JOTJHIUT ɨVT JO SFHBSE UP UIFJOìVFODFPO%FMFV[FPG64"NFSJDBO UIJOLFST CPUI%FMFV[FBOEIJTJOUFSQSFUFST IBWFCFFOSFNJTTJOGPDVTJOHBMNPTUFYDMV- TJWFMZ PO UIF 1SBHNBUJTUT BOE FTQFDJBMMZ PO$41FJSDF 4FDPOE POFDBOIFMQGVMMZ TRANSACTIONS OF THE CHARLES S. PEIRCE SOCIETY 270
    [Show full text]
  • Park, Sam-Yel (1999) a Study of the Mind-Body Theory in Spinoza. Phd Thesis. Copyright and Moral R
    Park, Sam-Yel (1999) A study of the mind-body theory in Spinoza. PhD thesis. http://theses.gla.ac.uk/2040/ Copyright and moral rights for this thesis are retained by the author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the Author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the Author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Glasgow Theses Service http://theses.gla.ac.uk/ [email protected] A Study of the Mind-Body Theory in Spinoza Departmentof Philosophy University of Glasgow A Study of Theory in Spinoza the pffindýBody by Sam-Yel Park A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of Arts in Fulfilment of the Requirementsfor the degreeof Doctor of Philosophy June 1999 C Sam-Yel Park 1999 Abstract A Study of the Mind-Body Theory in Spinoza by Sam-Yel Park This thesis investigates Spinoza's mind-body theory starting with the discussion of the diverse interpretations of his mind-body theory such as hylomorphism.,idealism, epiphenomenalism,and materialism. From the critical comments on inadequaciesof these interpretations, it turns out that Spinoza's argumentof the relationshipbetween the mind and the body should be understood as holding that there is a non-causalrelationship between the mind and the body and that they have equal weight.
    [Show full text]
  • A Type-F Monist Account of Phenomenal Consciousness
    INTRINSIC NATURALISM: A TYPE-F MONIST ACCOUNT OF PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS By LUKE ALEXANDER GORDON PALMER A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham for the degree of Master of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Law The University of Birmingham September 2010 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. ABSTRACT The aim of this thesis is to provide a theory of phenomenal consciousness which accords with both the science-friendly spirit of physicalism and the acknowledgement of panpsychism that phenomenal properties may be inextricably linked to entities, but with none of the problems associated with either type of model. Initially, physicalism and panpsychism are evaluated by the lights of their most serious problems, and solutions are offered to these problems from the point of view of a third kind of model: intrinsic naturalism, presented in the final chapter. This model holds consciousness to be among the battery of a functional system’s intrinsic (i.e. non-dispositional) properties. A definition is given, and defence made for the existence of these properties, and their compatibility with an otherwise physicalist ontology.
    [Show full text]
  • Where's the Action? Epiphenomenalism and the Problem of Free Will Shaun Gallagher Department of Philosophy University of Central
    Gallagher, S. 2006. Where's the action? Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will. In W. Banks, S. Pockett, and S. Gallagher. Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? An Investigation of the Nature of Volition (109-124). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Where's the action? Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will Shaun Gallagher Department of Philosophy University of Central Florida [email protected] Some philosophers argue that Descartes was wrong when he characterized animals as purely physical automata – robots devoid of consciousness. It seems to them obvious that animals (tigers, lions, and bears, as well as chimps, dogs, and dolphins, and so forth) are conscious. There are other philosophers who argue that it is not beyond the realm of possibilities that robots and other artificial agents may someday be conscious – and it is certainly practical to take the intentional stance toward them (the robots as well as the philosophers) even now. I'm not sure that there are philosophers who would deny consciousness to animals but affirm the possibility of consciousness in robots. In any case, and in whatever way these various philosophers define consciousness, the majority of them do attribute consciousness to humans. Amongst this group, however, there are philosophers and scientists who want to reaffirm the idea, explicated by Shadworth Holloway Hodgson in 1870, that in regard to action the presence of consciousness does not matter since it plays no causal role. Hodgson's brain generated the following thought: neural events form an autonomous causal chain that is independent of any accompanying conscious mental states. Consciousness is epiphenomenal, incapable of having any effect on the nervous system.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Epiphenomenalism
    Epiphenomenalism – the Do’s and the Don’ts Larry Shapiro and Elliott Sober University of Wisconsin, Madison Abstract: When philosophers defend epiphenomenalist doctrines, they often do so by way of a priori arguments. Here we suggest an empirical approach that is modeled on August Weismann’s experimental arguments against the inheritance of acquired characters. This conception of how epiphenomenalism ought to be developed helps clarify some mistakes in two recent epiphenomenalist positions – Jaegwon Kim’s (1993) arguments against mental causation, and the arguments developed by Walsh (2000), Walsh, Lewens, and Ariew (2002), and Matthen and Ariew (2002) that natural selection and drift are not causes of evolution. A manipulationist account of causation (Woodward 2003) leads naturally to an account of how macro- and micro-causation are related and to an understanding of how epiphenomenalism at different levels of organization should be understood. 1. The Weismann Model August Weismann (1889) is widely credited with disproving the Lamarckian theory of the inheritance of acquired characteristics. In one of his famous experiments, Weismann cut off the tails of newborn mice; when the mice grew up and reproduced, their offspring had tails as long as their parents’ had prior to surgery. These results remained constant over many generations. Weismann saw the same pattern, and the same evidence against the inheritance of acquired characteristics, in the fact that circumcision over many centuries had not caused boys to be born without foreskins. He also thought that his theory of the continuity of the germ plasm threw further doubt on the inheritance of acquired characteristics, though it is worth asking whether this theory was evidence against Lamarckianism (as Gould 2002 argues) or merely assumed that Lamarckian inheritance does not occur.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist by John R. Searle I Have Argued in a Number of Writings1 That the Philosophical Part (Though
    1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a fairly simple and obvious solution: All of our mental phenomena are caused by lower level neuronal processes in the brain and are themselves realized in the brain as higher level, or system, features. The form of causation is “bottom up,” whereby the behavior of lower level elements, presumably neurons and synapses, causes the higher level or system features of consciousness and intentionality. (This form of causation, by the way, is common in nature; for example, the higher level feature of solidity is causally explained by the behavior of the lower level elements, the molecules.) Because this view emphasizes the biological character of the mental, and because it treats mental phenomena as ordinary parts of nature, I have labeled it “biological naturalism.” To many people biological naturalism looks a lot like property dualism. Because I believe property dualism is mistaken, I would like to try to clarify the differences between the two accounts and try to expose the weaknesses in property dualism. This short paper then has the two subjects expressed by the double meanings in its title: why my views are not the same as property dualism, and why I find property dualism unacceptable. There are, of course, several different “mind-body” problems. The one that most concerns me in this article is the relationship between consciousness and brain processes. I think that the conclusions of the discussion will extend to other features of the mind-body problem, such as, for example, the relationship between intentionality and brain processes, but for the sake of simplicity I will concentrate on consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenomenalism?
    Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenomenalism? Richard Swinburne [Swinburne, Richard, 2011, “Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenom- enalism?”, Journal of Consciousness Studies, vol 18, no 3-4, 2011, pp.196-216.] Abstract: Epiphenomenalism claims that all conscious events are caused immediately by brain events, and no conscious events cause brain events. In order to have a justified belief in a theory someone needs a justified belief that it or some higher-level theory predicts cer- tain events and those events occurred. To have either of the latter be- liefs we depend ultimately on the evidence of apparent experience, memory, and testimony, which is credible in the absence of defeaters; it is an undermining defeater to a belief produced by apparent memory that it was not caused by a past belief, and to a belief pro- duced by apparent testimony that it was not caused by an intention to say what the speaker believes. A justified belief in epiphenomenalism requires either evidence about when conscious events occurred or evidence about what some theory that brain events are caused solely by physical events predicts, but epiphenomenalism rules out the avail- ability of the evidence of apparent memory and testimony on these matters. Hence only a rare individual scientist who could hold in her mind at one time the proof that a theory makes certain predictions could have a justified belief that epiphenomenalism is true. It follows that recent neurophysiological work in the tradition of Libet has no tendency whatever to provide a justified belief in epiphenomenalism. I Introduction I understand by ‘epiphenomenalism’ the theory that [X] all conscious events have physical events (viz.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil Mind Seminar Syllabus W 21
    Phil 296D: Phil Mind Seminar W 21 Prof Aaron Zimmerman Office Hours: By Appointment Office: https://ucsb.zoom.us/j/5972101028 The Evolution of Consciousness and the Development of Pragmatism I. General Description: The nature of consciousness (subjectivity, qualitative experience, what- it-is-likeness, etc) and the nature of agency (or control, will, volition, choice, decisions etc.) are the two most central issues in contemporary philosophy of mind. Though Pragmatism has come to be associated with anti-realist views of truth and reference, and coherence theories of meaning and justification, it in fact originated in the philosophy of mind and an approach to that subject grounded in developmental and evolutionary biology. Broadly speaking, pragmatists began to adopt a developmental approach to the will or our ability to control our behaviors and used this conception to define core components of consciousness and cognition: i.e. belief, doubt and those states of mind operative in the articulation and evaluation of philosophy itself. Indeed, James introduced the term “pragmatism” to name a philosophy that results from applying an account of belief grounded in evolutionary biology to debates over the nature of philosophy and its methods. It is perhaps no surprise, then, that pragmatism is experiencing a resurgence in the philosophy of mind as cognitive scientists have tried to integrate their work with what is known about the evolution of our nervous systems and have simultaneously come to recognize how much computation is devoted to action and how extensively action shapes perceptual experience. Our plan is to begin with this history and the intuitions that lead some philosophers to regard an organism’s consciousness as something that cannot be fully explained if we limit ourselves to the tools utilized by neurobiologists and other cognitive scientists: some philosophers, concluding from this that consciousness and/or agency are non-physical (dualism) and others concluding that consciousness is a fundamental force (panpsychism).
    [Show full text]