Aristotle: Happiness, Virtue and Contemplation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aristotle: Happiness, Virtue and Contemplation CHAPTER THREE ARISTOTLE: HAPPINESS, VIRTUE AND CONTEMPLATION ‘What is human life’s chief concern?’ One of the answers we should receive would be ‘It is happiness.’1 We come now to Aristotle whose approach to happiness is among the principal topics of his Nicomachean Ethics (c. 348–345 B.C.E.). This book, which is among the most influential works in all of Western philosophy, does not exhaust the whole of Aristotle’s treatment of moral theory. The Eudemian Ethics is an earlier study whose authorship was for many years in doubt. Today, however, there is no serious dispute that Aristotle wrote it as well.2 But for Aristotle’s definitive analysis of the good life and of the way to live it, the Nicomachean Ethics includes what one needs to know. In what follows, therefore, we turn our attention to key texts and argu- ments from the Nicomachean Ethics.3 Our concern, as it was with the chapters on Socrates and Plato, is to extract Aristotle’s conception of happiness, to see whether it presents any interpretive problems and to determine whether any inconsistencies are embedded in the text. Along the way, we will address an issue that emerges even from a relatively casual reading of this crowded work, “crowded” insofar as Aristotle takes up many topics and examples throughout its ten books. Is the Ethics what we traditionally think of as a book in ethics? Does it approach the mat- ter of what an agent ought to do in order to discharge a tissue of disin- terested obligations to others, or does it come across as a sophisticated “How-to?” book that tells a person what ideas and actions are necessary to secure and sustain his happiness? Perhaps the “or” of exclusion is inap- propriate. Does the Ethics deal with a tertium quid? Is its focus an effort to 1 William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, intro. Reinhold Niebuhr (New York: Collier Books, 1961), page 78. 2 See Martin Ostwald’s introduction to his translation of the Nicomachean Ethics (India- napolis: The Library of Liberal Arts, 1962), pages xvii–xviii. 3 Nicomachean Ethics, trans. W.D. Ross, rev. J.O. Urmson, in The Complete Works of Aris- totle, ed. Jonathan Barnes (2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), Volume II. All citations, included in parentheses in the text, are to the standard pagination. Refer- ences to this pagination occur throughout the text and in notes below. Nicomachean Ethics is sometimes referred to as Ethics and is abbreviated NE. 86 chapter three establish that disinterested virtue and the self-interested desire for happi- ness qualify as appropriate concerns for a formal study of theoretical and practical ethics? (1) We can begin this inquiry into Aristotle’s treatment of happiness as he begins the Ethics, with the claim that “Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and choice, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim” (NE.1094a,1–3; emphasis added). Since this declaration is too general as it stands, Aristotle adds that countless ends exist and that some of them are subordinate to other ends. He is, as a consequence, entitled to claim that “If, then, there is some end of the things we do, which we desire for its own sake (everything being desired for the sake of this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else for at that rate the process would go on to infinity, so that our desire would be empty and vain, clearly this must be the good and the chief good” (NE.1094a,17–20). Ethical theorists study the ends at which our conduct aims, but political scientists must study them as well. Political science addresses questions about the connections between individual and public good. So the con- nection between ethics and political science, with ethics being a branch of politics, makes it essential that political scientists know and elaborate what is good for human beings, individually and collectively (NE.10941,19– 1094b,11). In these opening pages, Aristotle also warns his readers that the study of what is good for human beings and for political societies is not a sci- ence in the strict sense (NE.1094b13–16). Expecting such a science in the Ethics is an expectation that neither he nor anyone else can provide. For Aristotle and for Plato, as we saw in Chapter 2, “science” is a finite body of necessary truths from which other necessary truths (theorems) necessar- ily follow. Anyone who demands a science of ethics or politics is ignorant; “for it is the mark of an educated man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits” (NE.1094b,25–6).4 4 For a related statement, see John Locke’s An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Book IV, chapter xi, paragraph 10. Locke was deeply disappointed that he could not provide a demonstrative science of morals. Aristotle acknowledges that the material which moral- ists and political scientists study is too recalcitrant to be incorporated into a scientific body .
Recommended publications
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Francis Bacon on Action
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Francis Bacon on Action, Contemplation, and the Human Good A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Aaron Maddeford Washington, D.C. 2018 Francis Bacon on Action, Contemplation, and the Human Good Aaron Maddeford, Ph.D. Director: John McCarthy, Ph.D. Francis Bacon is rarely, if ever, considered a moral philosopher. Commentators generally have focused on his contributions to natural philosophy. Nevertheless, he does write on moral philosophy. Further, throughout his natural philosophy, he employs a distinction central to ancient ethics, that of action and contemplation. Bacon seeks an action and contemplation more united than those of the ancients. What drives men’s actions, in his view, is the desire for immortality, of the individual and of the species. Such an aim is achieved most perfectly by Bacon’s natural philosophy, which has for its end the mastery of nature for the relief of man’s estate. Bacon uses Christian charity as an argument for his philosophy, but his understanding of charity is particularly un-Christian in its focus on this world. His moral philosophy and natural philosophy both reject the starting point of the ancients, namely, what is most known to us. Natural philosophy begins from simple natures, the first tendencies of matter, rather than from natural wholes. Moral philosophy begins not from opinions about the good, but from a consideration of the passions of men. Both natural and moral philosophy aim at immortality, one through dominion over the natural world, the other through dominion over men.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Pyrrho of Elis and the Pyrrhonian Praxis of Aporetic
    The Influence of Pyrrho of Elis and the Pyrrhonian Praxis of Aporetic Language by © Christopher Craig Dupuis A Thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, Department of Philosophy Memorial University of Newfoundland May, 2014 St. John’s Newfoundland and Labrador 2 Table of Contents Abstract 4 Introduction and Overview 5 Chapter One 1 Pyrrho’s Aporetic Linguistic Praxis 12 1.1 Ataraxia in Epictetus and Epicurus 21 1.2 The Role of Epoche and Ataraxia in Pyrrho 23 1.3 Plato’s Socrates as Pyrrho’s Sage 43 1.4 Pyrrho and Plato’s Phaedo 45 1.5 Pyrrho, the Meno, and The Soul of The Hellenes 48 1.6 Appearances, Customs, and The Soul of the Sceptic 51 1.7 Pyrrho and Plato’s Theaetetus 55 1.8 Chapter One Conclusion 62 Chapter Two 2.1 Introduction: Academic Scepticism 64 2.2 Scepticism up to this Point 65 2.3 Arcesilaus And the Early Academic Sceptics 68 2.4 Carneades And the ‘New’ Academic Sceptics 81 2.5 Connecting with Pyrrho 91 Chapter Three 3.1 Introduction: Later Pyrrhonian Scepticism 95 3.2 Aenesidemus and the Revival of Pyrrhonism 97 3.3 Aenesidemus, Relativity, and Language Practice 107 3.4 Later Pyrrhonism: Sextus Empiricus 112 3.5 Outline of Sextus 118 3.6 Phantasiai 119 3.7 Apprehension 122 3.8 What the Sceptics Do 125 3.9 Ataraxia and Epoche 128 3.10 The Five Ways to Epoche 133 3 3.10.1 The First Trope: Diaphonia 136 3.10.2 The Second Trope: Infinite Regression 138 3.10.3 The Third Trope: Relativity 139 3.10.4 The Fourth
    [Show full text]
  • The Birth of Belief, (PDF)
    The Birth of Belief Jessica Moss (NYU) and Whitney Schwab (UMBC)* Forthcoming in the Journal of the History of Philosophy 1 Introduction Did Plato and Aristotle have anything to say about belief? The answer to this question might seem blindingly obvious: of course they did. Plato distinguishes belief from knowledge in the Meno, Republic, and Theaetetus, and Aristotle does so in the Posterior Analytics. Plato distinguishes belief from perception in the Theaetetus, and Aristotle does so in the de Anima. They talk about the distinction between true and false beliefs, and the ways in which belief can mislead and the ways in which it can steer us aright. Indeed, they make belief a central component of their epistemologies. The view underlying these claims—one so widespread these days as to remain largely unquestioned—is that when Plato and Aristotle talk about doxa, they are talking about what we now call belief. Or, at least, they are talking about something so closely related to what we now call belief that no philosophical importance can be placed on any differences. Doxa is the ancient counterpart of belief: hence, the use nowadays of ‘doxastic' as the adjective corresponding to ‘belief.' One of our aims in this paper is to challenge this view. We argue that Plato and Aristotle raise questions and advance views about doxa that would be very strange if they concerned belief. This suggests either that Plato and Aristotle had very strange ideas about belief, or that doxa is not best understood as belief. We argue for the latter option by pursuing our second aim, which is to show that Aristotle, expanding on ideas suggested in Plato, explicitly develops a notion that corresponds much more closely to our modern notion of belief: hupolepsis.
    [Show full text]
  • Barnes, Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J
    PHYSICS Aristotle The Complete Works of Aristotle Electronic markup by Jamie L. Spriggs InteLex Corporation P.O. Box 859, Charlottesville, Virginia, 22902-0859, USA Available via ftp or on Macintosh or DOS CD-ROM from the publisher. Complete Works (Aristotle). Jonathan Barnes, Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J. 1991. These texts are part of the Past Masters series. This series is an attempt to collect the most important texts in the his- tory of philosophy, both in original language and English translation (if the original language is other English). All Greek has been transliterated and is delimited with the term tag. May 1996 Jamie L. Spriggs, InteLex Corp. publisher Converted from Folio Flat File to TEI.2-compatible SGML; checked against print text; parsed against local ”teilite” dtd. THE COMPLETE WORKS OF ARISTOTLE THE REVISED OXFORD TRANSLATION Edited by JONATHAN BARNES VOLUME ONE BOLLINGEN SERIES LXXI 2 PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS Copyright © 1984 by The Jowett Copyright Trustees Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William St., Princeton, New Jersey In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, Oxford No part of this electronic edition may be printed without written permission from The Jowett Copyright Trustees and Princeton University Press. All Rights Reserved THIS IS PART TWO OF THE SEVENTY-FIRST IN A SERIES OF WORKS SPONSORED BY BOLLINGEN FOUN- DATION Printed in the United States of America by Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey Second Printing, 1985 Fourth Printing, 1991 9 8 7 6 5 4 Contents Preface ................................... ii Acknowledgements ............................ v Note to the Reader ............................ vi PHYSICS ................................. 2 BOOK I ............................... 2 BOOK II .............................
    [Show full text]
  • Early Greek Philosophy by Jonathan Barnes (Translator
    Early Greek Philosophy Jonathan Barnes (Translator) Early Greek Philosophy Jonathan Barnes (Translator) Early Greek Philosophy Jonathan Barnes (Translator) This anthology presents the early sages of Western philosophy and science who paved the way for Plato and Aristotle and their successors. Democritus's atomic theory of matter, Zeno's dazzling "proofs" that motion is impossible, Pythagorean insights into mathematics, Heraclitus's haunting and enigmatic epigrams-all form part of a revolution in human thought that relied on reasoning, forged the first scientific vocabulary, and laid the foundations of Western philosophy. Jonathan Barnes has painstakingly brought together the surviving Presocratic fragments in their original contexts, utilizing the latest research and a newly discovered major papyrus of Empedocles. Early Greek Philosophy Details Date : Published September 26th 2002 by Penguin Books (first published 1987) ISBN : 9780140448153 Author : Jonathan Barnes (Translator) Format : Paperback 336 pages Genre : Philosophy, Nonfiction, Classics, History, Literature, Ancient Download Early Greek Philosophy ...pdf Read Online Early Greek Philosophy ...pdf Download and Read Free Online Early Greek Philosophy Jonathan Barnes (Translator) From Reader Review Early Greek Philosophy for online ebook Leslie Williamson says I believe book was my introduction to early Greek Philosophy - the first text book I read in my first year Philosophy. Martti says What exactly is cosmos, the universe of all things, everything, the whole world? Did the universe have a beginning? If so, how did it begin? Why does it move and develop? What are its basic constituents? What is rain, wind, thunder, minerals, plants, animals, and human life? These profound questions are the subjects of this excellent book.
    [Show full text]
  • Francis Bacon, Nature, and the Politics of Religion
    The World’s a Bubble: Francis Bacon, Nature, and the Politics of Religion James A. T. Lancaster A dissertation submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Combined Historical Studies The Warburg Institute, School of Advanced Studies University of London 2015 – !1 – I declare that the work presented in this thesis is my own James A. T. Lancaster The World’s a Bubble, and the life of man / less than a span. ⎯ Francis Bacon, ‘The World’s a Bubble’ – !2 – Abstract This thesis examines the development of Francis Bacon’s (1561-1626) religious views and their impact on his programme for the advancement of learning. It aims to address the largely misguided body of scholarly literature on Bacon’s beliefs by situating his understanding of religion within the complexity of its Elizabethan and Stuart contexts, and to show how Bacon steered his own considered course between the emergent pil- lars of Puritanism and Conformism. To the latter end, it evinces how he drew upon the Christian humanism of his parents, Nicholas and Anne Bacon, as well as the political thought of Niccolò Machiavelli, Francesco Guicciardini, and Justus Lipsius. Guided by the same intellectual commitments, he subsequently came to develop his own ideas about the reform of knowledge and the character of nature within the broader context of Christian humanism, Florentine political thought, and the Magisterial Reformation in England. It argues that, contrary to modern categories of thought, Bacon had no difficul- ty being both a Reformed Christian and a statesman for whom religion was often little more than a social or political currency.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoic Theory of Void
    Vanessa de Harven University of California, Berkeley How Nothing Can Be Something: The Stoic Theory of Void Introduction The notion of void has posed metaphysical difficulties for philosophers since antiquity, and the Stoics are no exception. What could something that is arguably nothing even be? The Stoics’ answer to this question was a matter of some internal debate then, as it is now to those of us looking back. I will give an account of the Stoics’ unique theory of void, and show how it illustrates the general ontological principles that make the Stoics our first true physicalists. To appreciate the uniqueness of Stoic void a little background is necessary. Leucippus and Democritus, in the 5th century BC were the first atomists, followed by Epicurus in the Hellenistic period (4th and 3rd centuries BC). As David Sedley has argued,1 these theories did not come about in a vacuum (so to speak), and their evolution is instructive of the conceptual difficulties of ancient Greek physics. The Greek translated as void is to kenon, which literally means the empty. It is natural to take this as a mass term and thereby understand void as empty space. As Sedley argues, however, in responding to Pythagoras, Parmenides and Melissus, the atomists Leucippus and Democritus conceived of void rather as an element, a negative substance that itself occupies space. Indeed, this is the force of positing atoms and the void (better: voids) as the ultimate constituents of the cosmos. Epicurus and Lucretius, on the other hand, did espouse a concept of void as empty space.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Concept of Love in the Selected Novels of Julian
    THE CONCEPT OF LOVE IN THE SELECTED NOVELS OF JULIAN BARNES A THESIS SUBMITED TO TILAK MAHARASHTRA VIDYAPEETH, PUNE FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY (PH.D.) IN ENGLISH UNDER THE FACULTY OF ARTS AND FINE ARTS BY SHAHANE DATTATRAY GORAKH UNDER THE GUIDANCE OF DR. PAWAR SUNIL VISHWANATH BOARD OF ARTS AND FINE ARTS STUDIES AUGUST – 2017 1 DECLARATION I hereby declare that the thesis entitled “ The Concept of Love in the Selected Novels of Julian Barnes” completed and written by me has not previously formed as the basis for the award of any Degree or other similar title upon me of this or any other Vidyapeeth or examining body. SHAHANE DATTATRAY GORAKH Research Student Place: Pune Date: I CERTIFICATE This to certify that the thesis entitled “ The Concept of Love in the Selected Novels of Julian Barnes” which is being submitted herewith for the award of the Degree of Vidyavachaspati (Ph.D.) in English of Tilak Maharashtra Vidyapeeth, Pune is the result of original research work completed by Shahane Dattatraya Gorakh under my supervision and guidance. To the best of my knowledge and belief the work incorporated in this thesis has not formed the basis for the award of any Degree or similar title of this or any other University or examining body upon him. DR. PAWAR SUNIL VISHWANATH Research Guide Place: Pune Date: II ACKNOWLEDGEMENT It is a privilege to put on record my sincerest gratitude while submitting my Ph.D. thesis entitled The Concept of Love in Julian Barnes’s Selected Novels for the award of the degree to Tilak Maharashtra Vidyapeeth, Pune.
    [Show full text]
  • Morison-21.Pdf
    1 Name: Benjamin C. A. MORISON Address: Department of Philosophy, 1879 Hall, Princeton University, Princeton NJ 08544 Email: [email protected] Telephone: (609) 258 4304 Curriculum Vitæ 2012-present Professor, Department of Philosophy, Princeton University 2009-2012 Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Princeton University 2001-2009 Michael Cohen Fellow in Philosophy, Exeter College, Oxford Titular CUF, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford 2000-2001 Lecturer in Philosophy, The Queen’s College, Oxford 1997-2000 Junior Research Fellow, Corpus Christi College, Oxford Postdoctoral Fellow, British Academy 1996-1997 Assistant, University of Geneva 1995-1996 DPhil, Balliol College, Oxford (British Academy Major Award) ‘Aristotle’s Concept of Place’, Supervisor: Michael Frede DPhil obtained June 1997 (Examiners: Edward Hussey, David Sedley) 1994-1995 Assistant to Jonathan Barnes, University of Geneva 1992-1994 BPhil in Philosophy, Balliol College, Oxford (British Academy Major Award) Thesis: ‘On Location with Aristotle’. Subjects taken: Frege, Aristotle, Philosophy of Logic and Language. BPhil obtained June 1994 1988-92 BA in Literae Humaniores, Balliol College, Oxford (MA 1997) 1990: Mods (1st Class), 1992: Greats (1st Class) Prizes etc.: Noble Scholarship, Jenkyns Exhibition, Jenkyns Prize, Ernest Walker Philosophy Prize (awarded jointly), Fraser Exhibition. Visiting Positions 2017-18 Visiting Professor, Sorbonne Paris-IV; Visiting Researcher, Centre Léon Robin, Paris 2016 Visiting Professor, Renmin University of China,
    [Show full text]
  • Induction Before Hume by J
    Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 38 (1987), 49-74 Printed in Great Britain 49 Induction before Hume by J. R. MILTON I Introduction 2 A Historical Survey 3 The Varieties of Inductive Scepticism 4 Hacking's Account 5 An Alternative Explanation I INTRODUCTION The history of what philosophers and scientists have thought about induc­ tion has received surprisingly little attention. The reasons for this are not particularly obscure or problematic. Many philosophers in the analytic tradi­ tion have professed a conception of the nature of their subject which makes the history of philosophy almost completely irrelevant: the occasional remarks and discussions about historical figures are as perfunctory as those which appear in scientific textbooks, and indeed have an essentially similar function. Other traditions in philosophy may take its history more seriously, but unfortunately they are often either uninterested in or else even con­ temptuous of the whole subject of inductive inference. Finally, one im­ portant and highly influential school within modern philosophy of science has denied not only the rationality but even the existence of inductive reasoning. If such a view is taken seriously then a history of opinions about induction becomes not merely a potentially unprofitable but also an exceedingly problematic undertaking. If we look back at the history of thinking about induction, two figures appear to stand out from the remainder. Francis Bacon appears, as he would have wished, as the first really systematic thinker about induction; and David Hume appears as perhaps the first and certainly the greatest of all inductive sceptics, as a philosopher who bequeathed to his successors a Problem of Induction, which might be solved, or dissolved, or by-passed, but which could not legitimately or honestly be ignored.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle. a Very Short Introduction, by Jonathan Barnes
    Aristotle: A Very Short Introduction Very Short Introductions are for anyone wanting a stimulating and accessible way in to a new subject. They are written by experts, and have been published in more than 25 languages worldwide. The series began in 1995, and now represents a wide variety of topics in history, philosophy, religion, science, and the humanities. Over the next few years it will grow to a library of around 200 volumes – a Very Short Introduction to everything from ancient Egypt and Indian philosophy to conceptual art and cosmology. Very Short Introductions available now: ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Continental Philosophy Julia Annas Simon Critchley THE ANGLO-SAXON AGE COSMOLOGY Peter Coles John Blair CRYPTOGRAPHY ANIMAL RIGHTS David DeGrazia Fred Piper and Sean Murphy ARCHAEOLOGY Paul Bahn DADA AND SURREALISM ARCHITECTURE David Hopkins Andrew Ballantyne Darwin Jonathan Howard ARISTOTLE Jonathan Barnes Democracy Bernard Crick ART HISTORY Dana Arnold DESCARTES Tom Sorell ART THEORY Cynthia Freeland DRUGS Leslie Iversen THE HISTORY OF THE EARTH Martin Redfern ASTRONOMY Michael Hoskin EGYPTIAN MYTHOLOGY Atheism Julian Baggini Geraldine Pinch Augustine Henry Chadwick EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY BARTHES Jonathan Culler BRITAIN Paul Langford THE BIBLE John Riches THE ELEMENTS Philip Ball BRITISH POLITICS EMOTION Dylan Evans Anthony Wright EMPIRE Stephen Howe Buddha Michael Carrithers ENGELS Terrell Carver BUDDHISM Damien Keown Ethics Simon Blackburn CAPITALISM James Fulcher The European Union THE CELTS Barry Cunliffe John Pinder CHOICE THEORY EVOLUTION Michael Allingham Brian and Deborah Charlesworth CHRISTIAN ART Beth Williamson FASCISM Kevin Passmore CLASSICS Mary Beard and THE FRENCH REVOLUTION John Henderson William Doyle CLAUSEWITZ Michael Howard Freud Anthony Storr THE COLD WAR Galileo Stillman Drake Robert McMahon Gandhi Bhikhu Parekh GLOBALIZATION paul E.
    [Show full text]
  • Authentic Skepticism: the Delineation of a Dialectical Counterpart to Positive Epistemology
    Centre for Croatian Studies Vanda Bazdan AUTHENTIC SKEPTICISM: THE DELINEATION OF A DIALECTICAL COUNTERPART TO POSITIVE EPISTEMOLOGY DOCTORAL THESIS Supervisor: prof.dr.sc. Filip Grgić Zagreb, 2016 Hrvatski studiji Vanda Bazdan AUTENTIČNI SKEPTICIZAM: RAZGRANIČENJE DIJALEKTIČKE PROTUTEŽE POZITIVNOJ EPISTEMOLOGIJI DOKTORSKI RAD Mentor: prof.dr.sc. Filip Grgić Zagreb, 2016 Summary Common traits identified through a critique of those arguments which serve as paradigm cases in the prevailing distinction between two types of skepticism in this dissertation serve as a stepping stone to a different interpretation of skeptical approach in philosophy. The interpretation primarily draws on authentic commitment to skepsis, inquiry, inherent to all original skeptical arguments, and thus represents a reading of skepticism based on genuine appreciation of the proclaimed aim to skeptical argumentation, which is to serve as a dialectical counterweight to that which is determined. As such, the reading of skepticism offered is far removed from those interpretations in which skepticism is portrayed as a theory of ignorance or negative dogmatism. Through the prism of traits identified in delineation of authentic skeptical approach, this study further investigates the causes and consequences of these latter interpretations, specifically in the form in which they appear in philosophical discourse of 20th century epistemology and epistemology of the day. Key words: skepticism, Academic skepticism, Pyrrhonian skepticism, Cartesian skepticism, dialectical aim,
    [Show full text]