Performing Desire Jill Dolan and Stacy Wolf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Performing Desire Jill Dolan and Stacy Wolf Peggy Shaw, publicity poster for Must: The Inside Story. (Photo by Manuel Vason) Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DRAM_a_00393 by guest on 29 September 2021 Performing Desire Jill Dolan and Stacy Wolf The trope of “desire” has long been generative in performance theory, especially to mark femi- nist and queer engagements with live art. Broadly configured as an entry into language through Lacanian paradigms; as an expression of yearning and sexual identification between spectator and performer; as a process of potential objectification but also of pleasurable liberation; and as a motivating force and process that was assigned a great deal of power from many critical and theoretical quarters, “desire” was, especially in the 1980s and 1990s, one of the cornerstones of feminist and queer performance studies. But the marketplace of ideas the academy represents constantly renews and rewrites theory and, in that process, “desire” lost some of its originary power as a concept. We returned to it with this TDR Consortium issue because of our own attachment to its original promise, and because it continues to motivate our spectatorship, our scholarship, and our criticism. On a very basic level, our desire — to see performance; to experience ever new and transformative produc- tions of musicals or plays, both new productions and ones we’ve seen before; to witness inno- vative theatrical objects with fascination, provocation, confusion, and delight; to appreciate how performance calls and thwarts our own very particular affective, intellectual, and political investments; and to understand how other spectators and publics make use of and experience performance — compels our engagements with performance. Our invitation to the authors whose essays are collected here was simple. We asked them to write about “desire” in whatever way that term now strikes them. This issue represents, as a result, an eclectic but powerful reminder of how desire, for these writers as well as for us, remains an optic through which we see, feel, and think about performance. Judith Hamera reads Osman Khan’s installation Come Hell or High Water, part of the Museum of Contemporary Art Detroit’s show (in)Habitation: A Reconsideration of Domesticity, as a synecdoche for a city she sees as “anti-desire,” because it is under water with debt and structural abandonment (Hamera 2014). Jill Dolan is the Annan Professor of English, Professor of Theatre, and Director of the Program in Gender and Sexuality Studies at Princeton University. She is the author of many books and articles, including The Feminist Spectator in Action: Feminist Criticism for Stage and Screen (Palgrave Macmillan, 2013) and Utopia in Performance: Finding Hope at the Theatre (University of Michigan Press, 2005). She has received a career achievement award from the American Society for Theatre Research, an outstanding teaching award from the Association for Theatre in Higher Education, and the George Jean Nathan Award for Dramatic Criticism for her blog, The Feminist Spectator (www.TheFeministSpectator.com). [email protected]. Stacy Wolf is Professor of Theatre at Princeton University, directs the Princeton Arts Fellows. She is the author of Changed for Good: A Feminist History of the Broadway Musical (Oxford University Press, 2011) and A Problem Like Maria: Gender and Sexuality in the American Musical (University of Michigan Press, 2002). She is the coeditor of The Oxford Handbook of the American Musical (Oxford University Press, 2011). [email protected]. TDR: The Drama Review 58:4 (T224) Winter 2014. ©2014 New York University and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology 9 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DRAM_a_00393 by guest on 29 September 2021 By contrast, Susan Bennett and Marlis Schweitzer see Disneyworld’s “brandscaped” retail envi- ronment on its Main Street as a site that constantly manufactures consumerist desires, consid- ering, as they write, the “signature Disney performance — the princess makeover — to articulate the interplay between the production of a desiring subject and the commodification of expe- rience” (2014:xx). Brian Herrera continues this theme in his discussion of Billy, Carlos, and Tyson, three dolls created as gay male characters, marketed in the 1990s as what Herrera calls “symbols of whimsical resistance” that “went mainstream as commodities of conspicuous con- sumption before finally being interred as debris within the archive of popular culture.” Herrera argues that, “In their quick transformation from highly visible objects of gay desire to forgotten detritus of the recent gay past,” the dolls “also score the cartoonishly abrupt historical turns in the legibility of gay male desire within mainstream US popular performance during in the 1990s” (2014:xx). Moving from cities and objects of consumption to the physical bodies of live performers, Maurya Wickstrom and Fintan Walsh consider how performance art builds a complex desire between performer and spectator, charting more personal, intimate interactions in exchanges that they report as nearly private. Wickstrom details her own contact with a performance by the transgender artist Cassils to begin a larger meditation on “innovations in desire and temporal- ity” (2014:xx). Walsh looks at three very different European performances to suggest how per- formance seduces us with flirtatious intimacy. Jaclyn Pryor, on the other hand, in her discussion of Peggy Shaw presenting her aging butch lesbian body in performance for a younger genera- tion of genderqueers, sees desire exchanged through different iterations of time, within the performance and across the audience. Mary Jo Watts and Sara Warner venture into the archive of revolutionary persona Valerie Solanas and assess what they call her “defiant desire” to thwart adulthood, adopting instead a “SCUM-my” child’s play to cultivate political desire in girls (2014:xx). Deborah Paredez analyzes musical performances by Lena Horne and Judy Garland as divas defined through the trope of desire. Sarah Myers and Holly Hughes read desire through performance pedagogy: Myers con- sidering the complicated exchanges of the Austin-based Rude Mechs’s GRRL Action, a pro- gram for which at-risk teenaged girls narrate their lives in performance; and Hughes reporting on the transhistorical transactions of desire present when her students from the University of Michigan mounted a revival of her infamous dyke noir radio play, The Well of Horniness, and toured it to New York. Deb Margolin and Daniel Alexander Jones think through the opera- tions of desire in relation to their own performance work: Margolin in her play about basket- ball; and Jones in his alter-ego, the global superstar diva Jomama Jones. Sharon Bridgforth and Omi Osun Jones perform, in language, the ways their desire as African American women moti- vates their working relationship and their art. Finally, Kim Marra extends personal desire into scholarship and art practice, describing her love for her horse, Mylo, and reading that attach- ment into and through the friezes depicting the homoerotics of men riding bareback that adorn the Parthenon. Desire, in other words, now seems freed from the constrictions of a particular theoreti- cal language into a more fluid, resonant practice, strategy, and tactic, as well as a metaphor, an affect, and a movement between and among bodies in performance, across time and space. This new elasticity makes us hopeful for and curious about how desire will continue to morph use- fully and unpredictably, across the embodiments of performance. References Bennett, Susan, and Marlis Schweitzer. 2014. “In the Window at Disney: A Lifetime of Brand Desire.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):23–31. Bridgforth, Sharon, and Omi Osun Joni L. Jones. 2014. “Black Desire, Theatrical Jazz, and River See.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):136–46. Hamera, Judith. 2014. “Domestic(-ated) Desires, Tanked City.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):12–22. Dolan/Wolf 10 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DRAM_a_00393 by guest on 29 September 2021 Herrera, Brian Eugenio. 2014. “Billy’s World, or Toying with Desire in the Gay 1990s.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):32–45. Hughes, Holly. 2014. “Left Wanting.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):120–25. Jones, Daniel Alexander. 2014. “The Radiant Desire of Jomama Jones.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):129–35. Margolin, Deb. 2014. “Basketball and Desire.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):126–28. Marra, Kim. 2014. “Queer Aging Bareback: A Ride with the Parthenon Sculptures.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):147–57. Myers, Sarah. 2014. “The Trouble with Tears: Excess and Desire in Austin’s Grrl Action.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):68–79. Paredez, Deborah. 2014. “Lena Horne and Judy Garland: Divas, Desire, and Discipline in the Civil Rights Era.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):105–19. Pryor, Jaclyn. 2014. “When Elephants Are in Must”: Peggy Shaw, Acts of Trans/fer, and the Present Future of Queer Desire.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):68–79. Walsh, Fintan. 2014. “Touching, Flirting, Whispering: Performing Intimacy in Public.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):56–67. Warner, Sara, and Mary Jo Watts. 2014. “Hide and Go Seek: Child’s Play as Archival Act in Valerie Solanas’s SCUM Manifesto.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):80–93. Wickstrom, Maurya. 2014. “Desire and Kairos: Cassils’s Terisias.” TDR 58, 4 (T224):46–55. Performing Desire 11 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DRAM_a_00393 by guest on 29 September 2021.
Recommended publications
  • Ethics – Handout 10 My Notes on Mill’S Utilitarianism
    24.231 Ethics – Handout 10 My Notes on Mill’s Utilitarianism (1) General concerns: • Are interpersonal comparisons of utility even possible? • What are we talking about – maximizing total utility or average utility? • Both seem to ignore issues of distributive justice (except instrumentally – diminishing marginal utility of resources) • Average utility has some implausible implications (especially when considering harms, rather than benefits – is it really not worse for a total population of 100 people to be suffering torture than for a total population of 10 people to be suffering it?), and seems not to sit comfortably with utilitarian intuitions. Total utility invites the repugnant conclusion (but it’s important to remember that this isn’t just a problem for utilitarianism). (2) On higher and lower pleasures: • Should a utilitarian make any distinction between these? Is “pushpin as good as poetry,” if the quatity of pleasure they produce is the same? • How are we to determine which of two pleasures is higher? Is Mill’s appeal to “competent judges who have experienced both pleasures” plausible? And if competent judges prefer the higher pleasures, should we think they do so because activities leading them are more pleasurable, or have a higher quality of pleasure? Isn’t it perhaps more plausible to think they value them more for some other reason, having nothing to do with pleasure? • Relatedly, even if competent judges do take more pleasure in engaging in “higher” activities, are these activities more valuable because they are more pleasurable
    [Show full text]
  • Rational Desire and Rationality in Desire: an Unapologetic Defense Peter Railton Preliminary Draft of October 2008—Please Do Not Circulate Without Permission
    Rational Desire and Rationality in Desire: An Unapologetic Defense Peter Railton Preliminary draft of October 2008—please do not circulate without permission Introduction Consider Robert Stalnaker’s well-known, elegant formulation of the interlocking, functional nature of belief and desire: Belief and desire … are correlative dispositional states of a potentially rational agent. To desire that P is to be disposed to act in ways that would tend to bring it about that P in a world in which one’s beliefs, whatever they are, were true. To believe that P is to be disposed to act in ways that would tend to satisfy one’s desires, whatever they are, in a world in which P (together with one’s other beliefs) were true. [Stalnaker (1984), 15; emphasis added] This characterization gives a picture of a potentially rational agent as, so to speak, at the mercy of his beliefs and desires, whatever they are. Whether an individual agent is actually rational, one might naturally think, will depend on what fills in for ‘whatever they are’—for this will determine the shape of her life and, roughly, who, if anyone, is in charge. Put another way: Autonomy will depend heavily on how ‘whatever they are’ is filled in—what role does the agent herself play? And rationality will depend heavily on what is filled in—will the agent’s beliefs and desires be as they rationally should be?1 The thought is: If your beliefs and desires are as they rationally should be, and you as agent have played the right sort of role in acquiring them, then insofar as they are functioning normally—namely, as Stalnaker indicates—to guide how you act, then your actions, too, will be autonomous, and as they rationally should be.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding and Watering the Seeds of Compassion
    Research in Human Development, 12: 280–287, 2015 Copyright © Taylor & Francis Group, LLC ISSN: 1542-7609 print / 1542-7617 online DOI: 10.1080/15427609.2015.1068060 Understanding and Watering the Seeds of Compassion Mark T. Greenberg and Christa Turksma Pennsylvania State University The authors call for a broad agenda to create comprehensive models and research on the devel- opment and promotion of empathy and compassion. This wish would lead to a new level of 5 developmental/ecological understanding of the growth of compassion as well as effective policies and practices and interventions that nurture caring, compassion, and service to others in our schools and communities. The authors define empathy and compassion, briefly discuss the outline of early developmental processes, and call for basic research on these essential aspects of human develop- ment. The authors conclude by discussing the need to develop new ways to promote empathy and 10 compassion in families, schools and communities. Our wish is for a life-span developmental psychology to make greater contributions to building a compassionate world society. This calls for a broad agenda to create comprehensive models and research on the development and promotion of emotional awareness, empathy, and com- passion. The practical outcome of such a comprehensive program would include (1) clearer 15 developmental/ecological models of the growth of compassion; (2) effective policies, programs, and practices that support the development of caring, compassion, and service to others in our schools and communities; and (3) children, youth, and adults who show greater service to others as well as caring about the preservation of the earth’s ecology.
    [Show full text]
  • Reaching the Minds and Hearts of Those We Serve
    Connection Through Self-Compassion and Compassion for Others: Reaching the Minds and Hearts of Those We Serve Roseann Cervelli, MS, LACDC, CCS, CPS [email protected] 732-937-5437 Ext.122 Compassion, COVID 19 And the Year 2020: A New Threshold for Humanity Objectives • To analyze and explore how Mindful Self-Compassion serves as an antidote to apathy and disconnection in today’s world. • To define Mindful Self-Compassion and Compassion for Others as an approach to well-being, physically, mentally, emotionally and spiritually. • To describe how Compassion Awareness can address meeting Basic Core Needs and healing Core Wounds • To explore the Neuroscience within Compassion Focused Therapy and Compassion Awareness. • To introduce and experience several Mindful Compassion Exercises and Practices What words come to mind when you hear or see the word "APATHY"? ⓘ Start presenting to display the poll results on this slide. What Is Apathy ? A feeling and/or attitude of indifference, unconcern, unresponsiveness, detachment, dispassion. An absence of interest or concern about emotional, social, spiritual, philosophical and/or physical life and the world. Why Apathy? To understand the part of us that Rarely is it good to run, but we are wants nothing to do with the full wiser, more present, more mature, necessities of work, of more understanding and more relationship, of loss, of seeing thoroughly human when we realize what is necessary, is to learn we can never flee from the need to humility, to cultivate self- run away. compassion and to sharpen that - David Whyte, Consolations: The Solace, Nourishment and sense of humor essential to a Underlying Meaning of Everyday Words (2106) merciful perspective of both a self and another.
    [Show full text]
  • The Perfect Storm: Gay Men, Crystal Meth and Sex Cultural Considerations for Gay Affirming Treatment
    The Perfect Storm: Gay Men, Crystal Meth and Sex Cultural Considerations for Gay Affirming Treatment Craig Sloane, LCSW, CASAC Private Practice New York City [email protected] 917-670-0483 How did Crystal Meth become so popular with Gay Men? In order to figure this out we need to understand: • Pharmacology of Crystal Meth • Cultural consideraons • Crystal meth, gay men and sex • Crystal meth and HIV • Gay Male Sex and Drug SuB-Cultures • Gay Men’s Vulnerabili:es to SuBstance ABuse and Why Crystal Meth is such a “Good Fit” How can addic9on professionals help? In order to figure this out we need to understand: • Gay Affirmave Treatment • How to Treat the Fusion of Crystal Meth Use and Sex • How to Overcome the Unique Challenges of Treang this PoPulaon Pharmacology of Methamphetamine Street Names for Methamphetamine • Chrissy • Ice • Crystal • Speed • Meth • Crank • Tina • Glass What is Crystal Meth? Crystal meth can Be found as a white, yellowish or reddish Powder, a waxy solid or a clear rock. A 1⁄4 gram dose costs about $20. As a s:mulant, crystal increases the release of doPamine and norePinePhrine, the Brain’s Pleasure and alert chemicals. This Produces euPhoria, increases energy, Prolongs sexual Performance, and suPPresses apPe:te. Crystal can also Produce feelings of Power, confidence, invulnerability, and intense sexual desire. The high can last 8 to 12 hours (dePending on tolerance) and is followed By a Period of exhaus:on, dePression, irritability, and (some:mes) Paranoia known as the “crash.” Crystal is extremely addic:ve. Many gay and Bi men overes:mate their ability to keeP recreaonal use from escalang into dependence History of Methamphetamines • 1887 synthesized By German Pharmacologist L.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards a Conceptual Model of Affective Predictions in Palliative Care
    Accepted Manuscript Towards a conceptual model of affective predictions in palliative care Erin M. Ellis, PhD, MPH, Amber E. Barnato, MD, MPH, Gretchen B. Chapman, PhD, J. Nicholas Dionne-Odom, PhD, Jennifer S. Lerner, PhD, Ellen Peters, PhD, Wendy L. Nelson, PhD, MPH, Lynne Padgett, PhD, Jerry Suls, PhD, Rebecca A. Ferrer, PhD PII: S0885-3924(19)30059-4 DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jpainsymman.2019.02.008 Reference: JPS 10037 To appear in: Journal of Pain and Symptom Management Received Date: 4 September 2018 Revised Date: 24 January 2019 Accepted Date: 10 February 2019 Please cite this article as: Ellis EM, Barnato AE, Chapman GB, Dionne-Odom JN, Lerner JS, Peters E, Nelson WL, Padgett L, Suls J, Ferrer RA (2019). Towards a conceptual model of affective predictions in palliative care. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management, 57(6), 1151-1165. doi: https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.jpainsymman.2019.02.008. This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain. ACCEPTED MANUSCRIPT 1 Running title: AFFECTIVE PREDICTIONS IN PALLIATIVE CARE Towards a conceptual model of affective predictions in palliative care Erin M. Ellis, PhD, MPH (National Cancer Institute, Bethesda, MD, USA; [email protected]) Amber E.
    [Show full text]
  • Desire and Desire Regulation
    CHAPTER 3 Desire and Desire Regulation Wilhelm Hofmann Hiroki P. Kotabe Kathleen D. Vohs Roy F. Baumeister A good deal of people’s waking time is, more or less directly, spent think- ing about and dealing with desire. There is no question that desires are often benign, functional, and evolutionary adaptive for the individual. However, there are cases where desire stands in conflict with important (self- regulatory) goals or (moral) values. Prime examples include the ex- smoker who, upon seeing other people smoke, reexperiences a strong craving for a cigarette despite her intention to never smoke again, or two colleagues at work who cannot help feeling sexually attracted to each other despite the fact that one of them has made public vows of faith on the not-so-long-ago wedding day. And sometimes, much more trivially, the time or opportunity to fulfill a certain desire is just not “right,” such as when someone feels a strong need to pee on a long bus ride and, alas, the toilet is broken. There are both individual and societal reasons for why the capacity for desire regulation is such a highly important aspect of everyday functioning. The primary questions that we seek to answer in this chapter are: What is desire? When does it become problematic? How does desire regulation work? When and why can it go wrong? And how can it be improved? To approach issues of desire regulation, we will draw both on the literature of self- control and emotion regulation. The self- control literature is central because desires are driving forces that sometimes need to be held in check through inhibition or overriding.
    [Show full text]
  • Compassion in Action Section 1
    Compassion in Action Section 1 In this toolkit we will explore ways to maintain a compassionate presence in our interactions with students, families and colleagues. The rationale for this work as described in the first circle Compassion( Resilience) on the school toolkit home page, points to many positive outcomes for us and others. It turns out that coming from a mindset of compassion greatly contributes to our job and life satisfaction. Our first focus in the toolkit is to ask: What is compassion, what does it look like in action, and what does compassion requires of us? Simply put, Compassion is concern for the wellbeing of others. It includes both the awareness of others’ distress coupled with a desire to alleviate it. At the same time that we desire to alleviate another’s distress, we also are confronted with the reality that we cannot “fix” another person’s pain. Throughout this toolkit we will explore our professional role in alleviating student, colleague and other’s distress while maintaining our well-being, in other words, we will focus on growing our compassion resilience. Compassionate Action Steps (Combined from works of Monica Worline, Awakening Compassion at Work, 2017 and Beth Lown, The Schwartz Center for Compassionate Healthcare, 2014) 1. Notice – Be present in the moment and able to 3. Seek understanding – Listen with curiosity to recognize signs of distress. comprehend the other’s perspective. This may seem like an obvious and simple step. In Once you have suspended your initial appraisals, seek our fast-paced, task-oriented lives it is probable that to understand what it might be like to experience the we walk by pain all the time without recognizing it.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Hobbes on Intentionality, Desire, and Happiness
    Chapter 9 Thomas Hobbes on Intentionality, Desire, and Happiness Hobbes offers a surprisingly modern account of happiness, or felicity, as con- tinuous success in life. At the same time, he recognizes its paradoxical aspects, namely, happiness is never devoid of anxiety. His idea of happiness is based on desires, which is to be expected because for Hobbes persons are dynamic agents who aim at their own good directed by deliberation. I pay attention to the problems of intentionality. Deliberation is presented by Hobbes in exten- sional language, according to the principles of his scientific project, although intensional language is clearly needed when we discuss the success of projects and something like hitting a set target. I review and criticize the views of some authors who write as if Hobbes’s project were plausible, or he could reduce causa finalis to causa efficiens. In the end, I offer some comments on Hobbes’s alleged egoism. Theories of Happiness The following theories of happiness have been popular. They answer the ques- tion, when can we say a person is happy? I provide a brief sketch of each of them, relate Hobbes to some of them, and finally go deeper into his theorizing. Here are six typical views of happiness: A virtuous and only a virtuous person is happy, or happiness is virtuousness. A person who enjoys life is happy, or happiness means maximal pleasure and avoidance of pain. This is hedonism. A person who is calm and contented is happy, or happiness is peace of mind (ataraxia); it is also possible she enjoys the benefits of apatheia or freedom from passions.
    [Show full text]
  • Age Differences in Emotional Reactivity to Subtypes of Sadness
    AGE DIFFERENCES IN EMOTIONAL REACTIVITY TO SUBTYPES OF SADNESS AND ANGER RYAN M. MUSKIN Bachelor of Arts in Psychology University of Dayton May 2019 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree MASTER OF ARTS at the CLEVELAND STATE UNIVERSITY May 2021 We hereby approve this thesis for RYAN MUSKIN Candidate for the Master of Psychology degree for the Department of Psychology and the CLEVELAND STATE UNIVERSITY’S College of Graduate Studies by _________________________________________________________________ Thesis Chairperson, Eric Allard, PhD _____________________________________________ Department & Date _________________________________________________________________ Thesis Committee Member, Conor McClennan, PhD _____________________________________________ Department & Date _________________________________________________________________ Thesis Committee Member, Katherine Judge, PhD _____________________________________________ Department & Date Student’s Date of Defense: May 4, 2021 AGE DIFFERENCES IN EMOTIONAL REACTIVITY TO SUBTYPES OF SADNESS AND ANGER RYAN M. MUSKIN ABSTRACT Emotional reactivity has been commonly studied through the discrete emotion approach model (DEA) that categorizes emotions as singular unique experiences (sadness, fear, disgust, anger, etc.). Reactivity to a discrete emotion is related to the contextual relevance of the emotional elicitor, and thus, may result in variable reactivity profiles across different age groups. While prior research has typically associated older age with sadness
    [Show full text]
  • An Affective Neuroscience Model of Boosting Resilience in Adults
    An Affective Neuroscience Model of Boosting Resilience in Adults Golnaz Tabibnia University of California, Irvine Correspondence should be addressed to: Golnaz Tabibnia Department of Psychological Science University of California, Irvine 4201 Social and Behavioral Sciences Gateway Irvine, CA 92697 (949) 824-3002 Fax [email protected] Page 1 of 123 Abstract Although research has identified dozens of behavioral and psychosocial strategies for boosting resilience in adults, little is known about the common underlying pathways. A comprehensive review of these strategies using an affective neuroscience approach indicates three distinct general routes to resilience (Fig. 1A): 1) down-regulating the negative (e.g., exposure, cognitive reappraisal) by reducing distress-related responses of the amygdala, hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal axis, and autonomic nervous system; 2) up-regulating the positive (e.g., optimism, social connectedness) by activating mesostriatal reward pathways, which in turn can buffer the effects of stress; and 3) transcending the self (e.g., mindfulness, religious engagement) by reducing activation in the default mode network, a network associated with self-reflection, mind-wandering, and rumination. Some strategies (e.g., social support) can boost resilience via more than one pathway. Under- or over-stimulation of a pathway can result in vulnerability, such as over- stimulation of the reward pathway through substance abuse. This tripartite model of resilience-building is testable, accounts for a large body of data on adult resilience, and makes new predictions with implications for practice. Keywords: resilience; well-being; emotion regulation; affective neuroscience; amygdala; stress; reward; default mode Page 2 of 123 1. Introduction Whether surviving a natural disaster, loss of a loved one, or violence, most people experience a traumatic event at some point in their lives.
    [Show full text]
  • Desire, Time, and Ethical Weight
    Desire, Time, and Ethical Weight Dr. Nick Bostrom Department of Philosophy Yale University New Haven, Connecticut 06520 U. S. A. Fax: (203) 432-7950 Phone: (203) 500-0021 Email: [email protected] Desire, Time, and Ethical Weight 1. Introduction We want more than we can have. So we must somehow weigh our desires in order to determine which of them it is most important that we satisfy. When the objective is simply to maximize the satisfaction of one’s own current desires (“egoism of the present moment”), decision theory provides a well-worked out, albeit highly idealized, framework for conducting the requisite deliberation. It takes into account the strength of the various desires one has and the subjective probabilities of the possible outcomes of the actions one is choosing between (and, on causal decision theories, also one’s beliefs about the causal relations between actions and outcomes1). All that an egoist of the present moment has to do is to introspectively ascertain these parameters, calculate (or intuitively estimate) the expected utility of the various choices, and then pick the one with the highest expected utility. But what if one is not an egoist of the present moment? What if, for example, one’s objective is to maximize desire-satisfaction simpliciter, or even just satisfaction of one’s own desires, past, present, and future? Then there is a complication. For in order to get a measure of the total preference satisfaction in these cases, we have to compare preferences held at different times and for different durations. How to operationally compare the strengths of different people’s preferences, or the preferences of the same person at different times, is a notorious challenge for social choice theory.
    [Show full text]