Why Behaviorism and Anti-Representationalism Are Untenable

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Why Behaviorism and Anti-Representationalism Are Untenable Why Behaviorism and Anti-Representationalism Are Untenable Markus E. Schlosser University College Dublin Forthcoming in the Journal of Mind and Behavior This is the author’s copy (which may differ from the final print version in minor details) It is widely thought that philosophical behaviorism is an untenable and outdated theory of mind. It is generally agreed, in particular, that the view generates a vicious circularity problem. There is a standard solution to this problem for functionalism, which utilizes the formulation of Ramsey sentences. I will show that this solution is also available for behaviorism if we allow quantification over the causal bases of behavioral dispositions. Then I will suggest that behaviorism differs from functionalism mainly in its commitment to anti-representationalism, and I will offer two new objections to anti-representationalism. The first will be based on considerations concerning the contents of desires and intentions. The second objection concerns inner speech and mental imagery. We will see that the objections are of relevance to contemporary debates, as they apply with equal force to the currently popular anti-representationalist versions of embodied and enactive cognition. Keywords: behaviorism, Ramsey sentences, anti-representationalism The philosophy of mind literature distinguishes between two main types of traditional behaviorism: philosophical and psychological behaviorism (also known as analytical and methodological behaviorism).1 Both views are usually presented as relics of the past, and the implicit message is often that they are still being taught only so that we can learn from their failure (Graham, 2019; Heil, 2012; Kim, 2010). It is certainly true that psychological behaviorism is widely considered to be hopeless as a general theory of mind, but there are some remnants of this view to be found in many areas of empirical psychology. Most importantly, it is still often held or implicitly assumed that phenomena that can be explained in behavioristic terms should be explained in this way—in particular, they should be I would like to thank Dr. Russ (Editor) and an anonymous referee for their very helpful comments on an earlier draft. Correspondence regarding this article should be sent to Dr. Markus Schlosser, School of Philosophy, University College Dublin, Newman Building, Belfield, Dublin 4, Ireland. Email: [email protected]. 1 Philosophical behaviorism is most closely associated with the work of Gilbert Ryle (especially Ryle, 1949; see also Hempel, 1949). Sympathizers included Rudolf Carnap, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and W. V. O. Quine. The most important psychological behaviorists were Ivan Pavlov, John Watson, and B. F. Skinner. 1 explained, if possible, without the ascription of representational mental states. Likewise, it is widely agreed that traditional philosophical behaviorism is an untenable theory of mind. But the more recent past has seen the emergence of various views that are in line with philosophical behaviorism in the sense that they propose accounts of embodied and enactive cognition that do not require the ascription of mental representations (Chemero, 2009; Hutto and Myin, 2013; Thompson, 2007; van Gelder, 1995; Varela, Thompson, and Rosch, 1991). My focus here is primarily philosophical behaviorism and its anti-representationalist dimension. I will return to psychological behaviorism briefly in the conclusion. Philosophical behaviorism faces many objections and challenges. One of these objections is commonly singled out as the most devastating problem for the view. This is the problem of circularity. I will argue that this problem admits of a relatively straightforward solution if we make use of some of the insights that have emerged from the more recent debate on the nature of dispositions. If we refer to the causal bases of behavioral dispositions, we can solve, as I will argue, the circularity problem in the same way as functionalism does. This will force us to get clearer about the difference between behaviorism and functionalism, and it will lead us to the second part, in which I present two new objections to philosophical behaviorism. The first objection will be based on considerations concerning the contents of desires and intentions. In the second objection I argue that behaviorism cannot explain inner speech and mental imagery. It will become clear that those objections apply with equal force to the currently popular anti-representationalist versions of embodied and enactive cognition, and I will suggest that they point to clear limits for neo-behavioristic aspirations in psychology and cognitive science. Before we turn to philosophical behaviorism, let me add a note on the overall dialectic, which may seem rather odd, at first. In the first part I defend behaviorism against the circularity objection, and in the second part I reject the view. As indicated, there is reason in 2 this apparent incoherence. The reply to the circularity objection will bring into focus the key difference between behaviorism and functionalism. This will take us to my objections, which are objections that apply to all forms of anti-representationalism. Philosophical Behaviorism And the Circularity Problem Let me begin with an outline of traditional philosophical (or analytical) behaviorism (henceforth behaviorism, for short). This outline is based on the received view, as it is presented in standard textbooks (Graham, 2019; Heil, 2012; Kim, 2010). There are two main components of the view. The first is an analytical component that concerns the meaning of mental terms. It says, roughly, that statements about mental phenomena can be analyzed in terms of (or reduced to) statements about behavior and behavioral dispositions. The second component is ontological. It concerns the nature of mental states. It says, again roughly, that having certain mental states consists in the possession of behavioral dispositions and their manifestations in overt behavior. The analytical component is supposed to yield the ontological component: when mental terms are analyzed in behavioristic terms we can see that the possession of mental states can be reduced to the possession and manifestation of behavioral dispositions. To illustrate, let us consider two stock examples. It seems, for instance, that being in pain is typically accompanied by certain types of expressions, such as wincing, moaning, and by actions that lead to a cessation or alleviation of the pain (avoidance behavior). Behaviorism suggests that “being in pain” can be analyzed entirely in terms of such behaviors and behavioral dispositions, and that we have therefore no reason to think that the mental state of being in pain involves anything else than that. Or, it seems plausible to assume that what people believe is strongly correlated with what they are disposed to assert. Behaviorism suggests that the mental state type “belief that p” can be analyzed in terms of assertions and 3 dispositions to assert, and that mental states of belief are nothing over and above such behaviors and behavioral dispositions. At the time when behaviorism was developed and defended, it was commonly thought that dispositional properties, including behavioral dispositions, could be analyzed in terms of counterfactual conditionals. Behaviorism is still usually presented in this way, even though the conditional analysis is now widely rejected (more on this below). Assuming this analysis for now, a first approximation to an analysis of belief may take the following form: S believes that p if and only if S would assert that p if S were asked about p. There are, of course, obvious problems with that. What if the agent does not want to say or is afraid to say what is believed? What if the agent intends to express the belief without being asked? What if there is some misunderstanding or miscommunication? And so on. Note, first, that one cannot avoid those issues by rejecting the conditional analysis. Nowadays, the conditional analysis of dispositions is widely rejected, mainly due to various counterexamples. Consider, for instance, a sorcerer who would change the intrinsic properties of a fragile glass if it were to be struck, so that it would not break when struck. Or suppose that the sorcerer would cover the fragile glass with protective coating if it were to be struck, so that it would not break when struck. The former is an example of a “finkish” disposition (Lewis, 1997), the latter is an example of a “masked disposition” (Johnston, 1992). Such examples show that the truth of the relevant counterfactual is not necessary. Reverse cases, sometimes called “mimics,” show the opposite. Assume, for instance, that the sorcerer would turn a paper cup into a fragile cup whenever it was about to be struck. This appears to be a counterexample to the claim that the truth of the relevant counterfactual is sufficient (for more on this see Fara, 2005; Manley and Wasserman, 2008). 4 Various lessons can be drawn from this. One may suggest that this shows that dispositions cannot be explained reductively, and that it simply has to be accepted as a brute fact that dispositions may be finkish or masked in various ways. In light of this, one may suggest that behaviorism can appeal to dispositions without analyzing them as conditionals, and that there is, therefore, no need to specify all the possible defeating conditions. Given this, the proposal may be rendered as follows: S believes that p if and only if S is disposed to assert that p when S is asked about p. On this suggestion, the mentioned complications are not counterexamples. No claims are being made about what the agent would do, but only about what the agent is disposed to do. Suppose that, under certain circumstances, the agent does not and would not say what is believed. It may nevertheless be true that the agent is disposed to say what is believed (even in those circumstances). This strategy may help to avoid apparent counterexamples, but it does not get to the bottom of the issue. The mentioned complications are not merely potential counterexamples to behavioral analyses.
Recommended publications
  • A Comprehension of Spinoza's God
    A Comprehension of Spinoza's God Through the Dichotomy of Labels Tania Norell LUNDS UNIVERSITET | CENTRUM FÖR TEOLOGI OCH RELIGIONSVETENSKAP TLVM77 Philosophy of Religion Master Thesis 30 credits Supervisor: Jayne Svenungsson, Professor of Systematic Theology Examiner: Jesper Svartvik, Professor of Theology of Religions Autumn term 2015 Lund University Sweden Lund University Tania Norell Abstract: The 17 th century philosopher Spinoza is known for his concept of God as One Substance, God or Nature and therefore considered as a monist and categorized as a naturalist. He has been labeled an atheist and God-intoxicated man, as well as a determinist and pantheist, which I perceive to be dichotomies. The problem, as I see it, is that Spinoza’s philosophy and concept of God has mainly been interpreted through a dualistic mind-set, traditional to philosophers and theologians of the West, but Spinoza has a monistic worldview, and this has consequences in regards to the comprehension of what Spinoza’s concept of God entails and what a relationship “with” God implies . The labels panentheist and necessitarianist are discussed and the label of theologian argued. The thesis methodology is constructive because the purpose is to provide a theoretical foundation that has the potential to be applied in dialogues about God between the vast varieties of believers and non-believers alike, as well as across boundaries of contradicting worldviews and academic disciplines, and this focus on functionalism is inspired by a theory that calls for the furthering of inter-disciplinary dialogue between the subject areas philosophy of religion and theology specifically. My personal worldview is that there might well be One Substance, God or Nature, but that does not necessarily mean that there is one truth that is valid, but rather that all truth claims may be of value.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This Is a Story About Philosophy. Or About Science
    Chapter 1: An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This is a story about philosophy. Or about science. Or about philosophy transforming into science. Or about science and philosophy, and how they are related. Or were, in a particular time and place. At least, that is the general area that the following narrative will explore, I hope with sufficient subtlety. The matter is rendered non-transparent by the fact that that the conclusions one draws with regard to such questions are, in part, matters of discretionary perspective – as I will try to demonstrate. My specific historical focus will be on the propagation of a complex intellectual tradition concerned with human sensation, perception, and mental function in early nineteenth century Britain. Not only philosophical opinion, but all aspects of British intellectual – and practical – life, were in the process of significant transformation during this time. This cultural flux further confuses recovery of the situated significance of the intellectual tradition I am investigating. The study of the mind not only was influenced by a set of broad social shifts, but it also participated in them fully as both stimulus to and recipient of changing conditions. One indication of this is simply the variety of terms used to identify the ‘philosophy of mind’ as an intellectual enterprise in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.1 But the issue goes far deeper into the fluid constitutive features of the enterprise - including associated conceptual systems, methods, intentions of practitioners, and institutional affiliations. In order to understand philosophy of mind in its time, we must put all these factors into play.
    [Show full text]
  • Wundt's "New Psychology"
    Wundt's "New Psychology" Wilhelm Wundt(1832-1920) was the first professional to call himself a psychologist. He founded one of the first psychological laboratories in Leipzig, Germany, in 1879. Wundt believed the "only certain reality is immediate experience" (Blumenthal, 1975). If psychology were to be a science, then psychologists would have to collect data about experience. To do this, Wundt used procedures similar to those developed by the psychophysicists. He arranged controlled laboratory settings. He carefully administered stimulation such as sounds and sights. He gathered information about how quickly people responded to a stimulus (reaction time) and what they experienced. Wundt believed these experiments would lead to a consensus or agreement among scientists about the nature of experience. Wilhelm Wundt Wundt's approach was not unreasonable. It resembled the way most natural sciences developed in the 1800s. Science like botany and zoology began with careful observation and an effort to arrive at consensual validation (agreement among different observers). For example, biologists began with careful descriptions of plants and animals before trying to classify them. Wundt believed the same approach would work in psychology. Careful scientific observers could simply look inside themselves to see the mind in action, and they should be able to agree on the basic phenomena of psychology. After agreeing about basic observations, they could do a deeper analysis of what they had found. The technique of "looking inside" to gather data about the mind is called introspection . The problem with Wundt's program is fairly obvious to those of us in the modern world, where differences between people are taken for granted.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 11: Behaviorism
    Chapter 11: Behaviorism Megan Davis, Nicole Pelley and Stephanie Quinlan Behaviorism (1892-1956) ● Psychology has been the study of the mind since the Greeks ○ The definition of the mind has been debated extensively ○ 20th century: Shift from what the mind was to what it did ■ Mind causes behavior ● New field of research ○ Psychology was redefined with help from animal psychology ○ People started believing humans evolved from animal forms ○ Had to rethink Descartes’ definition of the mind New Directions in Animal Psychology New Directions in Animal Psychology Animal psychology as Romanes begun it, used 2 methods: 1. Anecdotal Method → Collect data 2. Method of Inference → Interpret data Close examination in late 19th, early 20th century. Anecdote → Experiment From Anecdote to Experiment ● Experiment replaced anecdotes and informal, naturalistic experiments ● Aim of animal psychology - produce natural science and anecdote not the path to science ● Two important research programs: ○ Thorndike ○ Pavlov From Anecdote to Experiment Edward Lee Thorndike (1874-1949): ● Initially wanted to study children ● Not many readily available, took up animals ● Studied with William James ● Developed “connectionism” ○ Methodological and theoretical approach to animal learning ○ Formulation of an S-R psychology he called “connectionism” ○ Anecdotal method overestimated animal intelligence From Anecdote to Experiment Thorndike’s Puzzle Boxes ● Trap cat inside box ● Each box opened by cat in different way ● Rewarded with salmon for escaping ○ Ex. of instrumental
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded on 2017-02-12T06:33:32Z PROPERTY of the MIT PRESS for PROOFREADING, INDEXING, and PROMOTIONAL PURPOSES ONLY
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Cork Open Research Archive Title Gamification as behavioral psychology Author(s) Linehan, Conor; Kirman, Ben; Roche, Bryan Editor(s) Walz, Steffen P. Deterding, Sebastian Publication date 2015-01 Original citation Linehan, C., Kirman, B. and Roche, B. (2015) 'Gamification as behavioral psychology' in Walz, S.P. and Deterding, S. (eds.) The Gameful World: Approaches, Issues, Applications. Cambridge, MA, USA : MIT Press, pp. 81-105. Type of publication Book chapter Link to publisher's https://mitpress.mit.edu/books/gameful-world version Access to the full text of the published version may require a subscription. Rights © 2014, Massachusetts Institute of Technology. All rights reserved. No part of this chapter may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. Item downloaded http://hdl.handle.net/10468/3462 from Downloaded on 2017-02-12T06:33:32Z PROPERTY OF THE MIT PRESS FOR PROOFREADING, INDEXING, AND PROMOTIONAL PURPOSES ONLY 3 GAMIFICATION AS BEHAVIORAL PSYCHOLOGY Conor Linehan, Ben Kirman, and Bryan Roche Those who advocate the benefits of a gamified or behavior, and introduce the field of behavioral psy- gameful world often advance a vision of the future in chology as an approach to understanding observed which all life and all work becomes increasingly behavior in gamified products. Behavior analysis is
    [Show full text]
  • Neural Networks
    Neural Networks 1. Introduction Spring 2020 1 Neural Networks are taking over! • Neural networks have become one of the major thrust areas recently in various pattern recognition, prediction, and analysis problems • In many problems they have established the state of the art – Often exceeding previous benchmarks by large margins 2 Breakthroughs with neural networks 3 Breakthrough with neural networks 4 Image segmentation and recognition 5 Image recognition https://www.sighthound.com/technology/ 6 Breakthroughs with neural networks 7 Success with neural networks • Captions generated entirely by a neural network 8 Breakthroughs with neural networks ThisPersonDoesNotExist.com uses AI to generate endless fake faces – https://www.theverge.com/tldr/2019/2/15/18226005/ai-generated- fake-people-portraits-thispersondoesnotexist-stylegan 9 Successes with neural networks • And a variety of other problems: – From art to astronomy to healthcare.. – and even predicting stock markets! 10 Neural nets can do anything! 11 Neural nets and the employment market This guy didn’t know This guy learned about neural networks about neural networks (a.k.a deep learning) (a.k.a deep learning) 12 Objectives of this course • Understanding neural networks • Comprehending the models that do the previously mentioned tasks – And maybe build them • Familiarity with some of the terminology – What are these: • http://www.datasciencecentral.com/profiles/blogs/concise-visual- summary-of-deep-learning-architectures • Fearlessly design, build and train networks for various tasks
    [Show full text]
  • Integrating Logotherapy with Cognitive Behavior Therapy: a Worthy Challenge
    See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/300077249 Integrating Logotherapy with Cognitive Behavior Therapy: A Worthy Challenge Chapter · January 2016 DOI: 10.1007/978-3-319-29424-7_18 CITATIONS READS 2 4,466 1 author: Matti Ameli 5 PUBLICATIONS 25 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Integrating Logotherapy with Cognitive Behavior Therapy (CBT) View project Translation of a Logotherapy workbook on meaningful and purposeful goals. View project All content following this page was uploaded by Matti Ameli on 13 November 2017. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. Integrating Logotherapy with Cognitive Behavior Therapy: A Worthy Challenge Matti Ameli Introduction Logotherapy, developed by Victor Frankl in the 1930s, and cognitive behavior therapy (CBT) , pioneered by Aaron Beck in the 1960s, present many similarities. Ameli and Dattilio ( 2013 ) offered practical ideas of how logotherapeutic tech- niques could be integrated into Beck’s model of CBT. The goal of this article is to expand those ideas and highlight the benefi ts of a logotherapy-enhanced CBT. After a detailed overview of logotherapy and CBT, their similarities and differences are discussed, along with the benefi ts of integrating them. Overview of Logotherapy Logotherapy was pioneered by the Austrian neurologist and psychiatrist Viktor Frankl (1905–1997) during the 1930s. The Viktor-Frankl-Institute in Vienna defi nes logotherapy as: “an internationally acknowledged and empirically based meaning- centered approach to psychotherapy.” It has been called the “third Viennese School of Psychotherapy” (the fi rst one being Freud’s psychoanalysis and the second Adler’s individual psychology).
    [Show full text]
  • From Moses and Monotheism to Buddha and Behaviorism: Cognitive Behavior Therapy’S Transpersonal Crisis
    FROM MOSES AND MONOTHEISM TO BUDDHA AND BEHAVIORISM: COGNITIVE BEHAVIOR THERAPY’S TRANSPERSONAL CRISIS Douglas Y. Seiden, Ph.D. Kowloon Tong, Hong Kong KaNei Lam, Ph.D. Hung Hom, Hong Kong ABSTRACT: Philosophers of science in psychology have traditionally defined the field in such a way as to keep it distinct from inquiry into external referents of transpersonal experience. The cognitive behavioral mindfulness therapies (MTs) provide a forum for increased assimilation by the mainstream discipline of knowledge and skills drawn from the perennial psychologies and technologies of transcendence, and for accommodation of psychology’s own world hypotheses, root metaphors and truth criteria. The science-metaphysics debate in psychology is presented, including the pragmatism of William James, the radical behaviorism of B.F. Skinner, and the functional contextualism of Acceptance and Commitment Therapy. Classical and operant behavioral approaches to mysticism are explored, with a proposal for an integral behaviorism incorporating ‘‘putative events’’ associated with anomalous states. The authors recommend a Transpersonal Cognitive Behavior Therapy drawing from the full range of wisdom tradition teachings in a manner that is entheo-syntonic with a given client’s world view. Reality may be merely an inference and, according to some authorities, a bad one. What is important may not be the physical world on the far side of the skin but what that world means to us on this side. —B. F. Skinner (The steep and thorny way to a science of behavior, 1975, p. 43) With our thoughts we make the world. —S.G.Buddha(Byrom,Dhammapada: The sayings of the Buddha, 1976, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Part 1 Applied Behavior Analysis
    FBA’s to BIP’s…. Development and Implementation Autism Academy 2011 Georgia Department of Education Day 1 Tris E. Gilland, BCBA, Ed.S. Autism Specialist Douglas County Schools Scientific study of socially relevant behaviors… guided by theory and philosophy (Behaviorism) follows a logical problem-solving process uses a method for examining variables and determining progress with respect to a given set of goals (decisions are data driven) Applied Behavior Analysis A method, for which behaviorism provides the theoretical underpinnings, for studying behavior of social significance, to better lives of those for whom it is utilized. APPLIED: ABA focuses on the implementation of basic principles to behaviors of significance to the participants involved. BEHAVIORAL: ABA focuses on behavior in its own right as a target for change. -We change behavior in many different forms *Increase appropriate or educational skills *Decrease inappropriate or problematic skills ANALYTIC: ABA seeks to identify functional relations between behavior and environmental events through scientific study. -We analyze situations so that we understand why behaviors are changing. TECHNOLOGICAL: In ABA, procedures are completely and precisely defined. -We are precise in our methods so we are confident in our outcomes. GENERALIZED: Behavior analysts attempt to discover procedures that can be applied effectively in many settings and with many people. -Behavior analysts attempt to use procedures that promote generalization and maintenance of behavior change. Has been called: -behavior modification -operant conditioning -behavioral analysis -consequence learning -etc… **Within the autism community, Applied Behavior Analysis has been misrepresented as being synonymous with Discrete Trial Training (DTT), Lovaas therapy, incidental teaching, pivotal response training, and other teaching procedures.
    [Show full text]
  • Behavioral Economics and the Effects of Psychology on the Stock Market Justin L
    State University of New York College at Buffalo - Buffalo State College Digital Commons at Buffalo State Applied Economics Theses Economics and Finance 5-2017 Behavioral Economics and the Effects of Psychology on the Stock Market Justin L. Nagy [email protected] Advisor Dr. Theodore Byrley First Reader Dr. Theodore Byrley Second Reader Dr. Frederick Floss Third Reader Dr. Xingwang Qian Department Chair Dr. Frederick Floss To learn more about the Economics and Finance Department and its educational programs, research, and resources, go to http://economics.buffalostate.edu/. Recommended Citation Nagy, Justin L., "Behavioral Economics and the Effects of Psychology on the Stock Market" (2017). Applied Economics Theses. 24. https://digitalcommons.buffalostate.edu/economics_theses/24 Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.buffalostate.edu/economics_theses Part of the Behavioral Economics Commons Behavioral Economics and the Effects of Psychology on the Stock Market By Justin L. Nagy An Abstract of a Thesis In Applied Economics and Finance Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree, of Master of Arts 2017 Buffalo State College State University of New York Department of Economics and Finance i Abstract of Thesis Behavioral Economics and the Effects of Psychology on the Stock Market The purpose of this thesis is to study the contributions behavioral economics and finance have had on the understanding on how the stock market works. The idea that psychology plays a role in influencing the stock market can be dated back to Adam Smith who wrote about individual’s behavior in his work Theory of Moral Sentiments. It wasn’t until the latter half of the 20th century that behavioral economics became accepted as a counter to Eugene Fama’s widely accepted theory of Efficient Market Hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Studies Anatolia Journal Logoterapi Ve
    R&S - RESEARCH STUDIES ANATOLIA JOURNAL www.dergipark.gov.tr/rs Vol: 1, Issue: 2, pp. 389-393 SOCIAL AND HUMAN SCIENTIFIC Yıldırım, A. (2018). “Logoterapi ve Din”, R&S - Research Studies Anatolia Journal, Vol:1, Issue:2; pp: 389-393 Anahtar Kelimeler: Logoterapi, Din, Varoluşsal Yaklaşım Keywords: Logotherapy, Religion, Existential Approach Makale Türü: Derleme LOGOTERAPİ VE DİN Logotherapy and Religion Dr. Ahmet YILDIRIM Milli Eğitim Bakanlığı, Ölçme, Değerlendirme ve Sınav Hizmetleri Genel Müdürlüğü, Milli Eğitim Uzmanı, [email protected] Ankara/Türkiye Makale Geliş Tarihi Revize Tarihi Yayınlanma Tarihi 04.07.2018 12.07.2018 30.07.2018 ÖZ ABSTRACT Logoterapi, bazı psikolojik rahatsızlıkların ve varoluşsal Logotherapy is a therapeutic approach which aims to boşluğun çözülmesini hedefleyen ve anlam arayışına resolve some psychological disorders and existential dayanan terapötik bir yaklaşımdır. Viktor Frankl emptiness. Logotherapy is basically based on search for tarafından İkinci Dünya Savaşı ve takip eden yıllarda meaning. Logotherapy, which was developed by Viktor ortaya konulan logoterapi; hümanistik bir yaklaşımı içine Frankl in the Second World War and subsequent years almaktadır. Bu çalışmanın temel amacı Viktor Frankl rests on humanistic approach. The aim of this study is to tarafından geliştirilen logoterapinin; tarihsel gelişimini, explore the historical development, strengths and güçlü ve zayıf yönlerini, logoterapideki bazı temel weaknesses of logotherapy besides defining some basic kavramları ortaya koymaktır. Buna ek olarak, mevcut concepts in logotherapy. Moreover, with this study it is çalışma ile logoterapinin dinle olan bağlantısının ve aimed to bring up the relationship between logotherapy ilişkisinin ortaya konulması amaçlanmaktadır. Mevcut and religion. The current study is a review study which is çalışma, bir derleme çalışması olup literatür taramasına based on literature review.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind Contents
    w 页码,1/177(W) Philosophy of Mind Jaegwon Kim BROWN UNIVERSITY Westview Press A Subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. -v- Dimensions of Philosophy Series All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Copyright © 1998 by Westview Press, Inc., A subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. Published in 1996 in the United States of America by Westview Press, Inc., 5500 Central Avenue, Boulder, Colorado 80301-2877, and in the United Kingdom by Westview Press, 12 Hid's Copse Road, Cumnor Hill, Oxford OX2 9JJ A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 0-8133-0775-9; ISBN 0-8133-0776-7 (pbk.) The paper used in this publication meets the requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials Z39.48-1984. 10 9 8 -vi- Contents Preface xi 1 INTRODUCTION 1 Minds as Souls: Mental Substances , 2 Mental Properties, Events, and Processes , 5 Philosophy of Mind , 7 Supervenience, Dependence, and Minimal Physicalism , 9 Varieties of Mental Phenomena , 13 Is There a "Mark of the Mental"? 15 Further Readings , 23 Notes , 24 2 MIND AS BEHAVIOR: BEHAVIORISM 25 Reactions Against the Cartesian Conception , 26 What Is Behavior? 28 Logical Behaviorism: Hempel's Argument , 29 A Behavioral Translation of "Paul Has a Toothache," 31 Difficulties
    [Show full text]