Postscript: Further Thoughts About Analyticity:20 Years Later
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Virtue Epistemology: Why Uncle Andrew Couldn’T Hear the Animals Speak
1 Virtue Epistemology: Why Uncle Andrew Couldn’t Hear the Animals Speak One of the most fascinating scenes in The Chronicles of Narnia features an incident that is truly puzzling. The scene takes place in The Magician’s Nephew . Four lucky humans (Digory, Polly, Uncle Andrew, and Frank the Cabby) and one very unhappy Witch (Jadis) watch as Aslan sings the new world of Narnia into existence. When the newly-created Talking Animals begin to speak, the human witnesses are amazed to find that they can understand them. Everyone, that is, except Uncle Andrew. All he can hear is barkings, howlings, and the like (MN, Chapter 10, p. 75). But why? Why wasn’t Uncle Andrew able to understand like everyone else? This is the sort of question asked by virtue epistemologists. And as we shall see, virtue epistemologists can shed a great deal of light on the puzzle before us. But before looking at the insights that virtue epistemologists can bring us, let’s get clear on what virtue epistemology is . Epistemology is the branch of philosophy concerned with the study of knowledge and belief. Epistemologists seek to answer fundamental questions like: “What is knowledge?” “How do people come to know things?” “ Can we really know anything?” “When is a belief justified?” “Are any beliefs one hundred percent certain?” and “Is the hoky poky really what it’s all about?” One hot topic among epistemologists centers on the distinction between believing something to be true and knowing that it’s true. Clearly, I can’t know something unless it’s true. -
Knowledge of Logic Is It Possible for Us to Know The
Knowledge of Logic Is it possible for us to know the fundamental truths of logic a priori? This question presupposes another: is it possible for us to know them at all, a priori or a posteriori? In the case of the fundamental truths of logic, there has always seemed to be a difficulty about this, one that may be vaguely glossed as follows (more below): since logic will inevitably be involved in any account of how we might be justified in believing it, how is it possible for us to be justified in our fundamental logical beliefs? In this essay, I aim to explain how we might be justified in our fundamental logical beliefs. If the explanation works, it will explain not merely how we might know logic, but how we might know it a priori. The Problem Stated To keep matters as simple as possible, let us restrict ourselves to propositional logic and let us suppose that we are working within a system in which modus ponens (MPP) is the only underived rule of inference. My question is this: is it so much as possible for us to be justified in supposing that MPP is a valid rule of inference, necessarily truth‐preserving in all its applications?1 I am not at the moment concerned with how we are actually justified, but only with whether it makes sense to suppose that we could be. We need to begin with certain distinctions. Suppose it is a fact about S that, whenever he believes that p and believes that ‘if p, then q’, he is disposed either to believe q or to reject one of the other propositions. -
University of Oklahoma Graduate College The
UNIVERSITY OF OKLAHOMA GRADUATE COLLEGE THE VIRTUES OF BAYESIAN EPISTEMOLOGY A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE FACULTY in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY By MARY FRANCES GWIN Norman, Oklahoma 2011 THE VIRTUES OF BAYESIAN EPISTEMOLOGY A DISSERTATION APPROVED FOR THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY ______________________________ Dr. James Hawthorne, Chair ______________________________ Dr. Chris Swoyer ______________________________ Dr. Wayne Riggs ______________________________ Dr. Steve Ellis ______________________________ Dr. Peter Barker © Copyright by MARY GWIN 2011 All Rights Reserved. For Ted How I wish you were here. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Dr. James Hawthorne for his help in seeing me through the process of writing my dissertation. Without his help and encouragement, I am not sure that I would have been able to complete my dissertation. Jim is an excellent logician, scholar, and dissertation director. He is also a kind person. I am very lucky to have had the opportunity to work with him. I cannot thank him enough for all that he has given me. I would also like to thank my friends Patty, Liz, Doren, Murry, Becky, Jim, Rebecca, Mike, Barb, Susanne, Blythe, Eric, Ty, Rosie, Bob, Judy, Lorraine, Paulo, Lawrence, Scott, Kyle, Pat, Carole, Joseph, Ken, Karen, Jerry, Ray, and Daniel. Without their encouragement, none of this would have been possible. iv Table of Contents Acknowledgments iv Abstract vi Chapter 1: Introduction 1 Chapter 2: Bayesian Confirmation Theory 9 Chapter 3: Rational Analysis: Bayesian Logic and the Human Agent 40 Chapter 4: Why Virtue Epistemology? 82 Chapter 5: Reliability, Credit, Virtue 122 Chapter 6: Epistemic Virtues, Prior Probabilities, and Norms for Human Performance 145 Bibliography 171 v Abstract The aim of this dissertation is to address the intersection of two normative epistemologies, Bayesian confirmation theory (BCT) and virtue epistemology (VE). -
Virtuous Knowledge: an Account of Virtue Epistemology Senior Honors
Virtuous Knowledge: - An Account of Virtue Epistemology Senior Honors Thesis (HONRS 499) By Erin R. Smith Dr. Juli Eflin, Advisor Ball State University Muncie, IN April 28, 2000 Date of Graduation: May 2000 L L Acknowledgements Many thanks to Dr. Juli Eflin for her time, impartial guidance throughout the development of my thesis, and her encouragement, which helped me fearlessly expound my own ideas. Thanks must also be given to my parents and friends who felt the philosophical concentration of the past eight months along with me, and continually supported my efforts. Now we may all rest our heads. My appreciation to Krista, Matt, Deidre, David, Julia and Mindy for allowing me to immortalize them in this discussion of virtue. Et in Arcadia ego. - Abstract Throughout history, virtue has out-stepped the bounds of ethics and entered other philosophical venues such as epistemology. Just as a person is responsible for exhibiting virtuous behavior, so is he or she responsible for virtuously attaining and holding beliefs in the quest for knowledge. In virtue epistemology, epistemic virtues are the fundamental mediums through which one's beliefs are justified. They are similar to moral virtues in definition and consequences, but differ in function in that epistemic virtues direct beliefs while moral virtues direct behavior. Some virtues to be described are openness, epistemic conscientiousness, epistemic courage, introspection and the skilled use of reason. - "Again and again a new truth is revealed to us in whose light all our previous knowledge must be rearranged. " -- Evelyn Waugh, Brideshead Revisited Like all epistemic theories, virtue epistemology must establish criteria and goals necessary for one to meet so knowledge can be achieved. -
An Introduction to Philosophy
An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so. -
Confluence: Online Journal of World Philosophies, Volume 4
Symposium: »Is Reason a Neutral Tool in Comparative Philosophy?« A Manifesto for Re:emergent Philosophy Abstract Is Reason a Neutral Tool in Comparative Philosophy? In his answer to the symposium’s question, Jonardon Ganeri develops a »Manifesto for [a] Re:emergent Philosophy.« Tracking changes in the under- standing of ›comparative philosophy,‹ he sketches how today’s world of academic philosophy seems to be set to enter an »age of re:emer- gence« in which world philosophies will (and can) be studied through modes of global participation. In their responses, the symposium’s discussants tease out implications of this Manifesto for different is- sues: While Mustafa Abu Sway suggests that comparative philosophy be understood as an intra-philosophical dialogue, whose aim depends on its participants, Paul Boghossian questions whether there can be conflicting, yet equally valid, ways of arriving at justified beliefs about the world. For her part, Georgina Stewart draws out the simila- rities between Ganeri’s understanding of comparative philosophy and the ethical stance involved in studying Maori science. In his Reply, Ganeri fleshes out his understanding of a pluralistic realism. Only an epistemic culture, which is open to a plurality of epistemic stances, he contends, can propel polycentric modes of knowledge production. Keywords Comparative philosophy, intellectual decolonization, intra-philoso- phical dialogue, relativism, Indigenous philosophies, Jonardon Ga- neri, Mustafa Abu Sway, Paul Boghossian, Georgina Stewart. Insofar as »comparative philosophy« is a branch of philosophy reason must be instrumental in its pursuit, given that philosophy is the em- ployment of the human capacity for reasoned thought to »understand how things in the broadest possible sense of the term hang together in the broadest possible sense of the term«. -
Virtue Epistemology and Abilism on Knowledge *
Virtue Epistemology and Abilism on Knowledge* John Turri [email protected] Abstract: Virtue epistemologists define knowledge as true belief produced by intellectual virtue. In this paper, I review how this definition fails in three important ways. First, it fails as an ac- count of the ordinary knowledge concept, because neither belief nor reliability is essential to knowledge ordinarily understood. Second, it fails as an account of the knowledge relation itself, insofar as that relation is operationalized in the scientific study of cognition. Third, it serves no prescriptive purpose identified up till now. An alternative theory, abilism, provides a superior ac- count of knowledge as it is ordinarily and scientifically understood. According to abilism, knowledge is an accurate representation produced by cognitive ability. Keywords: knowledge; ability; virtue; belief; reliability; philosophical method A popular view in contemporary Anglophone epistemology is that knowledge is true belief pro- duced by intellectual virtue. Philosophers accepting this are often called “virtue epistemologists.” Virtue epistemologists differ on how to characterize an intellectual virtue. Some theorists focus on refined intellectual character traits, such as open-mindedness or conscientiousness, which the agent cultivates over time through deliberate effort (Code 1987; Montmarquet 1993; Zagzebski 1996). On this approach, knowledge is defined as true belief produced by a refined intellectual * This is the penultimate version (10 June 2016) of a paper to appear in Heather Battily (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Virtue Epistemology (Routledge). Please cite the final, published version if possible. !1 character trait. Other theorists include reliable cognitive faculties, such as excellent vision or memory, among the intellectual virtues (Sosa 1991; Greco 1993; Goldman 1993). -
REVIEW ESSAY a Very Bad Argument
097291-Stolzenberg.qxd 9/17/2008 8:49 PM Page 1 REVIEW ESSAY A Very Bad Argument Gabriel Stolzenberg Paul Boghossian, Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), 135 pp., £15.99/€25.30/$24.95. ISBN 0–19928–718–X. This slim book by the philosopher, Paul Boghossian, is a many-pronged attack on relativism and constructivism, especially social constructivism, as seen from an objectivist perspective that he attempts to justify by appeals to logic and common sense. He wishes to defend the privileged status of science against those who hold that all belief systems are ‘equally valid’. There is a wealth of interesting material. I recommend especially the criti- cism of Wittgenstein on the logic of the Azande and of Richard Rorty on the dispute between Galileo and Cardinal Bellarmine. They remind us not to be too quick to conclude that two belief systems are incommensurable. Other philosophers whose seemingly constructivist or relativist views are criticized include Nelson Goodman and Hilary Putnam on the description- dependence of facts, Thomas Kuhn on incommensurability in science, and Pierre Duhem on the underdetermination of theory by evidence. Doubts about the Success of the Project Although Boghossian seems confident that he has refuted relativism and constructivism, I don’t see that he has refuted either. Indeed, most of his attacks are directed against the wrong targets. This is a predictable conse- quence of his tacit assumption that he can learn how things appear from another perspective merely by observing, from his own perspective, how they appear to appear from the other one. -
Reducing Modality∗ Theodore Sider February 24, 2008
Reducing Modality∗ Theodore Sider February 24, 2008 Does the formula “necessity is truth in all possible worlds” constitute a reduction of modality? Only if possible worlds both exist and can be nonmodally de ned. David Lewis’s (1986) concrete possible worlds are non-modally de- ned1, but it is very dif cult to believe that they exist. Perhaps it is easier to believe in abstract possible worlds, for example Alvin Plantinga’s maximal consistent states of affairs. But Plantinga and others use modal notions to characterize consistency, and so cannot—and do not—claim to reduce modal- ity.2 Other attempted reductions of possible-worlds talk are combinatorialist, ctionalist, or both (Armstrong(1989, 1997); Rosen(1990)), but I have argued elsewhere (2002; 2005) that these projects fail to reduce modality. A very different strategy for reduction does not appeal to possible worlds at all, but rather locates modality, somehow, in linguistic convention. This strategy has been unpopular during the last thirty years, among other reasons because conventionalism is apparently inapplicable to Kripke and Putnam’s examples of the necessary a posteriori (and, relatedly, to de re modality), because of other failures of conventionalism to provide a materially adequate account of modality, and above all, because of dissatisfaction with the idea of truth by convention. These were good reasons to reject the crude conventionalism of the posi- tivists, Wittgensteinians, and ordinary language philosophers. But I think that an attractive theory can be salvaged from its wreck. The new theory assumes a realist approach to metaphysics, semantics and epistemology that is utterly at odds with the approach of the traditional conventionalists. -
Catherine Elgin CV.Pdf
CATHERINE Z. ELGIN [email protected] CURRENT Professor of the Philosophy of Education POSITION: Graduate School of Education Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138 (617) 496-0504 EDUCATION: Ph.D., 1975, Brandeis University. Dissertation: Reference and Meaning: a Study of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. B.A., 1970, Vassar College. Major: Philosophy. Thesis: ‘The Implications of the Theory of Relativity for the Philosophy of Time’. PREVIOUS EXPERIENCE: 2000-2001 Visiting Professor of Ethics, Harvard Kennedy School of Government 1997-1998 Visiting Professor, MIT 1997-1998 Visiting Professor, Graduate School of Education, Harvard University 1996-1997 Visiting Professor, Wellesley College 1993-1995 Visiting Professor, Wellesley College 1992-1993 Visiting Professor, Princeton University 1990-1991 Visiting Professor, Dartmouth College 1988-1989 Visiting Associate Professor, Princeton University 1986-1988 Visiting Associate Professor, Wellesley College 1982-1986 Associate Professor (Tenured), UNC, Chapel Hill 1983-1984 Visiting Associate Professor, Mount Holyoke College 1981-1982 Andrew W. Mellon Fellow, Harvard University 1979-1980 Assistant Professor, Michigan State University 1975-1979 Assistant Professor, Simmons College 1974-1975 Assistant Professor, Vassar College FELLOWSHIPS AND GRANTS: 2014-2016 John Templeton Foundation Research Grant: Understanding 2014-2015 John Templeton Foundation Research Grant: Intellectual Humility 2011 Newhouse Fellow in the Humanities, Wellesley College 2009-2011 Spencer Foundation Grant 2004-2005 N.E.H Fellowship for University Teachers 1995 N.E.H. Fellowship for University Teachers 1994-1995 Fellow, Bunting Institute, Harvard University 1986-1987 John Dewey Senior Research Fellowship 1984-1985 ACLS Research Fellowship 1 1981-1982 Andrew W. Mellon Faculty Fellowship in the Humanities, Harvard University 1979 N.E.H. Summer Seminar: Epistemological and Moral Relativism, with Richard Rorty PUBLICATIONS: Books True Enough. -
The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas
Knowing and Trusting: The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas by Matthew Kent Siebert A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2014 © Copyright by Matthew Kent Siebert, 2014 Knowing and Trusting The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas Matthew Kent Siebert Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2014 Abstract This dissertation is an introductory exploration of two influential medieval thinkers, Augustine and Aquinas, on the topic of testimony. I explain how Augustine’s view that testimony is a source of knowledge (notitia) developed through four stages, and argue that on Augustine’s view testimonial belief is justified inferentially. I argue that Aquinas thinks some testimonial belief is justified inferentially, and some is justified by adhering to the speaker as the formal object of one’s belief, on the grounds that the speaker is truthful. I argue that these provide knowledge when they provide cognitio. And I argue that Aquinas’s view can be developed into a plausible account of testimonial trust and trustworthiness. ii Acknowledgments I am extremely grateful for the guidance and support of Peter King, Martin Pickavé, and Jennifer Nagel in the writing of this dissertation. I am also grateful to Deborah Black, Michael Siebert, Simona Vucu, and Ian Drummond, for their very helpful comments on earlier drafts of some of these chapters. And I am grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Government of Ontario, and the University of Toronto for financial support. -
Saving Epistemology from the Epistemologists: Recent Work in the Theory of Knowledge
Saving epistemology from the epistemologists: recent work in the theory of knowledge Adam Morton _________________________________________________________________ ABSTRACT This is a very selective survey of developments in epistemology, concentrating on work from the past twenty years which is of interest to philosophers of science. The selection is organized around interesting connections between distinct themes. I first connect issues about skepticism to issues about the reliability of belief-acquiring processes. Next I connect discussions of the defeasibility of reasons for belief with accounts of the theory-independence of evidence. Then I connect doubts about Bayesian epistemology to issues about the content of perception. The last detailed connection is between considerations of the finiteness of cognition and epistemic virtues. To connect the connections I end by briefly discussing the pressure that consideration of social roles in the transmission of belief puts on the purposes of epistemology. 1 Introduction 2 The shortest possible history 3 Knowledge: skepticism to reliability 4 From defeasible intuitions to the autonomy of evidence 5 Bayesianism to perceptual content 6 Finiteness to virtue 7 The structure of belief: from holism to foreground/background 8 Conclusion: from social networks to the biology of science _________________________________________________________________ 1 Introduction When philosophers of science address questions about confirmation, evidence, knowledge and rational belief they are usually addressing special cases of more general epistemological questions. But the flavor of the discussion is often quite different. Philosophers of science are concerned with a particular complex of belief acquiring institutions and practices. They want to know how they work, how well they work, and how they can be kept in good working order.