Isolated Experiences: Gilles Deleuze and the Solitudes of Reversed Platonism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Isolated Experiences: Gilles Deleuze and the Solitudes of Reversed Platonism Isolated Experiences: Gilles Deleuze and the Solitudes of Reversed Platonism James Brusseau Facultad de Filosofia y Letras Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico Acknowledgement I acknowledge Professor Alphonso Lingis for his contributions to this work. The task of contemporary philosophy has been defined: the reversal of Platonism. --Gilles Deleuze, 1968 Difference and Repetition Contents Introduction..............................................1 I Difference............................................ 1. Difference As Production And Limitation............... 2. The Eternal Return Does Difference: Production........ 3. See With My Own Eyes: Limitation...................... II Possession............................................ 4. Verbs And Nouns....................................... 5. Emily, The Patient, Bliss, Deleuze.................... 6. Desire, Not Want...................................... 7. Invitation To Possession.............................. III Alienation............................................ 8. Distance Without Measure.............................. 9. Rank Weeds And Fair Appearances....................... 10. Love Is For Other People.............................. Endnotes................................................... Introduction Experiences can be incestuous. They develop away from the general population; their genetic structures restlessly curve back into their own private histories. If they are going to be explained, they will have to explain themselves. Like sideshows at the travelling fair, it is not enough for the aberrations to be there. If the bearded woman and her dwarf-husband are just there, just walking around like all the rest of us, everybody ignores them, pretends not to notice, turns the other way. So a barker must be there too, with a tent to conceal the singular couple. He explains to passers-by why they want to see this freak of nature; he tells us why we should pay money to look. When his reasons make sense we go in and stare. This is a crucial element of what Gilles Deleuze means by reversing Platonism, it is not just malforming the priorities within Platonism, but also redirecting the mechanism for understanding reality, redirecting it into certain scenes. These scenes conjure their own meaning. Understanding no longer stretches out toward common reference and public accessibility, like Socrates referring to his universal metaphysical skyline. Understanding retracts into generation, a specific generation that looks like side-shows and backwater, provincial customs; it looks like things that make their own sense at their own performance and nowhere else. This book charts three secluded locations of experience bending back in on itself: difference, possession, alienation. In the bending back, philosophy splits. Difference is the broad, theoretical watershed dividing a transient world of becoming from one destined for placid identity. Possession is the subject's watershed dividing bodies violently swirled into disjoint forms and capacities from identities suffering nothing more than slight modifications in the midst of projects and circumstances. Alienation is the social watershed dividing a world mired in solitude from one understood through others. At each of these points, Deleuze follows the first alternative and so cuts away from philosophy's oldest tradition and finest lineage. I go with him. I show why Platonism fails to explain experience in limited cases, each within the categories of difference, possession, or alienation. Then I practice Deleuze's very twisted Platonism to better account for the recalcitrants. Platonism is not Plato. To grasp Plato, read the dialogues as criticizing Socrates. Platonism helplessly worships Socrates. Platonism identifies with the Republic's allegory of the cave, it grovels for the sun-drenched Outside. It allies with the young Socrates in the Parmenides as he earnestly ponders whether there exist Forms of hair and dirt. When ideas like this get taken seriously, Plato reduces to Platonism. If Platonism is so stunted, why reverse it? Because difference at its most compelling waits on the other side. Nietzsche would say Platonism is pregnant with a future; it is pregnant with difference. But not a simple opposite, no one will understand Deleuze by reading Plato and then looking up antonyms. Reversing Platonism means listening for another truth curled inside Socrates. Deleuze: That this reversal conserves many of the characteristics of the Platonists is not only inevitable but desirable....it is like the animal in the midst of being trained, its movements in final crisis best witness the state of natural liberty about to be lost: the Heraclitean world wails in Platonism. The essential elements of difference have been constrained inside Platonism. To bring them out, and in concentrated form, bring on a crisis. The crises in this book will always be crises of explanation, short moments where Socrates painfully fails to describe the world but where he imposes nevertheless. Here, from the gaps of brief failure, difference will surge. And surge through the very terms and ideas Socrates is imposing. Desire, for example, plays a leading role for both Platonism and Deleuze, as does the simulacrum. But Deleuze always perverts the precedent; watch him put lack after desire and raise simulacra to philosophic respectability. Platonism howls in protest. And it should howl, we should protest because Platonism is generally good, both intellectually and morally. It explains larger chunks of experience better than difference while buttressing a civilized ethics. Meanwhile, Deleuze's earth fills with localized threats of holocaust. Difference chisels experience with snarling aggression. It starts with an imposition blowing past dependence on others and blowing out the world entirely, then it pitilessly regenerates being and meaning in rigid compliance with its own selfish projects. This is Shakespeare's Titus Andronicus recklessly slaughtering a play's entire cast on the way to claiming his daughter's shame as his own. It remains uncertain whether this deranged power should be taught. But even if we don't teach it, scattered experiences will still fall through the cracks in morally acceptable philosophies. Deleuze enters here, explaining what no one else can, explaining with a method and with a philosophy inspired by Platonism reversed. He enters only rarely. Deleuze's philosophy works selectively. In this book, Deleuze's brand of difference will explain rare cases of possession and infrequently encountered states of alienation. No attempt to go further. This is not about imperial theory, it is about regional philosophic practices. The principal Deleuzean texts of reversal: Nietzsche and Philosophy (French publication: 1962), Difference and Repetition (1968), and Logic of Sense (1969). From Nietzsche, the first thinker to work explicitly against Socrates by working within Platonism, Deleuze learned a willpower that constructs: the world can be an active fabrication, not a corrupted metaphysical truth. In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze spells out difference's historical situation and basic tenets. Here, difference contains itself as a locus of production, a production climaxing in the generation of its own limits, its own end. Reference to anything exterior, anything outside falls away. Like Nietzsche before him, Deleuze is more than elitist. In Logic of Sense, Deleuze exhibits one of Plato's authentic skills, the ability to meld philosophy with literature. The book jauntily displays ideas developed earlier and dryly. Style reaches adequacy to substance; in both form and content, Deleuze has enveloped Socrates, spun him around, taken something from him, and guiltlessly moved on. The sequence counting down to Deleuze's reversal: Nietzsche, difference, difference practiced in literature. The sequence determining this book: difference, difference possessing, difference as possession generating isolation. At each step, the corridor between Platonism and Deleuze will narrow. First, it is an open dispute about the genesis of the world. Then it tightens to human proportion and grinding strife on the formation of identity. Finally, the way between collapses under the combined weight of alienation and a grave choice between two irreconcilable positions--one side or the other, Socrates or Deleuze, identity or difference. I wrote this book to distill a reversed Platonism and to draw it through selected and critical subjects Deleuze himself barely touched, subjects demonstrating the practical value, the potency of his thought. I wrote because Deleuze's work lets philosophy inject legitimate difference into experience and because Deleuze's work purges the fear from possession and because only Deleuze can answer this: what does it mean to be alone? I. Difference Begin with production and limitation. Production works at the base level where unformed being, where unformed experience emerges. The specific character experience takes, whether we see a table as gracefully carved from supple wood or as something keeping books and papers off the floor, whether we hear a blood- curdling scream and fearfully retreat or wait in anticipation, whether we think of Beethoven as musical elegance or shrill noise, all this is limitation. To achieve identification, a production must be limited; when limitation encircles production we have discrete experience. The ancient Greeks gave us form and matter. In the Phaedo, Socrates maintained a firm duality: when the physical body died,
Recommended publications
  • Introduction Part I Deleuze and Systematic Philosophy
    Notes Introduction 1. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane (New York: Viking, 1977), p. 240. 2. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi. (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), p. 3. 3. Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations, trans. Martin Joughin. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), pp. 88–89. 4. Gilles Deleuze, Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, trans. Constantine Boundas (New York: Columbia University Press, 1991), p. 107. 5. Ibid., p. 106. 6. Henri Bergson, The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison (New York: Philosophical Library, 1946), pp. 21–28. 7. Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994), p. 8. Part I Deleuze and Systematic Philosophy 1. Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations (1972–1990), trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), p. 31. 2. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), p. 18. 3. Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press), pp. 170–6. 4. Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books, 1992). This logic of expression is developed in chapters 1–2 and 6–8. 5. Spinoza brings together the notion of substance and expression in Part 1 of the Ethics: definitions 4 and 6, Proposition 10, and the Scholium following Proposition 10. The treatment of modifications and individuals first appears in Part 2, Proposition 7 along with its Corollary and Scholium.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Data Ethics 1 Defining Data Ethics in His Book Tap, Anindya Ghose Imagines a Future in Which a Company Could
    Introduction to Data Ethics Chapter from: The Business Ethics Workshop, 3rd Edition By: James Brusseau Boston Acacdemic Publishing / FlatWorld Knowledge ISBN: 978-1-4533-8744-3 Introduction to Data Ethics 1 Defining Data Ethics In his book Tap, Anindya Ghose imagines A future in which a company could send a coupon to a potential customer before she even leaves for a shopping trip that she didn’t even know she was going to take.1 This future will be made possible by data technology that gathers, stores, and organizes information about users of Facebook, Amazon, Google, Verizon. Every time you log in, you add details about who your friends are (Facebook), what you’re buying (Amazon), what’s going on in your life (Gmail), and where you are (mobile phone towers need to locate you to provide service). All this data is stockpiled atop the information about age, gender, location, and the rest that you handed over when you created your account. Then there are the databrokers—companies with less familiar names, Acxiom, for example—that buy the personal information from the original gatherers, and combine it with other data sources to form super-profiles, accumulated information about individuals that’s so rich, companies can begin to predict when you will go shopping, and what you’ll buy. The gathering and uses of data go beyond the marketplace. Law enforcement organizations, anti-terrorism efforts, and other interests are also learning how to gather and use digital traces of human behavior, but the most compelling scenes of data ethics are also the most obvious: occasions where we volunteer information about ourselves as part of an exchange for some (usually quick) satisfaction.
    [Show full text]
  • The Barbara Johnson Reader a John Hope Franklin Center Book the Barbara Johnson Reader the Surprise of Otherness
    The Barbara Johnson Reader A John Hope Franklin Center Book The Barbara Johnson Reader The Surprise of Otherness Barbara Johnson edited by melissa feuerstein bill johnson gonzález lili porten keja valens With an Introduction by judith butler and an Afterword by shoshana felman Duke University Press Durham and London 2014 © 2014 Duke University Press Afterword © 2014 Shoshana Felman All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America on acid- free paper ∞ Designed by April Leidig Typeset in Minion Pro by Westchester Publishing Services Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The Barbara Johnson reader : the surprise of otherness / edited by Melissa Feuerstein, Bill Johnson Gonzalez, Lili Porten, and Keja Valens, with an introduction by Judith Butler and an afterword by Shoshana Felman. pages cm “A John Hope Franklin Center Book.” Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978-0-8223-5419-2 (pbk : alk. paper) isbn 978-0-8223-5403-1 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Johnson, Barbara, 1947–2009. 2. Feminist literary criticism. I. Feuerstein, Melissa. II. Johnson Gonzalez, Bill, 1970– iii. Porten, Lili. IV. Valens, Keja, 1972– pn98.w64b37 2014 801.'95092—dc23 2013045003 Contents Ac know ledg ments vii Editors’ Preface xi Personhood and Other Objects: The Figural Dispute with Philosophy by Judith Butler xvii Barbara Johnson by Barbara Johnson xxvii part i | Reading Theory as Literature, Literature as Theory 1 The Critical Diff erence: BartheS/BalZac 3 2 Translator’s Introduction to Dissemination (abridged) 14 3 Poetry and Syntax:
    [Show full text]
  • Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues Author(S): R
    Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues Author(s): R. E. Allen Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 69, No. 2, (Apr., 1960), pp. 147-164 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183501 Accessed: 10/08/2008 14:32 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org PARTICIPATION AND PREDICATION IN PLATO'S MIDDLE DIALOGUES* I PROPOSE in this paper to examine three closely related issues in the interpretation of Plato's middle dialogues: the nature of Forms, of participation, and of predication.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Predication
    DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12054 Aristotle on Predication Phil Corkum Abstract: A predicate logic typically has a heterogeneous semantic theory. Sub- jects and predicates have distinct semantic roles: subjects refer; predicates char- acterize. A sentence expresses a truth if the object to which the subject refers is correctly characterized by the predicate. Traditional term logic, by contrast, has a homogeneous theory: both subjects and predicates refer; and a sentence is true if the subject and predicate name one and the same thing. In this paper, I will examine evidence for ascribing to Aristotle the view that subjects and predicates refer. If this is correct, then it seems that Aristotle, like the traditional term logician, problematically conflates predication and identity claims. I will argue that we can ascribe to Aristotle the view that both subjects and predicates refer, while holding that he would deny that a sentence is true just in case the subject and predicate name one and the same thing. In particular, I will argue that Aristotle’s core semantic notion is not identity but the weaker relation of consti- tution. For example, the predication ‘All men are mortal’ expresses a true thought, in Aristotle’s view, just in case the mereological sum of humans is a part of the mereological sum of mortals. A predicate logic typically has a heterogeneous semantic theory. Subjects and predicates have distinct semantic roles: subjects refer; predicates characterize. A sentence expresses a truth if the object to which the subject refers is correctly characterized by the predicate. Traditional term logic, by contrast, has a homo- geneous theory: both subjects and predicates refer; and a sentence is true if the subject and predicate name one and the same thing.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 1 and Unexemplified Properties, Kinds, and Relations
    UNIVERSALS I: METAPHYSICAL REALISM existing objects; whereas other realists believe that there are both exemplified CHAPTER 1 and unexemplified properties, kinds, and relations. The problem of universals I Realism and nominalism The objects we talk and think about can be classified in all kinds of Metaphysical realism ways. We sort things by color, and we have red things, yellow things, and blue things. We sort them by shape, and we have triangular things, circular things, and square things. We sort them by kind, and 0 Realism and nominalism we have elephants, oak trees, and paramecia. The kind of classification The ontology of metaphysical realism at work in these cases is an essential component in our experience of the Realism and predication world. There is little, if anything, that we can think or say, little, if anything, that counts as experience, that does not involve groupings of Realism and abstract reference these kinds. Although almost everyone will concede that some of our 0 Restrictions on realism - exemplification ways of classifying objects reflect our interests, goals, and values, few 0 Further restrictions - defined and undefined predicates will deny that many of our ways of sorting things are fixed by the 0 Are there any unexemplified attributes? objects themselves.' It is not as if we just arbitrarily choose to call some things triangular, others circular, and still others square; they are tri- angular, circular, and square. Likewise, it is not a mere consequence of Overview human thought or language that there are elephants, oak trees, and paramecia. They come that way, and our language and thought reflect The phenomenon of similarity or attribute agreement gives rise to the debate these antecedently given facts about them.
    [Show full text]
  • Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Commons@Waikato Philosophical Papers Vol. 30, No. 2 (July 2001): 117-143 Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg Abstract: This paper contrasts the scholastic realists of David Armstrong and Charles Peirce. It is argued that the so-called 'problem of universals' is not a problem in pure ontology (concerning whether universals exist) as Armstrong construes it to be. Rather, it extends to issues concerning which predicates should be applied where, issues which Armstrong sets aside under the label of 'semantics', and which from a Peircean perspective encompass even the fundamentals of scientific methodology. It is argued that Peir ce's scholastic realism not only presents a more nuanced ontology (distinguishing the existent front the real) but also provides more of a sense of why realism should be a position worth fighting for. ... a realist is simply one who knows no more recondite reality than that which is represented in a true representation. C.S. Peirce Like many other philosophical problems, the grandly-named 'Problem of Universals' is difficult to define without begging the question that it raises. Laurence Goldstein, however, provides a helpful hands-off denotation of the problem by noting that it proceeds from what he calls The Trivial Obseruation:2 The observation is the seemingly incontrovertible claim that, 'sometimes some things have something in common'. The 1 Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. Justus Buehler (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), 248. 2 Laurence Goldstein, 'Scientific Scotism – The Emperor's New Trousers or Has Armstrong Made Some Real Strides?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol 61, No.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • 2.2 Glock Et Al
    Journal for the History of Book Symposium: Analytical Philosophy Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy? Volume 2, Number 2 Introduction Hans-Johann Glock..................... 1 Editor in Chief Mark Textor, King’s College London Commentaries Guest Editor Leila Haaparanta......................... 2 Mirja Hartimo, University of Helsinki Christopher Pincock....................6 Editorial Board Panu Raatikainen........................11 Juliet Floyd, Boston University Graham Stevens.......................... 28 Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William Smith Colleges Ryan Hickerson, University of Western Oregon Replies Henry Jackman, York University Hans-Johann Glock..................... 36 Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Chris Pincock, Ohio State University Richard Zach, University of Calgary Production Editor Ryan Hickerson Editorial Assistant Daniel Harris, CUNY Graduate Center Design Douglas Patterson and Daniel Harris ©2013 The Authors What is Analytic Philosophy? shall not be able to respond to all of the noteworthy criticisms and questions of my commentators. I have divided my responses ac- Hans-Johann Glock cording to commentator rather than topic, while also indicating some connections between their ideas where appropriate. Let me start by thanking the Journal for the History of Analytical Phi- losophy for offering me this opportunity to discuss my book What is Analytical Philosophy? (Cambridge, 2008). I am also very grateful Hans-Johann Glock for the valuable feedback from the contributors. And I thank both University of Zurich the journal and the contributors for their patience in waiting for [email protected] my replies. I was pleased to discover that all of my commentators express a certain sympathy with the central contention of my book, namely that analytic philosophy is an intellectual movement of the twentieth-century (with roots in the nineteenth and offshoots in the twenty-first), held together by family-resemblances on the one hand, ties of historical influence on the other.
    [Show full text]
  • Media Translations of Fantasy Worlds
    A World of Difference: Media Translations of Fantasy Worlds Rachel Louise Mizsei Ward Doctor of Philosophy University of East Anglia School of Film, Television and Media Studies May 2013 This copy of the thesis has been supplied on condition that anyone who consults it is understood to recognise that its copyright rests with the author and that use of any information derived there-from must be in accordance with current UK Copyright Law. In addition, any quotation or extract must include full attribution. Rachel Mizsei Ward University of East Anglia Abstract The modern consumer has access to a massively complex entertainment world. Many of the products available reveal a visible movement of popular fantasy worlds between different media. This transmedia process creates a strong link between film, merchandising and games; with all of these mediums borrowing from each other. This borrowing takes various forms, from licensed adaptations to unofficial copying of ideas, settings and characters as well as exploiting the different aesthetics and techniques of different media. Much of the scholarship on transmedia concentrates on storytelling, where a single overarching narrative unfolds over several different media. This thesis will move away from storytelling to consider how culture producers borrow the aesthetics, narratives and fantasy worlds from other sources, including computer games. This borrowing happens because it enables them to use transmedia functionality to gain market share from an already established audience who have a vested interested in, and enthusiasm for, an established world. Most of this borrowing happens around specific genres – especially fantasy, science fiction and horror. These genres are particularly wide-ranging and emphasise the possibilities of worldbuilding, making then good sources for multi-media franchises.
    [Show full text]
  • Favorite Twilight Zone Episodes.Xlsx
    TITLE - VOTING BRACKETS First Round Second Round Sweet Sixteen Elite Eight Final Four Championship Final Four Elite Eight Sweet Sixteen Second Round First Round Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes Votes 1 Time Enough at Last 57 56 Eye of the Beholder 1 Time Enough at Last Eye of the Beholder 32 The Fever 4 5 The Mighty Casey 32 16 A World of Difference 25 19 The Rip Van Winkle Caper 16 I Shot an Arrow into the Air A Most Unusual Camera 17 I Shot an Arrow into the Air 35 41 A Most Unusual Camera 17 8 Third from the Sun 44 37 The Howling Man 8 Third from the Sun The Howling Man 25 A Passage for Trumpet 16 Nervous22 Man in a Four Dollar Room 25 9 Love Live Walter Jameson 34 45 The Invaders 9 Love Live Walter Jameson The Invaders 24 The Purple Testament 25 13 Dust 24 5 The Hitch-Hiker 52 41 The After Hours 5 The Hitch-Hiker The After Hours 28 The Four of Us Are Dying 8 19 Mr. Bevis 28 12 What You Need 40 31 A World of His Own 12 What You Need A World of His Own 21 Escape Clause 19 28 The Lateness of the Hour 21 4 And When the Sky Was Opened 37 48 The Silence 4 And When the Sky Was Opened The Silence 29 The Chaser 21 11 The Mind and the Matter 29 13 A Nice Place to Visit 35 35 The Night of the Meek 13 A Nice Place to Visit The Night of the Meek 20 Perchance to Dream 24 24 The Man in the Bottle 20 Season 1 Season 2 6 Walking Distance 37 43 Nick of Time 6 Walking Distance Nick of Time 27 Mr.
    [Show full text]