Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind http://content.cdlib.org/xtf/view?docId=ft958009gj&chunk.id=0&doc.v... Preferred Citation: Annas, Julia E. Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind. Berkeley: University of California Press, c1992 1991. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft958009gj/ Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind Julia Annas UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS Berkeley · Los Angeles · Oxford © 1994 The Regents of the University of California Preferred Citation: Annas, Julia E. Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind. Berkeley: University of California Press, c1992 1991. http://ark.cdlib.org/ark:/13030/ft958009gj/ Preface I began the project of writing this book in 1983, and it has been through a number of different versions. It was originally intended as part of a larger collaborative work on Hellenistic philosophy as a whole; but the larger work lagged while my chapter kept on growing and (I hope) improving, until finally it seemed more appropriate to let it expand to a more appropriate length as an independent publication. Since 1983 I have worked periodically on the book as well as on other research, and I have been able to work in more depth on some topics relevant to the book, such as Epicurean emotions, Stoic epistemology, and Epicurus' difficult views on agency. The book has improved from this, and also from the critical distance one can achieve when returning to familiar material after an interval. My aim has remained the same; I hope to provide a clear introduction to a fascinating subject, one that will help to make the subject accessible to readers with differing backgrounds, philosophical and classical. There is no area of ancient philosophy which is officially called "philosophy of mind"; but as practicing philosophers all know, the official demarcations of one's subject matter may not answer to the ways the subject develops, and I hope that readers will agree that when we look at the texts, what we find is in fact philosophy of mind. The contributions of the Stoics and Epicureans have long suffered neglect and sometimes contempt, partly from lack of sympathy with their fundamental principles and partly from misconceptions as to what the ― viii ― Stoics and Epicureans were trying to do. I have tried to be both sympathetic and critical, but my principal aim is to present a clear view of the Stoic and Epicurean theories, their major advantages and some problems they face. I spent the academic year 1983/84 at the Center for Hellenic Studies in Washington, D. C., as a junior fellow, doing research for this book. I am very grateful to Bernard Knox, then the director, and to everyone at the Center for making that such an enjoyable year. The Center is an ideal place for research, and like many junior fellows, I only wish I could return again. Several people read and commented on the first complete draft of the book. I am especially grateful to Myles Burnyeat, Jonathan Barnes, Tony Long, Martha Nussbaum, Brad Inwood, Christopher Gill, and Malcolm Schofield. Others who have helped me with portions 1 of 151 8/6/2006 1:30 PM Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind http://content.cdlib.org/xtf/view?docId=ft958009gj&chunk.id=0&doc.v... of the book are David Sedley, Simon Laursen, Gisela Striker, and Stephen Everson. I have benefited from discussion of papers relevant to parts of the book at the Duke University Conference on Tradition and Innovation in Epicureanism in the spring of 1989 and the Fifth International Symposium Hellenisticum in Syam, France, in August 1989. In the spring of 1989 I gave a seminar at the University of Arizona based on material from the book. I learned much from the graduates taking the seminar, especially from Stephen Laurence and from Victor Caston (visiting that semester from the University of Texas at Austin). Subsequently my colleague Rob Cummins read the whole manuscript and made valuable comments, many of which forced me to be more critical of crucial arguments or to make the progress of the argument clearer for readers who are not specialists in ancient philosophy. In my final rewriting I have been helped by detailed comments from Tony Long and from a referee for the University of California Press. With all this generous help I am especially sorry for mistakes and confusions that remain, for which I alone am of course responsible. I have been aided in two bouts of work on the book by having study leave from the Philosophy Department at the University of Arizona, and I am very grateful for this, as well ― ix ― as for the stimulating atmosphere and beautiful surroundings I enjoyed at Tucson. I am also grateful to Jonathan Barnes for joint seminars on Hellenistic philosophy which we held in Oxford and for continuing to inspire and stimulate my interest in Hellenistic philosophy by his own work. I am very grateful to Michele Svatos for preparing the Index Locorum and for enormous assistance with the General Index. The book is dedicated to my husband, David, who has been supportive and helpful intellectually and in every other way through the various stages of the book's progress (including periods when there was no progress), and to our daughter, Laura, who has been a source of joy for all eight years of her life, and seven of the book's. ― 1 ― Introduction Modern philosophy of mind, like most areas of philosophy, harks back from time to time to predecessors in the ancient world. Usually the predecessor singled out is Aristotle, the great founder of the subject. Aristotle's De anima and Parva naturalia are the first works to study psychological phenomena seriously in a philosophical way. Rooting "study of the soul" firmly in biology, Aristotle's works are the ancestors not only of philosophy of mind, as that is studied in philosophy departments, but also of systematic psychology, the more purely scientific study of psychological and mental phenomena. And Aristotle's approach is still of interest to modern philosophers, as is witnessed by the huge amount of research devoted in the last two decades to understanding Aristotle's theory of the soul and classifying it as physicalist, dualist, or functionalist.[1] Aristotle's successors, the philosophers of the Hellenistic or post-Aristotelian period, have been comparatively neglected. This is a pity, because the theories are sophisticated and interesting. It is also somewhat surprising, since even from the perspective of modern interest the Hellenistic theories have a great deal more in common with modern concerns than Aristotle's does. Furthermore, Hellenistic accounts of partic- [1] For a selection of recent work and reference to the vast secondary literature, see Nussbaum and Rorty (1991). ― 2 ― ular phenomena, such as perceiving, are often of great interest in their own right. Thus, both on grounds of their intrinsic interest and from the viewpoint of modern concerns, it seems reasonable to expand our picture of ancient philosophy of mind to include Aristotle's great successors. Hellenistic philosophy of mind has been generally neglected in the history of recent scholarship because Hellenistic philosophy generally has been undervalued, an imbalance that is now being corrected. In the recent past, however, this period of philosophy of mind was thought especially worthy of neglect. It was dismissed as crude, as a mere throwback to earlier ideas,[2] and even as a type of theory which was patently inadequate, but whose faults were overlooked in the haste to get to what was really supposed to matter, namely, the ethical conclusions.[3] Why was Hellenistic philosophy of mind held to be crude? The main reason is that all the major theories 2 of 151 8/6/2006 1:30 PM Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind http://content.cdlib.org/xtf/view?docId=ft958009gj&chunk.id=0&doc.v... are physicalist; they hold that the mind is (with refinements we shall examine) something physical. And until surprisingly recently the philosophical background of scholars interpreting Hellenistic philosophy was one in which the dominant theory was dualism. Hence we frequently find scholars dismissing Hellenistic theories as inadequate in principle on the grounds that they merely study the material conditions for mental activity to be possible, [2] Hellenistic theories often criticize, and make use of, pre-Socratic ideas; but so does Aristotle, who is not usually dismissed as a mere throwback. The relative importance attached by Stoics and Epicureans to their intellectual forebears is still uncertain and controversial. [3] Cf. Jaeger (1913, 56): "In der krasser Materialität der Seele erblicken sie [die Stoiker] wie die Atomisten den festen Anker, mit dem das politisch wurzellose Individuum, der apolis des Hellenismus sein vereinzeltes Dasein im Gesetzesfrieden des ehrwürdigsten aller Staat gründete, dem kosmos der sich wandelnden und umformenden Urstoffe." This general claim, that Hellenistic philosophy is a rush to ethical certainty motivated by the unbearable anomie of the postclassical period, is now thoroughly discredited. Further, the more important ethics is to a philosopher, the more important it is to have a firm basis for it, rather than a faulty one. ― 3 ― and omit mental activity itself.[4] More recently interpreters havetended to have an intellectual background in which it is physicalism that is dominant and dualism that is not taken seriously. And this makes it easier for us to understand the Hellenistic theories, for in that period also physicalism was seen as the norm. The terms "physicalism" and "materialism" have been used for many different kinds of theory. The theories that we shall examine in detail, those of the Stoics and Epicureans, are theories of a kind which I shall call physicalist. "Physicalism" here covers theories which claim that everything that exists is physical. "Physical" here in turn means "falls under the laws of physics." Something is physical if and only if it can be described and explained using only the concepts and methods of physics.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Happiness Regents Professor Julia Annas
    Philosophy 220: Philosophy of Happiness Regents Professor Julia Annas. MWF 1 – 1.50 pm. Chavez 301. The course has a D2L website, where all the readings are to be found. My office is Social Science Building 123. Office hours TBA. The Philosophy Department office is Social Sciences Building 213. Why happiness? Happiness matters!. There are large numbers of self-help books telling us how to be happy. Some nations are planning to measure the happiness of their citizens to find out how it can be increased. There is a huge field of ‘happiness studies’, and focus on happiness in positive psychology as well as politics and law. Much of this is confusing, since it’s often not clear what the authors think happiness is. Is it feeling good? Is it having a positive attitude to the way you are now? Is it having a positive attitude to your life as a whole? Is it having a happy life? How can some people advise others on how to be happy? Philosophers have explored happiness, and our search for happiness, for two thousand years. They have asked what happiness is, and have developed different answers, including some now being rediscovered. In this course we will ask what happiness is, and look at major answers. We’ll look at rich philosophical traditions of thinking about happiness, and also at some recent work in the social sciences. We’ll examine the contributions being made to the ongoing search to find out what happiness is, and how we can live happy lives. Course Readings Course readings will be available on the D2L site.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero on Epicurean Friendship: a Reappraisal 109
    Cicero on Epicurean Friendship: A Reappraisal 109 POLITEIA VOL. 1, No 2, SPRING 2019 APPENDIX CICERO ON EPICUREAN FRIENDSHIP: A REAPPRAISAL Phillip Mitsis New York University Given the occasion, I thought I might take the opportunity to revisit my first pub- lished paper on Epicureanism1 originally begun in a Lucretius seminar at Cornell in 1978 taught by Elizabeth Asmis. The paper's argument now seems to me in retrospect to exhibit a certain naive confidence in Cicero's reliability as a source, and though I still stand by some of its overall conclusions about Epicurean friendship, my views about the nature of the path that one needs to take to get to those conclusions has changed considerably.2 Readers will best judge whether a forty-year gap in looking at these arguments, apart from merely complicating matters, has led to any progress. At De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum 1.65-70, Cicero, through the character of Tor- quatus, offers our most detailed and seemingly systematic surviving account of Epi- curean views of friendship. Brad Inwood has forcefully reminded us, however, that this work has a particular focus and that its overall structure and arguments clearly reflect it.3 Cicero is examining what the fines (limits, ends, criteria, etc.) of goods and of evils are in various rival philosophical theories and in the first two books he sets himself the project of presenting and criticizing the Epicurean claim that pleasure serves as a final end or goal of our actions. One recurring problem in his account is that he glosses the notion of finis with terms having different valences and, thus, those wishing to extract from Cicero's discussion Epicurus' original view of friendship are faced with the problem that he often describes the relation of friendship to pleasure in terminology imprecise enough to encompass different theoretical outlooks.
    [Show full text]
  • Happiness in Ancient Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Happiness in Ancient Philosophy Juha Sihvola Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies The article discusses the conceptions of eudaimonia in the philosophy of Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics and argues against the growing tendency to make a sharp distinction between the ancient notion of eudaimonia and the modern notion of happiness. On the contrary, the traditional translation of eudaimonia as happiness is defended because it emphasizes the powerfulness of the challenge that the ancient eudaimonistic theories of ethics provide for our contemporary ways of thinking. Comparison with the ancient views encourages us to reject a purely subjective conception of happiness, defined with a reference to beliefs that one is getting the important things one wants and accompanying pleasant affects. The paradigm of happiness as subjective desire-satisfaction is shown to disregard the notion’s more objective aspects which can be uncovered by philosophical reflection. At the beginning of his famous Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle states that his aim is to determine what the ultimate end or good is that human beings aim at in their lives (I 2, 1094a18–28). He spells out certain formal criteria that this final end should fulfill: it is something complete and self-sufficient, something we aim at for its own sake and not for the sake of anything else. When we have reached this end, our lives are as good as they can possibly become; nothing further can improve our lives in any way.
    [Show full text]
  • An Existentialist Reconstruction of Pyrrhonism
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. VI 2012 Issue 1 Doubt and Anxiety: An Existentialist Reconstruction of Pyrrhonism Örsan K. Öymen (Bahcesehir University) The aim of this paper is to develop a potential relation between Pyrrhonism and existentialism. This is possible by establishing either an existentialist reconstruction of Pyrrhonism or a Pyrrhonian reconstruction of existentialism. The necessity of unveiling such a relation derives from: (1) the lack of an epistemological sceptical perspective and a normative ethical position within existentialism; (2) the lack of an accurate analysis of the human being within Pyrrhonism. However, the compatibility of the strong aspects inherent in both schools, the sceptical subjectivist arguments and the normative approach to morality inherent in Pyrrhonism and the analysis of the human being in relation to anxiety, potentiality, becoming, alienation, inauthenticity, authenticity and freedom inherent in existentialism, may show us a new way of looking into the universe and human life. The aim of this paper is to present a rather odd and unusual but hopefully original analysis on a potential relation between Pyrrhonism and existentialism. The way to do this is my proposal to establish either an existentialist reconstruction of Pyrrhonism or a Pyrrhonian reconstruction of existentialism. The necessity of unveiling such a relation derives from the lack of an epistemological sceptical perspective and a normative ethical position within existentialism as well as from the lack of an accurate analysis of the human being within Pyrrhonism; and the hope that the compatibility of the strong aspects inherent in both schools may show us a new way of looking into the universe and human life.
    [Show full text]
  • Greek Skepticism: Sextus Empiricus Merlin CCC – 7 November 2020 David Nowakowski [email protected]
    Greek Skepticism: Sextus Empiricus Merlin CCC – 7 November 2020 David Nowakowski [email protected] https://davidnowakowski.net People, Books, and Terms • Pyrrho of Elis (c. 360–c. 270 BCE) → Pyrrhonism. • Arcesilaus (c. 315–240 BCE) → the “Skeptical Academy.” • Sextus Empiricus (2nd/3rd cent. CE). ◦ The Outlines of Pyrrhonism. (abbreviation: PH). ▪ Book I: Skepticism and its methods. ▪ Book II: Applications: Logic. ▪ Book III: Applications: Physics and ethics. ◦ Against the Mathematicians. • Skeptics (and sceptics) and dogmatists. What is Skepticism? • “Skepticism is an ability to set out oppositions among things which appear and are thought of in any way at all, an ability by which, because of the equipollence in the opposed objects and accounts, we come first to suspension of judgement and afterward to tranquility.” (PH, I.8) ◦ An ability. ◦ Things which appear; things which are thought of. ◦ Equipollence. ◦ Suspension of judgement. ◦ Tranquility (ataraxia). • How does suspension “follow”? Logically, or chronologically? • Beliefs (dogma) vs. appearances. Examples • “Honey is sweet” (PH, I.92). • Mirrors and tricks of light (PH, I.48). ◦ The trial of Galileo. • The (moral) status of dogs (PH, I.62–72). • Comets (PH, I.141). ◦ Colonizing outer space? Sextus’ Four (Types of) Exceptions • “We live in accordance with everyday appearances, without holding opinions — for we are not able to be totally inactive.” (PH, I.23) 1. Guidance by nature → perceiving and thinking. (Descartes?) 2. Necessitation by feelings (pathē) → hunger leads to food, thirst leads to drink. 3. Handing down of customs and laws → accept (from an everyday point-of-view) that piety is good, and impiety is bad. 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue As a Skill
    InFocus Virtuenew trends, newas techniquesa Skill and current industry issues By Jon A. Schmidt, P.E., SECB have suggested previously (“Rethinking Engineering Ethics,” and “neo-Aristotelian” versions of the skill analogy in light of modern November 2010; “Engineering Ethics as Virtue Ethics,” May research – specifically, the Dreyfus model that I summarized in my 2011) that virtue ethics seems like a more appropriate approach last column (“The Nature of Competence,” March 2012). for engineering ethics than deontology (based on rules, duties, Aristotle identified three indispensable attributes of a virtuous person, Ior obligations) or consequentialism (based on outcomes). I have besides the obvious one of doing that which is virtuous: knowing also argued on multiple occasions that engineering is more of an art, what one does, intending to do it for its own sake, and acting with which is all about skill, than a science, which is all about knowledge. certainty and firmness. Doing the right® thing accidentally, or for the This column will attempt to unify these two ideas, drawing fromThe wrong reason, or only tentatively instead of habitually, is not sufficient Skill of Virtue, the 2007 dissertation of Matt Stichter, who was then to qualify as evidence of genuine expertise in virtue. Based on the a doctoral student at Bowling Green State University and is now an Dreyfus model, the same can be said of exercising a skill, except for assistant professor at the University of Washington. He noted that the stipulation that it be done for its own sake. one of the traditional tenets of virtue ethics, going all the way back Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus anticipated this discrepancy in a 2004 to the ancient Greeks, is that virtues are analogous to skills.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Voula Tsouna
    CURRICULUM VITAE VOULA TSOUNA PROFESSIONAL ADDRESS: Dept. of Philosophy University of California at Santa Barbara Santa Barbara, California 93106 telephone: (805) 893-3990 CITIZENSHIP: Greek CURRENT ACADEMIC STATUS: Tenured Professor of Philosophy, currently under consideration for accelerated promotion to Full Professor Step III at the Philosophy Department, UCSB. AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION: Socrates, Minor Socrates, Plato, Hellenistic Philosophy, Roman Philosophy, The Philosophical Papyri of Herculaneum. AREAS OF COMPETENCE: Presocratic Philosophers, Aristotle, issues in Medieval Philosophy, French philosophers of the 17th and 18th centuries, British Empiricists, areas of Epistemology, Ethics and Moral Psychology. EDUCATION: University of Athens, School of Philosophy, 1979-83; Πτυχεῖον in Philosophy (equivalent to the BA) 1983. Université de Paris X, 1983-84, 1986-88. Diplôme d'Études Approfondies (D.E.A.) in Ancient Philosophy 1984. Subject of thesis: "Sextus Empiricus et le réalisme ontologique," supervised by Prof. J. Brunschwig. Ph.D. in Ancient Philosophy (thèse de Doctorat) 1988. Subject: "Les philosophers Cyrénaïques et leur théorie de la connaissance" supervised by Prof. J. Brunschwig. Cambridge University, King’s College, 1984-86 (fully matriculated): Research in Hellenistic Philosophy. Supervisors: Prof. Myles Burnyeat and Prof. David Sedley. ACADEMIC AWARDS AND HONORS: Honourary acceleration to tenure, Department of Philosophy, UCSB, 2000. Theodor Mommsen Award for the book [Philodemus] [On Choices and Avoidances] (Bibliopolis, Naples 1995) . National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship in Philosophy, 1994-95. Centro per lo Studio dei Papiri Ercolanesi (Naples, Italy), Research Fellowship, 1988-89. Université de Paris X, Doctorat summa cum laude 1988. Université de Paris X, D.E.A. summa cum laude 1984. University of Athens, School of Philosophy, Ptykheion (equivalent of B.A.) with highest honors, 1983.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Bloomfield
    PAUL BLOOMFIELD Department of Philosophy University of Connecticut 344 Mansfield Rd, U-1054 Storrs, Connecticut 06269 [email protected] ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2013-Present: Professor, University of Connecticut 2006-2013: Associate Professor, University of Connecticut 2000-2006: Assistant Professor, University of Connecticut 1998-2000: Visiting Assistant Professor (Special Category), McGill University 1995-1998: Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Arizona EDUCATION 1995: Ph.D., Philosophy, Syracuse University 1984: B.A., Philosophy, Tufts University BOOKS Monographs The Virtues of Happiness: A Theory of the Good Life, Oxford University Press, New York (2014), paperback (2016). • Published in the series Oxford Moral Theory • Author-Meets-Critics, American Philosophical Association (Pac. Div.) 2016 Moral Reality, Oxford University Press, New York (2001), paperback (2004). • Author-Meets-Critics, American Philosophical Association (Pac. Div.) 2004 Edited Volumes Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism, David Copp (co-editor), Oxford University Press, New York (under contract). Morality and Self Interest, Oxford University Press, New York (2008). ARTICLES AND CHAPTERS "Virtues are Excellences", Ratio (forthcoming). "Humility is Not a Virtue", in The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Humility, Mark Alfano, Michael Lynch, and Alessandra Tanesini (eds.) 2021. "Skills of Justice", in The Routledge Handbook of Skills and Expertise, Ellen Fridland and Carlotta Pavase (eds.) 2021. Bloomfield, page 2 “Epistemic Temperance”, American Philosophical Quarterly vol. 56, no. 2: 109-24, 2019. "The Character of the Hypocrite", Journal of Philosophical Research vol. 44: 69-82, 2018. "Tracking Eudaimonia", Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology vol. 10, no. 2: 1-24, 2018. "Morality is Necessary for Happiness", Philosophical Studies vol. 174, no. 10: 2613-2628, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Archery and Virtue: Ancient and Modern Conceptions of Value
    Philosophers’ volume 14, no. 19 So too your friends … when they had considered the beauty of virtue, june 2014 forthwith flung aside everything they had seen except virtue itself. Imprint – Cicero, Fin. 4.421 In the opening lines of the Nicomachean Ethics, just before he begins to sketch an account of the human good, Aristotle draws a distinction Of Archery and between the kinds of ends at which a skill (technê) or an inquiry (methodos) may aim. Some ends, he remarks, are themselves activities (energeiai). Other ends are products (erga) distinct from the activities. Whenever a skill aims at some distinct product, Aristotle says, the Virtue: Ancient and product is by nature better than the exercise of the skill.2 This Aristotelian claim has been thought to mark a difference between ancient and modern conceptions of value. Thomas Hurka, for instance, suggests that Modern Conceptions it is characteristic of . modern values to deny [Aristotle’s assumption] and to hold that there are activities that necessarily aim at an external goal but whose value is internal to them in the sense that it depends entirely on of Value features of the process of achieving that goal.3 Hurka argues that it is in fact the concept of a game, in contrast to that of a productive skill, that best illustrates the modern understanding of value. He maintains that “game-playing is an important intrinsic good, which gives the clearest possible expression of what can be called a modern, as against a classical, or more specifically Aristotelian, view of 1. Sic isti cum … virtutis pulchritudinem aspexissent, omnia quae praeter virtutem ip- Jacob Klein sam viderant abiecerunt (trans.
    [Show full text]
  • NATURE and REASON in STOIC ETHICS a Dissertation Presented To
    NATURE AND REASON IN STOIC ETHICS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Jacob Samuel Klein May 2010 © 2010 Jacob Samuel Klein NATURE AND REASON IN STOIC ETHICS Jacob Samuel Klein, Ph.D. Cornell University 2010 This dissertation develops an interpretation of the foundational commitments of Stoic ethics. I argue, first, that the Stoics are committed to rational eudaimonism, understood as the claim that all reasons for action are relative to and explained by an agent’s own happiness. I argue, second, that this commitment clarifies the role of cosmic nature in Stoic theory and structures two fundamental Stoic doctrines, the doctrine of oikeiôsis and the doctrine of preferred indifferents. According to the doctrine of oikeiôsis, an organism’s telos is realized through the perfection of its controlling faculty or hêgemonikon. I argue that the Stoic account of self-perception is the most important element of this doctrine and helps to explain its role in Stoic ethical argument. According to the doctrine of preferred indifferents, although external circumstances make no difference to an agent’s happiness, the rational Stoic agent will prefer some indifferent outcomes to others. I argue that, as a consequence of Stoic eudaimonism, the value of preferred and dispreferred indifferents should be understood as epistemic rather than intrinsic. I conclude by distinguishing the Stoic conception of practical reason from Humean and Kantian conceptions. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Jacob Klein was born in Kealakekua, Hawaii. He received a B.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Practical Skepticism: Sextus Empiricus and Zhuangzi
    Practical Skepticism: Sextus Empiricus and Zhuangzi A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts By Brian York, March 2014 Thesis Written by Brian D. York B.A. Belmont University, 2011 M.A. Kent State University, 2014 Approved by Jung-Yeup Kim, Advisor Linda Williams, Interim Chair, Department of Philosophy Raymond. A Craig, Associate Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements……………………………………………………………….xi Introduction…………………………………………………………………………1 Chapter I Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Theory…………………………………........2 Section 1.1 Introduction……………………………………………………….2 Section 1.2 Definition of ‗Skeptic‘……………………………………………4 Section 1.3 Goal of the Skeptic……………………………………………….6 Section 1.4 Methodology of the Skeptic………………………………………9 Sction 1.5 Modes of Argumentation…………………………………………11 Section 1.6 Appearances……………………………………………………..19 Section 1.7 Inferences and Signs…………………………………………….23 Section 1.8 Conclusion…………………………………………………........24 II Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Practice…………………………………....25 Section 2.1 Introduction……………………………………………………...25 iii Section 2.2 Apraxia Charge………………………………………………….25 Section 2.3 Skepticism‘s Proper Scope……………………………………...28 Section 2.4 Appearance and Belief…………………………………………..30 Section 2.5 The Epistemic reading of ‗Appear‘……………………………..31 Section 2.6 An Alternative Interpretation……………………………………32 Section 2.7 Sextus‘ Four Guidelines…………………………………………34 Section 2.8 Solutions to the Apraxia Charges……………………………….37 Section 2.9 An Outline of
    [Show full text]
  • Julia Elizabeth Annas
    Julia Elizabeth Annas B.A. (Hons.), First Class, University of Oxford, 1968. A.M. Harvard University, 1970; Ph.D. Harvard University, 1972 Honorary Doctor of Philosophy, Uppsala University, Sweden, 2007. Lecturer in Philosophy, St. Hugh's College, Oxford, 1970-71. Fellow and Tutor in Philosophy, St. Hugh's College, Oxford, 1971-1986. Lecturer in Philosophy, Christ Church, Oxford, 1979-1986. Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Arizona, 1986-1991. Professor, Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, 1991-1992. Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Arizona, 1992- Regents Professor, University of Arizona, 1995- Senior Fellow, The Center for Hellenic Studies, Washington, D.C. 1993-1998. Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences (elected 1992) Getty Scholar, The Getty Center for the History of Art and the Humanities, 1994-5. College of Social and Behavioral Sciences 1996 Teaching Award for Graduate Teaching. University of Arizona Graduate Council 1999/2000 Award for mentoring graduate students. Research Professor, Social and Behavioral Sciences Researach Institute, University of Arizona, Fall 2000. Honorary Fellow, St. Hugh’s College, 2001. President, Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association, 2004-5 (vice-president 2003-4). Founder Editor, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 1983-1992. Co-Editor, Oxford Aristotle Series (with Dr. L. Judson). Referee for books: Oxford University Press, Cambridge University Press, University of Toronto Press, Cornell University Press. Referee for journal articles for journals in philosophy, ancient philosophy and classical studies. Evaluator for grants proposals for the N.E.H. and N.S.F., and for tenure and promotion decisions in U.S.,Canadian and U K universities, and Stanford Humanities Center fellowships, Advisor to the Understanding Agency project, University of Uppsala 1 Member of the international advisory committee to the Philosophical Psychology, Morality and Politics Center of Excellence, University of Helsinki.
    [Show full text]