Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-06231-3 — the Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic Edited by Catarina Dutilh Novaes , Stephen Read Index More Information

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-06231-3 — the Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic Edited by Catarina Dutilh Novaes , Stephen Read Index More Information Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-06231-3 — The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic Edited by Catarina Dutilh Novaes , Stephen Read Index More Information Index sı﻾, 81, 89, 311– 312, 315, 343, 345, 348ﻻʿAbd al- Latı﻾f al- Baghda﻽dı﻾, 80 Al- T￵u ʿAbdalla﻽h al- Ka﻽tib, 47 Alyngton, Robert, 152, 163 Abelard, Peter, 108– 113, 221, 223, Ammonius, 25, 28– 29, 35, 36– 37, 38, 248– 249, 251, 260, 300, 305, 47– 48, 176 317, 323, 359– 360, 361 ampliation, 220, 225, 232– 233, 234, 241, Abridgement of Logic, 51– 52 242, 327, 349 abstract intentions, 204 and restriction, 172, 182– 183, 225, 232, abstract meanings, 251, 263 233, 234, 237, 241, 242 abstractive thought, 161 rejection of, 75 al- Faraj b. al- Tayyib,￵ 50 analogy, 6, 80, 233, 330, 376 ﻻ Abu ,Bakr al- Ra﻽zı﻾, 49 analysis, technique of, 52– 53, 103, 108 ﻻAbu ,Bishr Matta﻽, 23, 26, 27, 41, 47, 51 109, 184– 186, 234, 285, 286, 308 ﻻAbu Ab Hamid Muhammad al- Ghazal, 120 344, 349– 350, 361– 362 ʾUthma﻽n al- Dimashqı﻾, 25, 32, 37, anaphoric words, 235, 242, 279 ﻻAbu 39, 41, 47 Andronicus of Rhodes, 20, 28, 35– 36 accidents, 31, 34, 52, 56, 58, 202, 209, 235, Anglicus, Robertus, 203 261– 262, 293, 333– 334, 336 Anonymous (Ars Burana), 250– 251, 263 Adam of Balsham, 112, 313 Anonymous (Ars Meliduna), 112, 251, 263 Adamson, Peter, ii, 5 Anselm of Canterbury, 8, 94, 101– 103, 221, affirmations, 6, 215, 246– 247, 258 see also 237, 239 negations antecedent, 71, 114, 155, 187– 189, 235– 237, affirmative propositions, 74, 88, 229– 230, 284, 312– 313, 318– 321, 322– 323, 291, 329– 330, 361 331– 334, 336 Agricola, Rudolph, 175 and consequent, 64, 71, 106, 110– 111, 114 Alberic of Paris, 112, 113, 115, 317 impossible, 72, 188, 311, 314 Albert of Saxony, 158, 164, 165, 169– 170, propositions, 300 183, 227, 233– 234, 238, 242– 243, reduction, 185 269, 279, 318 true, 187 Albert the Great, 34, 37, 120, 129, 170, Antichrist, 382 173, 200, 213, 217 Antonio Coronel, 187 Albertists, 170, 172 Apollonius Dyscolus, 34 Albricini, 112, 114 appellation, 102, 145, 182, 220, 223, 234, Alcuin of York, 32, 94– 96, 97– 99, 103, 104, 109 237– 238, 239– 240, 241, 242 alethic modalities, 62, 271, 344, 350, doctrine of, 238 353– 355, 357 replaced by supposition, 240 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 28, 30, 36, 47, restricted to appellative terms, 238 54, 176 “speculativa” (theoretical), 137 algorithms, 54 a- proposition, 351, 355, 357 ,al- H￵asan ibn Suwa﻽r, 46 Apuleius, 21, 28, 29, 32– 33, 35, 39, 41 Al- Kindı﻾ circle, 11, 25, 41, 42, 46 98, 101 437 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-06231-3 — The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic Edited by Catarina Dutilh Novaes , Stephen Read Index More Information 438 Index Aquinas, Thomas, 19, 120, 123, 170, Aristotelian Organon, 20, 46– 47, 50, 51, 172– 173, 177, 217– 218, 251, 253, 257, 140, 167, 180 see also Organon 263, 268 Aristotelian syllogistics, 272, 285, 293, 297, Arabic logic, vii, x, 2, 41, 45, 47, 49, 66, 84, 302, 312, 316– 317, 325 92, 348, 349– 350 Aristotelian theory of necessity syllogistics, Arabic logicians, 37, 45, 52, 59, 65– 66, 71, 132 75, 88, 295, 311 Aristotelian traditions, ix, 2, 31, 68, 75, 198, Arabic Middle Ages, 21, 39, 290 220, 347 Arabic Organon, 23, 42, 45 Aristotle, 2, 20– 22, 60, 118, 122– 128, 208, Arabic philosophers, 45, 47, 54– 55, 215, 258– 259, 304– 307, 316– 317, 123, 199 342– 343, 383– 384 Arabic translations, 20, 22, 24– 27, 32, 38, Analytics, 290 42, 47– 48, 342 and assertoric logic, 60 canonical position, 3, 10 27 ,26 ,ﻻBisr Matta ﻻby Abu ,by Hunayn’s son Ish￲a﻽q ibn H￵unayn, 24 Categories, 6, 7, 10, 32, 58, 124, 146– 147 lost, 26, 32, 37 158, 195, 227, 317 of Alexander’s commentary on the Prior corpus of natural philosophy, 47, 138 Analytics, 47 De Interpretatione, 7, 10, 19, 37, 100, 104, of Isagoge, 31, 38, 39– 40, 41– 42, 50, 98, 119, 127, 146, 195, 252, 317 100, 195– 196, 201, 202, 204, 206 Metaphysics, 153 of Porphyry’s commentaries on the Organon, 19, 20– 21, 31, 32, 35, 36, 40, Categories and On Interpretation, 37 41– 43, 45– 47, 67, 80– 81, 177– 178 pre- existent, 23 philosophy and logic, 121 argumentation, 9, 19, 32, 33, 44, 55, 139, Poetics, 45 175, 246, 262, 306 Posterior Analytics, 19, 21, 23, 36– 37, dialectical, 19, 36 38– 39, 40– 42, 46, 68, 156, 177– 178, dialogical, 20 199– 200, 216 logical, 55 Prior Analytics, 19, 25, 37– 38, 39– 42, schemata, 383 47– 48, 49– 50, 52, 124– 125, 127, 176, techniques, 6 296– 298, 342 theory, 394 Rhetoric, 27, 45 arguments, 86– 87, 113– 114, 116, 190, 245, Sophistical Refutations, 19, 42, 46, 265, 300, 302, 319, 334– 335, 337– 338, 60, 68, 112, 115, 144, 147, 183, 339– 340 200, 270 heuristic, 52 texts of, 10, 21, 27, 38, 50, 120, 209 non- syllogistic, 339 theory of cognition, 203 ordinary- language, 293 theory of syllogisms, 66, 302, 309 reductio, 111 Topics, 19, 33, 383– 384, 386 sophistical, 302 use of schematic letters, 322 syllogistic, 339– 340 see also argumentation Aristotle’s thesis, 74, 81, 82 Aristo, 35 Ars Burana, 250– 251, 263 Aristotelian dialectical games, 46, 52, 383, 392 Ars Meliduna, 112, 251, 263 Aristotelian essences, 359 Art of Logic, 145, 155, 271 Aristotelian logic, 7, 11, 19, 21, 166, 168, ascent, 183– 184, 229 170, 173, 175, 176– 177, 179– 180, 183 corresponding, 184, 237 summarized, 166, 176 equivalent, 184 supplemented, 220 suppositional, 183, 185 theory, 364, 367 Ashworth, E. Jennifer, vii– ix, 4, 6, 152, treatises, 49– 50 166– 190, 221, 244 Aristotelian logicians, 60, 81 Aspasius, 35 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-06231-3 — The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic Edited by Catarina Dutilh Novaes , Stephen Read Index More Information Index 439 assent, 56– 57, 67, 69, 70, 82, 254, 255, Buridanism, 171, 173 261, 263 Buridan’s nominalism, 155, 160, 163, 173 assertoric propositions, 344, 364, 365– 366 Burley, Walter, 143– 146, 147– 148, 151, 153, Athanase of Balad, 25, 26, 32 160, 161– 162, 237– 238, 253, 271– 274, Athı﻾r al- Dı﻾n al- Abharı﻾, 68– 69 324, 333, 336– 337 attribution, 184, 209 Buser, William, 159 Augustine, ii, 29– 30, 32, 43, 98, 149, 222– 223 Aulus- Gellius, 29 Calvin, John, 149 Averroes, see Ibn Rushd Cameron, Margaret, viii– ix, 14, Averroism, 139 195– 219, 393 Avicenna, see Ibn Sı﻾na﻽ Carolingian Renaissance, 8, 40 Avicennan logicians, 6, 11– 12, 68– 69, 73– 74 casus (set of assumptions), 265, 266, 268, axiomatic topics, 21, 33 275, 277, 279– 280, 283, 285, 372, 381, 393 Robert Bacon, 133– 134 categorematic, (subject and predicate) terms, Roger Bacon, 121, 132, 241 21, 105, 107, 147, 221– 222, 224, 258, Badawi, Abd al- Rahman, 23, 25, 36, 48 269– 270, 325, 332, 335, 336 Barbara LML, 369 categorical propositions, 74, 75, 80, 89, 181, Barbara LXL, 125, 364, 366, 368 236, 247, 290– 291, 305, 329, 330, 344 Barbara XLL, 125, 364, 366, 368– 369 particular, 329 Barbara XLM, 369 simple, 329 Barbara XLX, 369 standard, 183, 185 Barbara, inding a major premise for a categorical syllogisms, 21, 33, 42, 49, 97, syllogism in, 53– 54, 62, 105, 291 108, 304– 305, 307 “Begging the Question and False Cause”, categories, 24, 35, 36– 37, 41– 42, 58, 302, 304 67– 68, 95– 96, 128, 160– 161, belief, 267, 277, 391 195– 196, 208– 215, 257– 258 belief, religious, 199 logical, 210 belief revision, 394 material, 97, 99 Biard, J., 129, 161, 164, 254, 279 metaphysical, 210 Billingham, Richard, 150– 151, 164, 169, non- reducible, 213 261, 318 pseudo- Augustinian, 32 bivalence, principle of, 282, 288 subject matter of, 201, 210 Black, D.L., 5, 19, 46, 232, 377 Categories, 6, 7, 10, 32, 58, 124, 146– 147, Bobzien, Susanne, 29, 33, 39 158, 195, 227, 317 Boethius, 25, 28– 30, 33, 34– 37, 39, 42, Celaya, 170 see de Celaya, Juan 100– 101, 119– 120, 195, 298– 300, Cesalli, Laurent, 245– 264 316– 317, 383– 384 Cesena, Michael, 147, 153 Boethius’ thesis, 72 Chatton, Walter, 146, 151, 255, 257 Book of Six Principles (Liber de sex Cicero, 21, 29, 36, 97, 99, 230, 269, 316 principiis), 195 and Stoic logic, 29 Bradwardine, Thomas, i, 148, 269 De inventione, 33 Bricot, Thomas, 173 rhetorical and dialectical writings, 43 Brinkley, Richard, 151, 378 Topics, 30, 34, 37, 42, 98 Brito, Radulphus, 120, 129, 137, 204– 205, Ciceronis Topica, 33 209– 210 Clichtove, Josse, 174 Brumberg- Chaumont, Julie, vii– ix, 19– 44 commentaries, 35, 36– 39, 50– 51, 83– 84, Buridan, John, 154– 156, 163, 214, 238, 119– 120, 122– 124, 127– 128, 269– 270, 283– 284, 303, 320– 321, 168– 169, 172– 173, 176– 178, 324– 327, 330– 331, 338, 367– 369 195– 196, 198– 199 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-06231-3 — The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic Edited by Catarina Dutilh Novaes , Stephen Read Index More Information 440 Index commentaries (cont.) contemporary notions, 262, 264 bilious, 117 contingency, 72, 251, 342, 346 earliest known complete Latin, 342 indeterminate, 361 earliest known thirteenth- century, 212 natural, 361 literal, 51, 146, 197 propositions, 360, 366 logical, 36– 37, 38, 42 contingency- inferences, 364 middle, 50, 124– 125, 144, 296– 297 contraposition, 59– 60, 67, 73– 74, 81, 82, mid- thirteenth century, 217 83– 84, 90, 357 published, 170, 172, 178 conversion, 28, 59, 64, 67, 73, 82, 83– 84, 90, commentary traditions, 82– 83, 98, 108, 119, 344, 346– 347, 349, 357– 358 121– 123, 136, 140, 196 accidental, 130 complexly signiiables (complexe discussing modal, 72 signiicabilia), 156– 157, 182, 256, laws, 357 260– 261, 263 partial, 292 composite sense necessity- proposition, 365 rules,
Recommended publications
  • Obligations, Sophisms and Insolubles∗
    Obligations, Sophisms and Insolubles∗ Stephen Read University of St Andrews Scotland, U.K. March 23, 2012 1 Medieval Logic Medieval logic inherited the legacy of Aristotle: first, the logica vetus, Aristo- tle's Categories and De Interpretatione, which together with some of Boethius' works were all the logic the Latin West had to go on around 1100. Subse- quently, over the following century, came the recovery of the logica nova: the rest of Aristotle's Organon, all of which was available in Latin by 1200. The medievals' own original contribution began to be formulated from around 1150 and came to be known as the logica modernorum. It consisted of a theory of properties of terms (signification, supposition, appellation, ampli- ation, restriction etc.); a theory of consequences; a theory of insolubles; and a theory of obligations. This development was arguably stimulated by the theory of fallacy, following recovery of De Sophisticis Elenchis around 1140.1 It reached fulfilment in the 14th century, the most productive century for logic before the 20th. In this paper, I will concentrate for the most part on the theory of obligations|logical obligations. My focus will be on some logicians at the University of Oxford, mostly at Merton College, in the early fourteenth century, in particular, Walter Burley (or Burleigh), Richard Kilvington, Roger Swyneshed and William Heytesbury. I will contrast three different approaches to the theory of obli- gations found in these authors, and some of the reasons for these contrasts. The standard theory of obligations, the responsio antiqua, was codified by Burley in a treatise composed in Oxford in 1302.
    [Show full text]
  • Logica Vetus in Medieval France Jacob Archambault
    Contributions to a Codicological History of the Logica Vetus in Medieval France Jacob Archambault Abstract: In this paper, I provide a brief outline of shifts in the teaching of the texts of the Old Logic, or Logica Vetus, in France and its surrounding regions from the 10th to the mid-14th century, primarily relying on codicological evidence. The following shows: 1a) that prior to the 13th century, the teaching of the old logic was dominated by the reading of commentaries, primarily those of Boethius, and 1b) that during this same period, there are no clear signs of a systematic approach to teaching logic; 2) that during the 13th century, Boethius’ commentaries cease to be widely read, and the beginnings of a curriculum in logic develop; and 3) that the major development from the 13th to the 14th century in the organization of the Logica Vetus is the decreased presence of the Latin auctores, and a corresponding Hellenization of the study of logic more generally. Keywords: Aristoteles Latinus; Logic in Medieval France, history of; Ars Antiqua; Logica Vetus; Aristotle; Boethius; Medieval education, history of. Introduction This paper aims to outline the general features of the shift in the study of the Aristotelian logical corpus in the Gallican region from the 10th to the mid-14th century. The reason for this undertaking is in part a need to supplement more standard attempts at tracing the history of Medieval logic. Such accounts tend to be guided by, it seems to me, at least one of following three tendencies. The first is to focus heavily on the contributions of singular individuals, prodigies like Abelard or Ockham, who often attracted a number of followers.1 Though there certainly were major thinkers of this kind, the tendency to focus almost exclusively on them – trying, for instance, to determine whether one thinker is or is not directly acquainted with the thought of another – has arisen not so much because of the evidence itself as because of a certain romantic ideal governing much of our historiography of the middle ages, viz., that of the solitary genius.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Medieval Philosophy
    Syllabus 1 HISTORY OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY TIME: TTh 5:00-6:15 INSTRUCTOR: Stephen D. Dumont CONTACT: Malloy 301 /1-3757/ [email protected] OFFICE HOURS: By appointment. · REQUIRED TEXTS (Note edition) Hyman- Arthur Hyman and James J. Walsh, Philosophy in the Middle Ages 2nd ed. Walsh (Hackett , 1983) Spade Paul V. Spade, Five Texts on Mediaeval Problem of Universals (Hackett, 1994) Wolter Allan B. Wolter, Duns Scotus Philosophical Writings (Hackett, 1987) · RECOMMENDED TEXT McGrade Steven A. McGrade, Cambridge Companion to Medieval Philosophy (Cam- bridge, 2003) · COURSE REQUIREMENTS Undergraduate Graduate 25% = Midterm (Take-home) 50% = Research Term paper (20 pages) 25% = Term Paper (10 pages) 50% = Final (Take-home) 50% = Take Home Final · SYLLABUS: [Note: The following syllabus is ambitious and may be modified as we progress through the course. Many readings will be supplied or on deposit for you to copy.] EARLY MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY · BOETHIUS 1. Universals: Second Commentary on the Isagoge of Porphyry (In Isagogen Porphyrii commenta) [Handout from Richard McKeon, Selections from Medieval Philosophers. (New York, 1930), 1:70-99; cf. Spade, 20-25] 2. Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents: Consolation of Philosophy V [Handout from John F Wippel and Allan B. Wolter. Medieval Philosophy: From St. Augustine to Nicholas of Cusa, Readings in the History of Philosophy. (New York: Free Press), 1969, pp. 84-99] · ANSELM 1. Existence of God: Proslogion 1-4; On Behalf of the Fool by Gaunilo; Reply to the Fool. [Hyman-Walsh, 149-62] Syllabus 2 · ABELARD, 1. Universals: Glosses on Porphyry in Logic for Beginners (Logica ingredientibus) [Spade, 26-56; cf.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Renaissance and Modern Logic from 1400 to 1850
    History of Renaissance and Modern Logic from 1400 to 1850 https://www.historyoflogic.com/logic-modern.htm History of Logic from Aristotle to Gödel by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] History of Renaissance and Modern Logic from 1400 to 1850 INTRODUCTION: LOGIC IN CONTINENTAL EUROPE "At the end of the fourteenth century there were roughly three categories of work available to those studying logic. The first category is that of commentaries on Aristotle's 'Organon'. The most comprehensive of these focussed either on the books of the Logica Vetus, which included Porphyry's Isagoge along with the Categories and De Interpretatione; or on the books of the Logica Nova, the remaining works of the 'Organon' which had become known to the West only during the twelfth century. In addition there were, of course, numerous commentaries on individual books of the 'Organon'. The second category is that of works on non-Aristotelian topics. These include the so-called Parva logicalia, or treatises on supposition, relative terms, ampliation, appellation, restriction and distribution. To these could be added tracts on exponibles and on syncategorematic terms. Peter of Spain is now the best-known author of parva logicalia, but such authors as Thomas Maulvelt and Marsilius of Inghen were almost as influential in the late fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. Another group of works belonging to the second category consists of the so-called 'tracts of the moderns', namely treatises on consequences, obligations and insolubles. A third group includes treatises on sophisms, on the composite and divided senses, and on proofs of terms, especially the well-known Speculum puerorum by Richard Billingham.
    [Show full text]
  • General Introduction
    MP_A02.qxd 11/17/06 5:26 PM Page 1 General Introduction Medieval Philosophy in Perspective In the modern mind, the adjective “medieval” has often been associated with ideas of darkness, dogmatism, oppression, and barbarity. This should not be surprising, if we con- sider how modernity came to define itself, precisely in opposition to the medieval tradition, as the Renaissance, the re-birth of ancient learning, the Reformation of a corrupt church, the Enlightenment after an age of darkness, an Age of Reason after an age of ignorance and blind faith. Even today, this mentality has its visible effects. To the intellectual reflexes of “the modern mind” referred to above, the very phrase “medieval philosophy” until fairly recently sounded almost like an oxymoron, indeed, so much so that in modern curricula of the his- tory of philosophy the medieval period was barely mentioned, and even nowadays it is skipped by some philosophy departments, boldly leaping from ancient philosophy directly to the study of Descartes (ignoring about two thousand years of Western intellectual history). To be sure, this situation is happily changing. In the larger scheme of things this is prob- ably due to the fact that we live in a postmodern period, in which the grand, defining ideas of modernity itself have become at least questionable, if not discredited, as a result of mod- ern historical experience (think world wars, industrialized genocides, global exploitation of people and nature, the manipulative uses of “values,” ideologies and religions, etc.). This postmodern perspective, by revealing the various limitations of the “grand ideas” of mod- ernity, naturally prompts historical and philosophical reflection on their validity in history, and thus on their emergence from developments in the medieval period.
    [Show full text]
  • Triumphus Matris
    LES ENLUMINURES LES ENLUMINURES, LTD. Le Louvre des Antiquaires 2 Place du Palais-Royal 2970 North Lake Shore Drive 75001 Paris (France) Chicago, IL 60657 (USA) tel. +33 (0)1 42 60 15 58 • fax. +33 (0)1 40 15 00 25 tel. +773 929 5986 [email protected] fax. +773 528 3976 [email protected] [ORGANON]. PORPHYRY, Isagoge (transl. Boethius); ARISTOTLE. Categoriae (tr. Boethius); Liber peri hermenias (tr. Boethius); ANICIUS MANLIUS SEVERINUS BOETHIUS, Liber de divisione; De topicis differentiis; De categoricis syllogismis; ARISTOTLE, Liber topicorum; De sophisticis elenchis; Priora analytica (trs. Boethius); Posteriora analytica In Latin, decorated manuscript on parchment France, Paris, or Normandy(?), c. 1150-1200 and c. 1250-1300 173 ff., preceded and followed by modern paper flyleaves, composite manuscript, apparently complete (collation: i14 [8, with an added separate gathering of 6 inserted], ii-vi8, vii-x8, xi6, xii5 [of 6, first leaf of quire cancelled, with no apparent interruption of text sequence], xiii-xiv6, xv8, xvi-xix8, xx-xxii8), first part (ff. 1-54v) written in a very regular 12th century minuscule, remainder of manuscript written in a variety of tight and highly abridged protogothic or gothic bookhands, four written above-top-line, various hands, with at least five distinguishable (hand A, ff. 1-4v and ff. 11-54v; hand B, ff. 55-97; hand C, ff. 98-117v; hand D, ff. 118-172; hand E, ff. 5-10v [inserted in the middle of the first gathering]), in brown or black ink, six different textblocks each ruled to a different pattern of between 29 and 38 lines, prickings still visible, guide letters in the margin, paragraph marks in red, opening initials of pink or brown and pink, one larger decorated initial P in red and brown with face drawn in red in the infill (a tonsured monk?), diagrams in text or in margins (ff.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late Mediaeval Logic and Semantic Theory
    Thoughts, Words and Things: An Introduction to Late Mediaeval Logic and Semantic Theory Paul Vincent Spade Version 1.1: August 9, 2002 Copyright 2002 by Paul Vincent Spade Permission is hereby granted to copy this document in whole or in part for any purpose whatever, provided only that acknowledgment of copyright is given. The “dragon” that graces the cover of this volume has a story that goes with it. In the summer of 1980, I was on the teaching staff of the Summer Institute on Medieval Philosophy held at Cornell University under the direction of Nor- man Kretzmann and the auspices of the Council for Philosophical Studies and the National Endowment for the Humanities. While I was giving a series of lectures there (lectures that contribute to this volume, as it turns out), I went to my office one morning, and there under the door some anonymous wag from the Institute had slid the pen and ink drawing you see in the picture. It represents “Supposition” as a dragon, making a rude face at the viewer. The tail of the dragon is divided — not entirely accurately, as it turns out — into the various branches and subbranches of supposition. If the details are not alto- gether correct, the spirit is certainly understandable. A few years ago, I discovered that the anonymous artist was not altogether as original as I had at first supposed. While glancing one day — don’t ask why — through the charming A Coloring Book of the Middle Ages (San Francisco, Cal.: Bellerophon Books, 1969), I turned a page and was startled to find this very creature leering out at me! The inscrip- tions in the tail and at the bottom were not there, but otherwise it was the same creature! A note at the top of the page said “From the Treatise of Walter de Milemete, De Nobilitatibus Sapientiis et prudentiis Regum, Oxford, Christ Church Library, MS.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late Mediaeval Logic and Semantic Theory
    Thoughts, Words and Things: An Introduction to Late Mediaeval Logic and Semantic Theory Paul Vincent Spade Version 1.2: December 27, 2007 Thoughts, Words and Things: An Introduction to Late Mediaeval Logic and Semantic Theory by Paul Vincent Spade is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The “dragon” that graces the cover of this volume has a story that goes with it. In the summer of 1980, I was on the teaching staff of the Summer Institute on Medieval Philosophy held at Cornell University under the direction of Nor- man Kretzmann and the auspices of the Council for Philosophical Studies and the National Endowment for the Humanities. While I was giving a series of lectures there (lectures that contribute to this volume, as it turns out), I went to my office one morning, and there under the door some anonymous wag from the Institute had slid the pen and ink drawing you see in the picture. It represents “Supposition” as a dragon, making a rude face at the viewer. The tail of the dragon is divided — not entirely accurately, as it turns out — into the various branches and subbranches of supposition. If the details are not alto- gether correct, the spirit is certainly understandable. A few years ago, I discovered that the anonymous artist was not altogether as original as I had at first supposed. While glancing one day — don’t ask why — through the charming A Coloring Book of the Middle Ages (San Francisco, Cal.: Bellerophon Books, 1969), I turned a page and was startled to find this very creature leering out at me! The inscrip- tions in the tail and at the bottom were not there, but otherwise it was the same creature! A note at the top of the page said “From the Treatise of Walter de Milemete, De Nobilitatibus Sapientiis et prudentiis Regum, Oxford, Christ Church Library, MS.
    [Show full text]
  • MEDIEVALIA Vol
    MEDIEVALIA Vol. 16 (2013) Directors Secretari Almudena Blasco, Antonio Contreras, Alberto Reche (IEM) Daniel Rico (IEM) Redactors Joan Curbet (IEM), Sergi Grau Alejandro Martínez Giralt (UdG), (Fundación CIMA), Celia López Alcalde Katarzyna Krystyna Starczewska (IEM), (IEM), Josemi Lorenzo Arribas (IEM), Luciano José Vianna (IEM) Consell Avaluador Luigi Allegri (Univ. di Parma), Vicenç José Martínez Gázquez (IEM), Francesc Beltran Pepió (La Sapienza), Eduardo Massip (URV), Paolo Odorico (EHESS), Carrero (IEM), Manuel Castiñeiras Josep Pujol (IEM), Gisela Ripoll (UB), (IEM), Vincent Debiais (Univ. de Jesús Rodríguez Velasco (Columbia Poitiers), Manuel Pedro Ferreiro (Univ. Univ.), José Enrique Ruiz-Domènec Nova de Lisboa), Alexander Fidora (IEM), (IEM), Rebeca Sanmartín (UAM), Maricarmen Gómez Muntané (IEM), Harvey L. Sharrer (Univ. of California), Roberto Hofmeister Pich (PUCRS), Matthias Tischler (TU Dresden) Consell Assessor David Abulafia (Univ. of Cambridge), Paul Freedman (Univ. of Yale), Gabriella Airaldi (Univ. di Genova), Jane Hardie (Univ. of Sydney), José Carlos Alvar (Univ. de Genève), Stefan Hinojosa (Univ. d’Alacant), Herbert Andreescu (Univ. din Bucureşti), Martin Kessler (Johns Hopkins Univ.), Gábor Aurell (Univ. de Poitiers), Kathleen Klaniczay (CEU, Budapest), Mario Biddick (Univ. of Notre Dame), Franco Mancini (Univ. di Bologna), Jean-Claude Cardini (ISU, Firenze), Isabel Del Val Schmitt (EHESS), Jean Wirth (Univ. de (Univ. de Valladolid), Genève) Medievalia <http://revistes.uab.cat/medievalia> es una publicació de l’Institut d’Estudis Medievals (IEM), institut propi vinculat a la Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona i creat l’any 1973 i. L’objetiu de la revista és servir de mitjà de difusió d’investigacions i d’idees originals sobre l’Edat Mitajana des d’una perspectiva d’interciència.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Aquinas, Magister Ludi: the Relation of Medieval Logic and Theology
    JOSHUA P. HOCHSCHILD Thomas Aquinas, Magister Ludi: The Relation of Medieval Logic and Theology Ludus delectabilis est, et contemplatio sapientiae maximam delectationem habet. – Thomas Aquinas: Expositio libri Boetii De ebdomadibus, proemium I. INTRODUCTION Hermann Hesse’s The Glass Bead Game (Das Glasperlenspiel) is Aristotelian science fiction. Published in 1943, Hesse’s last, brooding, existential novel describes neither advanced technology nor new discoveries in natural science; instead, it imagines an advanced culture of philosophical study and learning, an aristocratic intellectual bulwark against utilitarian science and shallow mass media, which synthesized and developed the best habits of academy, monastery, conservatory and university – a kind of alternative-history neo-scholasticism. At the heart of this culture is a game – “the Glass Bead Game” – which makes it possible to carry out theoretical exploration and conversation, ritually but cre- atively, through the manipulation of highly symbolic glass beads. A move in the game is meaningful not only because of the beads’ individual meanings, but ad- ditionally because of the relation between the beads to each other in the game, and even more the relation between the play of the present game and that of past games. Moves, governed by elaborate and highly traditional rules, are thus not only assertions or questions but allusions to or variations on past moves, and part of a larger overall conversation about or exploration into the profoundest ideas and highest objects of contemplation. As such, the “game” is a means of the most refined and intense spiritual dis- cipline: It represented an elite, symbolic form of seeking for perfection, a sublime alchemy, an approach to that Mind which beyond all images and multiplicities is one within itself – in other words, to God… The symbols and formulas of the Glass Bead Game combined structurally, musically, and philosophically within the framework of a uni- 44 JOSHUA P.
    [Show full text]
  • Remarks on Nominalistic Roots of Modern Science
    O R G A N O N 4(1967) L’ANTIQUITÉ CLASSIQUE ET LES DÉBUTS DE LA SCIENCE MODERNE Jürgen Mittelstrass (German Federal RepuBlic) REMARKS ON NOMINALISTIC ROOTS OF MODERN SCIENCE In discussions dealing with the Beginning of modern science, i.e. of Galileo’s physics, the question continues to Be raised—especially since Pierre Duhem’s far-fetched antedating of this Beginning1—as to the part played in it By nominalism. Starting from the assumption, usually formulated none too precisely, that up to this very day modern physics is essentially nominalistic, an effort is Being made to estaBlish a link Between the nominalism of late Scholastic times and modern physics. In the following, I shall attempt to show how such a con­ nection, although very limited in scope, can indeed Be oBserved. To start with, here is a Brief comment on the historical pattern of nominalism as far as this now concerns us. As a philosophical theory of language, nominalism contests the assertion of the “realists” that the order of signum and res, as applied in the use of proper names, is valid also in the case of what is called universalia; that is—in modern wording—that to predicates (or to concepts, if the phonemic realization of predicates may Be ignored) there corresponds something still “distinguishaBle” from existing things. According to nominalistic interpretation these universals are (in a rather unfortunate termino­ logy, dictated By the adverse party) nothing But “mere names,” whose correlates in reality are again supposed to Be nothing But existing 1 Duhem started with an attempt to present Leonardo da Vinci as a decisive precursor of Galileo (Les Origines de la Statique, I—II, Paris 1905—1906).
    [Show full text]
  • The Education System (1)
    The Education System (1). Trivium. (Artes sermocinales. ) Grammar. Rhetoric. Dialectic /Logic . Quadrivium. (Artes reales / Artes physicae .) Arithmetic. Geometry. Astronomy. Music. Ancient sources. Varro (116-28 BC), Cassidorus (c.490-c.585), Boëthius (c.475-524). Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 2/42 The Education System (2). “Renaissances” of the Middle Ages. Carolingian Renaissance. Alcuin (735-804). Gottschalk and the first debate on double predestination. Johannes Scotus Eriugena (c.810-877). Ottonian Renaissance. Gerbert of Reims (later Pope Silvester II ; c.945-1003). Fulbert of Chartres (c.955-1028). Berengar of Tours (d.1088). Lanfranc (c.1005-1089). Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109). Renaissance of the XIIth century. Peter Abelard (1079-1142). John of Salisbury (c.1110-1180). The birth of the European University. Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 3/42 The Education System (3): A continuum? Gerbert of Reims (c.945-1003) Fulbert of Chartres (c.955-1028) j TT jt jjj TTT* Berengar of Tours Lanfranc (d.1088) (c.1005-1089) j jt jjj Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109) j jt jjj Anselm of Laon Jean Roscelin (c.1050-1117) (c.1045-c.1120) TTTT jj TTT* jt jjj William of Champeaux / Peter Abelard (c.1070-1121) (1079–1142) John of Salisbury (c.1110-1180) Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 4/42 Realism & Nominalism. Was not a issue in the XIth century (Garland the Computist). Roscelin; Abelard (XIIth century). Aristotelian distinction: Universal substances: Animal , Human . Particular substances: Socrates , Plato , Aristotle . Universals exists independent Realists. of the particulars. Problem. What is the ontological status of these universals? Universals exist only through Nominalists.
    [Show full text]