Stephen R. Grimm Curriculum Vitae

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stephen R. Grimm Curriculum Vitae Stephen R. Grimm Curriculum Vitae Associate Professor Office: 718-817-3282 Philosophy Department [email protected] Fordham University http://faculty.fordham.edu/sgrimm Bronx, NY 10458 Employment Fordham University: Associate Professor (2012—), Assistant Professor (2008—2012) • Principal Investigator, Varieties of Understanding: New Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy, and Theology Project. Joint Award from the John Templeton Foundation and Henry Luce Foundation. Amount: $4,240,000. Funding Period: July 2013 to June 2016. University of Montana: Assistant Professor (2006—2008) University of Notre Dame: Edward Sorin Postdoctoral Fellow (2005—2006) Education University of Notre Dame: Philosophy, Ph.D., 2005 • Dissertation Title: Understanding as an Epistemic Goal • Recipient of 2006 Eli J. and Helen Shaheen Graduate School Award for Outstanding Graduate Student in the Humanities at Notre Dame University of Toronto: Theology, M.A., 1996 Williams College: Philosophy and Art, B.A., 1993 Areas of Specialization Epistemology • Philosophy of Science Areas of Competence Ethics • Philosophy of Religion • Wittgenstein Publications Books 2 Explaining Understanding: New Essays in Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science. Eds. Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, & Sabine Ammon. New York: Routledge. Forthcoming. Articles “How Understanding People Differs From Understanding the Natural World.” Philosophical Issues (Noûs supplement). Forthcoming. “Understanding and Transparency.” In Explaining Understanding: New Essays in Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science. Eds. Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, & Sabine Ammon. New York: Routledge. Forthcoming. “The Logic of Mysticism.” European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion. Forthcoming. [special issue on mysticism] “Wisdom in Theology.” In The Oxford Handbook for the Epistemology of Theology. Eds. William Abraham and Fred Aquino. New York: Oxford University Press. Forthcoming. “The Value of Reflection.” In Performance Epistemology. Ed. Miguel Angel Fernandez. New York: Oxford University Press. Forthcoming. “Knowledge, Practical Interests, and Rising Tides.” In Epistemic Evaluation: Point and Purpose in Epistemology. Eds. John Greco and David Henderson. New York: Oxford University Press. Forthcoming. “Wisdom.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93: 139-154. (2015) “Understanding as Knowledge of Causes.” In Virtue Scientia: Essays in Philosophy of Science and Virtue Epistemology. Ed. Abrol Fairweather. Special issue of Synthese. (2014) “Getting it Right.” (with Kristoffer Ahlstrom) Philosophical Studies 166: 329-347. (2013) “The Value of Understanding.” Philosophy Compass 7: 103-117. (2012) “What is Interesting?” Logos and Episteme: An International Journal of Epistemology 2: 515-542. (2011) “On Intellectualism in Epistemology.” Mind 120: 705-733. (2011) “Understanding.” In The Routledge Companion to Epistemology. Eds. Duncan Pritchard and Sven Berneker. New York: Routledge. (2010) 3 “The Goal of Explanation.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 41: 337-344. (2010) “Understanding.” Oxford Bibliographies Online. New York: Oxford University Press. www.oxfordbibliographiesonline.com (2010) “Epistemic Normativity.” In The Value of Knowledge. Eds. Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard. New York: Oxford University Press. (2009) • Reprinted in Virtue Epistemology: MIT Readers in Contemporary Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (2012) “Reliability and The Sense of Understanding.” In Philosophical Perspectives on Scientific Understanding. Eds. Henk de Regt, Sabina Leonelli, and Kai Eigner. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press. (2009) “Epistemic Goals and Epistemic Values.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 725-744. (2008) “Explanatory Inquiry and the Need for Explanation.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59: 481-497. (2008) “Review Essay: Kvanvig’s The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding.” (with Michael DePaul). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 498-514. (2007) “Easy Cases and Value Incommensurability.” Ratio 20: 26-44. (2007) “Is Understanding a Species of Knowledge?” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 515-535. (2006) “Kant’s Argument for Radical Evil.” The European Journal of Philosophy 10: 160-177. (2002) “Ernest Sosa, Knowledge, and Understanding.” (With a response by Sosa). Philosophical Studies 106: 171-191. (2001) “Cardinal Newman, Reformed Epistemologist?” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 75: 497-522. (2001) Encyclopedia Entries “Understanding.” The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. 3rd Edition. Ed. Robert Audi. New York: Cambridge University Press. Forthcoming. 4 Book Reviews Review of The Nature and Value of Knowledge, by Duncan Pritchard, Allan Millar, and Adrian Haddock. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. (2011) Review of Aiming at Truth, by Nicholas Unwin. Mind, 118: 886-889. (2009) Works in Progress “Knowing How to Live Well.” In Knowledge Indeed. Eds. Stephen Hetherington and Clayton Littlejohn. Publisher TBD. New Essays in the Philosophy of Understanding. Ed. Stephen R. Grimm. Proposal in preparation for Oxford University Press. Varieties of Understanding: New Perspectives from Philosophy, Psychology, and Theology. [Collected papers from the Varieties of Understanding Capstone Conference.] Ed. Stephen R. Grimm. Proposal in preparation for Oxford University Press. Media Interviews “Understanding Understanding.” 3AM Magazine. April 2013. “Varieties of Understanding.” Williams College Magazine. Summer 2013. Presentations June 2015. “The Nature and Value of Understanding.” Varieties of Understanding Midpoint Conference. Fordham University. March 2015. “Nothing that is Genuinely Human Fails to Find an Echo: Vatican II at 100.” Vatican II at 50: The Post-Conciliar Generation Looks at the Next Half Century. Fordham University, Center for Religion and Culture. November 2014. “How Understanding Human Beings Differs from Understanding the Natural World.” Bucknell University, Philosophy Colloquium. October 2014. “Understanding and Transparency.” University of California, Berkeley; Concepts and Cognition Lab Colloquium. October 2014. Comments on James Brent, “Aquinas’s Three Replies to the Evidentialist 5 Objection.” American Catholic Philosophical Association. Washington, D.C. May 2014. “The Logic of Mysticism.” Mysticism Conference. Moscow, Russia. Fall 2014. “Wisdom & Theology.” Faith & Culture Lecture, Villanova University March 2014. “Understanding and Transparency.” Towards an Epistemology of Understanding: Rethinking Justification Conference. University of Berne. Fall 2013—Fall 2014. “What is Wisdom?” Wake Forest University, Philosophy Colloquium; Holy Cross, Philosophy Colloquium; Middlebury College, Philosophy Colloquium; Williams College, Philosophy Colloquium; Walton Lecture on Science, Religion, and Philosophy, Fordham University August 2013. “Wisdom and Its Value” 23rd World Congress of Philosophy. Athens, Greece. February 2013. “Understanding as Knowledge of Causes.” Felician College, Philosophy Colloquium. May 2012. “The Value of Reflection.” Virtue Theory: Ethics vs. Epistemology, East vs. West Conference. Soochow University, Taiwan. May 2012. “Getting it Right” (with Kristoffer Ahlstrom). Aims of Inquiry and Cognition Conference. University of Edinburgh. May 2012. “The Value of Reflection.” Epistemology Research Group. University of Edinburgh. April 2012. “Idealization and Understanding.” Fordham Philosophical Society Spring Symposium. Fordham University. April 2012. “The Value of Reflection.” Epistemology Brown Bag Series. Northwestern University. October 2011. “Comments on Pruss and Dougherty.” Georgetown/Baylor/Notre Dame Philosophy of Religion Conference. Georgetown University. June 2011. “Understanding as Knowledge of Causes.” Knowledge, Understanding, and Wisdom Conference. Bled, Slovenia. October 2010. “Craigian Insights on Epistemic Evaluation.” The Point and Purpose of Epistemic Evaluation Conference. University of Nebraska. 6 June 2010. “Which Knowledge is of Most Worth?” Ecology of Knowledge Conference. University of Edinburgh. April 2010. “Human Cloning: Pro and Con.” Fordham President’s Spring Visit Lecture for Newly Admitted Students. March 2010. “What’s Interesting?” Society of Christian Philosophers, Eastern Division Meeting. Wake Forest University. October 2009. “The Epistemic Point of View.” Loyola Marymount University, Los Angeles. October 2009. “Knowledge, Practical Interests, and Rising Tides.” University of Edinburgh. October 2009. “The Nature of Knowledge.” University of Edinburgh Philosophy Society. October 2009. “Knowledge, Practical Interests, and Rising Tides.” University of Glasgow. June 2009. “Knowledge, Practical Interests, and Rising Tides.” Virtue and Value in Epistemology Conference. Bled, Slovenia. March 2009. “Epistemic Normativity and Common Goods.” Normativity and Culture Conference. University of Antwerp. March 2009. “Understanding and Epistemic Goodness.” Epistemic Goodness Conference. University of Oklahoma. November 2007. “How Knowledge and Practical Interests are Related.” American Catholic Philosophical Association. Marquette University. October 2007. “Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge.” Northwest Philosophy Conference. Lewis & Clark College. August 2007. “Pritchard on Understanding and Epistemic Value.” Value of Knowledge Conference. Free University, Amsterdam. August 2007. “The End of Orthodox Epistemology?: How Knowledge and Practical Interests are Related.” Value of Knowledge Conference. Free University,
Recommended publications
  • Weighing Falling Bodies. Galileo's Thought Experiment in The
    Weighing Falling Bodies. Galileo’s Thought Experiment in the Development of his Dynamical Thinking. Maarten Van Dyck Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science Centre for History of Science Ghent University [email protected] {The author is research assistant of the Fund for Scientific Research (FWO) – Flanders} 1 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to thank Tim De Mey, without whom I would have never plunged so deep in Galileo’s thought experiment; Paolo Palmieri, who made the invaluable suggestion that I should have a look at the postils to Rocco , and whose comments on a first version of this paper helped to significantly improve both its contents and presentation; and Sabina Leonelli for her much appreciated assistance in translating the Italian fragments from the postils to Rocco. 2 CONTENTS 1. Introduction: The intelligibility of dynamics – the dynamics of intelligibility PART I – Understanding weight as a dynamic factor: Ambiguities 2. La bilancetta : Understanding mixtures and transforming gravities 2.a Solving the crown problem 2.b Balancing mixtures and speeds 3. De motu : Attempts at an Archimedean natural philosophy 3.a The dynamics of De motu 3.b From equal volumes to unit volumes 4. De motu : Introducing the thought experiment 4.a A hidden assumption 4.b The dynamical conundrum 5. Discorso : The impotence of specific gravity as a dynamic factor 5.a Moment and absolute weight 5.b Moment and specific weight 5.c The extrapolation argument PART II – Understanding weight as a dynamic factor: Towards a resolution 6. Postille a Roco : Rethinking the thought experiment 6.a Re-presenting the thought experiment 6.b Resolving the dynamical conundrum 7.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Later Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend
    Durham E-Theses Pluralism and the 'Problem of Reality' in the Later Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend KIDD, IAN,JAMES How to cite: KIDD, IAN,JAMES (2010) Pluralism and the 'Problem of Reality' in the Later Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/864/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 Kidd Pluralism and the ‘Problem of Reality’ in the Later Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend Abstract Feyerabend’s later philosophy was a sustained defence of cultural and epistemic diversity. After Against Method (1975) Feyerabend argued that his rejection of methodological monism challenged the presumed unity and superiority of scientific knowledge and practices. His later philosophy was therefore dedicated to a reassessment of the merits of a wide range of ‘non-scientific’ traditions present throughout non-Western indigenous cultures.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding the Progress of Science
    Understanding the Progress of Science C. D. McCoy 30 May 2018 The central problem of epistemology has always been and still is the problem of the growth of knowledge. And the growth of knowledge can be studied best by studying the growth of scientific knowledge. —(Popper, 2002b, xix) Merely fact-minded sciences make merely fact-minded people. —(Husserl, 1970, 6) The growth of human knowledge is realized most dramatically in the growth of scientific knowledge. What we have come to know through science about the workings of our human bodies and the workings of heavenly bodies, among much else, astounds, especially in comparison to our accumulating knowledge of the commonplace and everyday. Impressed by the evident epistemic progress made by science, many philosophers during the 20th century thought that studying how scientific knowledge increases is a crucial task of epistemological inquiry, and, indeed, the progress of science has been a topic of considerable interest. Yet, eventually, late in the century, attention waned and for the most part shifted to other tasks. Recently, however, a provocative article by Bird has re-ignited philosophical interest in the topic of scientific progress (Bird, 2007). Bird criticizes what he takes to have been the most prominent accounts advanced in the 20th century and presses for what he views as a venerable but lately overlooked one. He claims that realist philosophers of science have often presumed that truth is the goal of science and progress to be properly characterized by an accu- mulation of truth or truths, and notes that anti-realists have often rejected truth as a goal of science and characterized progress in terms of, among other things, “problem-solving effectiveness.”1 He criticizes the former for overlooking the relevance of justification to progress and the latter for giving up on truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century
    GEORGEMASON UNIVERSITY UNIVERSllY LIBRARIES THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF GERMAN PHILOSOPHY IN THE NINETEENTH CENTURY ............................................................................................................................................................... Edited by MICHAEL N. FORSTER and KRISTIN GJESDAL OXFORD U N lV ERSITY PR ESS OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Great Clarendon Street , Oxford, o:u 6oP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a depart ment of the t:niver,11r of Chford It furthers the University's obJective of excellence m n·s~·arch, s.:hol.1r,h1r , . and edu cation by publishing wor ldwide . Oxford is a regmereJ trade mJrk ,,t Oxford University Press m the IJK and in certain other countnc, © The several contribu tors 1015 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition pub!t,hed 10 2015 Impress ion 1 All rights reserved . No part of this publication may be rerroJuceJ. stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any mea ns, without the prior permiss ion in writing of Oxford University Press, or as npreHl y pcrm1tteJ by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the arpropr1ate repr oi:raph1,, rights organi zation. Enquiries concerning reproduction outsi de th e swre of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford tJ111vers1ty Pre,,, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impo se this same condit ion on any .icqu irt'r Published in the United States of America by Oxford University l're,s 198 Madison Avenue , New York, NY wo16, United StJ tes of Amer tCJ British Library Cataloguing in Puhlication l>Jta Data availa ble Library of Congress Control Numher: 2014946121 ISBN 978- 0 -19-969654 - 3 Printed and boun d by CPI Gro up (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CRO 4YY Links to thud party websites are provided by Oxford in !(OOJ faith anJ for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 What's So Special About Model Organisms?
    ORE Open Research Exeter TITLE What makes a model organism? AUTHORS Leonelli, Sabina; Ankeny, Rachel A. JOURNAL Endeavour DEPOSITED IN ORE 15 January 2015 This version available at http://hdl.handle.net/10871/20864 COPYRIGHT AND REUSE Open Research Exeter makes this work available in accordance with publisher policies. A NOTE ON VERSIONS The version presented here may differ from the published version. If citing, you are advised to consult the published version for pagination, volume/issue and date of publication What’s So Special About Model Organisms? Rachel A. Ankeny* and Sabina Leonelli *Corresponding author: email: [email protected] , mailing address: School of History and Politics, Napier 423, University of Adelaide, Adelaide 5005 SA, Australia, telephone: +61-8-8303-5570, fax: +61-8-8303-3443. Abstract This paper aims to identify the key characteristics of model organisms that make them a specific type of model within the contemporary life sciences: in particular, we argue that the term “model organism” does not apply to all organisms used for the purposes of experimental research. We explore the differences between experimental and model organisms in terms of their material and epistemic features, and argue that it is essential to distinguish between their representational scope and representational target . We also examine the characteristics of the communities who use these two types of models, including their research goals, disciplinary affiliations, and preferred practices to show how these have contributed to the conceptualization of a model organism. We conclude that model organisms are a specific subgroup of organisms that have been standardized to fit an integrative and comparative mode of research, and that must be clearly distinguished from the broader class of experimental organisms.
    [Show full text]
  • ICOHTEC NEWSLETTER O N 176, December 2020
    ICOHTEC NEWSLETTER No 176, December 2020 www.icohtec.org Sound To Light System Sound Operated Lamp Switch Circuit The first real dedicated disco lights were invented in about 1968 when someone decided to control lighting using electronics (Transistors and Thyristors in those days, no silicon chips) the idea was to flash lamps to different frequencies, originally three channels. Basically one lamp would flash in time with the Bass frequency, one in time with the Middle and one in time with the Treble. For the first time Sound To Light was born. The sound of the light: https://youtu.be/vkVPXpSE_Us Newsletter of the International Committee for the History of Technology - ICOHTEC Editor: Francesco Gerali, The University of Oklahoma School of Library and Information Studies. Norman, OK, United States. Mail to [email protected] Newsletter of the International Committee for the History of Technology - ICOHTEC Editor: Francesco Gerali, 2020 IEEE Pugh Visiting Scholar, IEEE History Center, NJ, United States. Mail to [email protected] I. ICOHTEC I.1 26TH INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS OF HISTORY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY AND THE 48TH SYMPOSIUM OF ICOHTEC GO ONLINE I.2 MAURICE DAUMAS PRIZE - ICOHTEC’S ARTICLE PRIZE I.3 TURRIANO ICOHTEC PRIZE 2021 - CALL FOR SUBMISSIONS I.4 ICON II. PRIZES III. JOURNALS IV. E-SCHOL@RSHIP IN THE V. OPEN ACCESS VI. CALLS FOR MANUSCRIPTS VII. CALLS FOR PAPERS VIII. PLASTICIDADE, UMA HISTÓRIA DOS PLÁSTICOS EM PORTUGAL, A HISTORY OF PLASTICS IN PORTUGAL IX. JOBS, POSTDOCTORAL POSITIONS, AND RESEARCH FELLOWSHIPS X. JOIN ICOHTEC 1 I. ICOHTEC I.1 26th International Congress of History of Science and Technology and the 48th Symposium of ICOHTEC go online Dear Colleagues and Friends, Due to the risks of a real meeting, the organizers of the 26th International Congress of History of Science and Technology, ICHST (25 – 31 July 2021), decided to organize the conference online.
    [Show full text]
  • Arc of the Data Scientific Universe Leslie HDSR
    The Arc of the Data Scientific Universe A comment on Sabina Leonelli’s “Data Science in Times of Pand(dem)ic” David Leslie, The Alan Turing Institute [email protected] To be published in Harvard Data Science Review (Winter 2021) Abstract In this paper explore the scaffolding of normative assumptions that supports Sabina Leonelli’s implicit appeal to the values of epistemic integrity and the global public good that conjointly animate the ethos of responsible and sustainable data work in the context of COVID-19. Drawing primarily on the writings of sociologist Robert K. Merton, the thinkers of the Vienna Circle, and Charles Sanders Peirce, I make some of these assumptions explicit by telling a longer story about the evolution of social thinking about the normative structure of science from Merton’s articulation of his well-known norms—those of universalism, communism, organized skepticism, and disinterestedness—to the present. I show that while Merton’s norms and his intertwinement of these with the underlying mechanisms of democratic order provide us with an especially good starting point to explore and clarify the commitments and values of science, Leonelli’s broader, more context-responsive, and more holistic vision of the epistemic integrity of data scientific understanding, and her discernment of the global and biospheric scope of its moral-practical reach, move beyond Merton’s schema in ways that effectively draw upon important critiques. Stepping past Merton, I argue that a combination of situated universalism, methodological pluralism, strong objectivity, and unbounded communalism must guide the responsible and sustainable data work of the future.
    [Show full text]
  • Aspects of Theory-Ladenness in Data-Intensive Science1
    Aspects of theory-ladenness in data-intensive science1 Wolfgang Pietsch2 Munich Center for Technology in Society, TU München, Munich, Germany Abstract Recent claims, mainly from computer scientists, concerning a largely automated and model- free data-intensive science have been countered by critical reactions from a number of philosophers of science. The debate suffers from a lack of detail in two respects, regarding (i) the actual methods used in data-intensive science and (ii) the specific ways in which these methods presuppose theoretical assumptions. I examine two widely-used algorithms, classificatory trees and non-parametric regression, and argue that these are theory-laden in an external sense, regarding the framing of research questions, but not in an internal sense concerning the causal structure of the examined phenomenon. With respect to the novelty of data-intensive science, I draw an analogy to exploratory as opposed to theory-directed experimentation. 1. Introduction Over the past decade, computer scientists have claimed that a new scientific methodology has become possible through advances in information technology (e.g. Gray 2007). This approach is supposed to be data-driven, strongly inductive, and relatively theory-independent. The epistemology of such data-intensive science has recently emerged as a novel topic in philosophy of science. Generally, the reactions have been rather critical, often referring to the more or less trivial observation that some kind of theory-ladenness always occurs in scientific research. But, as I will argue, this means throwing the baby out with the bathwater, since interesting shifts in the role of theory can indeed be observed when examining specific methods employed in data-intensive science.
    [Show full text]
  • Academic Philosopher of Science and Information Sabina Leonelli
    DEPARTMENT OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY STUDIES STS Careers Podcast – Dr Emma Tobin talks to former BSc History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Science student, and current Professor of Philosophy and History of Science at the University of Exeter, Sabina Leonelli. Sabina graduated from the BSc in History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Science in 2000, before completing an MSc at LSE, going on to work as a research assistant to Hasok Chang at the Centre for the Philosophy of Natural and Social Science. She joined the University of Exeter in 2009, where she works to this day. ET Welcome to the STS Careers Podcast series. I’m Dr Emma Tobin, a philosopher of science here at STS, and I’m joined today by Dr Sabina Leonelli, who is a lecturer in the department of Sociology and Philosophy at the University of Exeter. Hi Sabina. SL Hi Emma. ET So thanks for joining us today in advance of your research seminar here at the department. What we wanted to do today is talk a little bit about careers in academia and ask you a little bit about your career path, how it went, some of the problems that you faced along the way and so on… and obviously some of the successes that you gained along the way. Can you tell us briefly what your career path has been. You started, obviously, with us as one of our undergraduate students here at STS. SL Sure. Right after that I was already thinking – I had a very strong inclination to do a PhD.
    [Show full text]
  • Program Booklet
    16th International Congress on Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science and Technology Bridging across academic cultures Faculty of Architecture, Czech Technical University in Prague Prague, Czech Republic 5–10 August 2019 Words of Welcome from the DLMPST/IUHPST Dear Logicians and Philosophers of Science, On behalf of the Division of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science and Technology of the International Union of History and Philosophy of Science and Technology (DLMPST/IUHPST), we should like to welcome all fellow researchers and scholars in our fields to the XVI Congress on Logic, Methodology, and Philoso- phy of Science and Technology (CLMPST) and look forward to your joining us in Prague in August 2019. Our fields, logic and the philosophy of science and technology, traditionally form a nexus between disciplines, equally at home in the sciences, the humanities and the social sciences. As a consequence, many logicians and philosophers of science fre- quently act as mediators between disciplinary traditions and serve as translators of mutually unintelligible academic vernaculars. Thus the theme of the 2019 congress, “Bridging across academic cultures”, is central to the experience of many among us. The theme refers not only to the aforementioned academic cultures, so forcefully evoked in C. P. Snow’s 1959 Rede lecture, “The Two Cultures”, which celebrates its 60th anniversary in the year of our congress, but also to the highly topical cultural dif- ferences between various countries and regions around the globe. As the global repre- sentative of our fields, DLMPST/IUHPST seeks to enrich our scientific dialogue by including the voices of those traditionally underrepresented in our academic fields, be it due to geography, culture, ethnicity, or gender.
    [Show full text]
  • SPSP2016 Program
    6th Biennial Conference of the Society for Philosophy of Science in Practice (SPSP) Rowan 2016 OpenConf Peer Review & Conference Management System Thursday, 16 June 2016 9:30-14:00 Pre-Conference Workshop: Empirical Methodology for Philosophy of Science (Enterprise 409) 19:00-22:00 Pre-Conference Informal Gathering (Landmark Americana Tap & Grill) Friday, 17 June 2016 8:30-9:00 Continental Breakfast & Coffee (Eynon Anteroom) 9:00-10:10 Plenary I - Julie Nelson, "Critiquing the Foundations of Economics, and Why It Matters" (Eynon Ballroom) Session Chair: Joe Rouse 10:10-10:30 Coffee Break (Eynon Anteroom) 10:30-12:00 CONCURRENT SESSIONS I Symposium - Contributed Contributed Symposium - Contributed Repertoires: Papers - Papers - Philosophy of Papers - Dynamics of Instruments Issues in the Autism Diverse Scientific and Data Social Session Chair: Modeling Collaboration Session Chair: Sciences Abigail Gosselin Practices in the Life Mieke Boon Session Chair: Session Session Chair: Sciences On The Michael Stuart Description: Emmanuele Ratti Jami L. Session Chair: Application Of Ontological Animal Models Of Anderson; Ruth Hanne Andersen Science To Investigations Pain And The J. Sample; Susan Session Science Itself: And Social Puzzle Of V. H. Castro Description: Chemistry, Scientific Practice Similarity Self Identities Sabina Leonelli; Instruments, And Simon Lohse Nina Atanasova And Self Rachel Ankeny The Scientific Bias And Social Experimentation Labor Process Diagnoses The Functions Of Science On Analogue George Borg Jami L. Anderson Repertoires In Experiments Models Does Autism Scientific The Evolution Of Sharon Crasnow Susan Sterrett Spectrum Research Instruments For Using Philosophy There And Back Disorder Have A Rachel Ankeny; Empirical Of Statistics To Again: Gender? Sabina Leonelli Investigation: Make Progress In Comparative Choosing Ruth J.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Sabina Leonelli's Data-Centric Biology
    Manuscript Copyright The Philosophy of Science Association 2018. Preprint (not copyedited or formatted). Please use DOI when citing or quoting. DOI: 10.1086/697732 Sabina Leonelli, Data-Centric Biology: A Philosophical Study. Chicago: University of Chicago Press (2016), 281 pp., $35.00 (paperback). Beckett Sterner School of Life Sciences Arizona State University E-mail: [email protected] Introduction The word “data” is everywhere in current discussions of science. How we store and share things people label “data” has become a central concern for the Open Science movement, for example, and the National Science Foundation and National Institutes of Health have invested billions of dollars in the creation of publicly accessible databases as a major new source of intellectual capital in science and industry. What is new here? Has there been a shift in what “data” means that is key to understanding the future of science? Sabina Leonelli’s new book, Data-Centric Biology: A Philosophical Study, argues for an important and fruitful answer outside the comfort zone of many philosophers. Along the way, she also delivers a range of valuable insights into the expanding efforts to standardize, automate, and communicate how scientists handle, share, reproduce, interpret, and store data. From the start, Leonelli rejects the idea that we can understand the significance of data for science in terms of intrinsic properties data possess as material traces of past processes. Similarly, the changes we’re seeing in science aren’t driven simply by revolutionary technologies or methods. “The real source of innovation in current biology is the attention paid to data handling and dissemination practices and the ways in which such practices mirror economic and political modes of interaction and decision making” (1).
    [Show full text]