Causal Explanation Under Indeterminism: a Sampling Approach

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Causal Explanation Under Indeterminism: a Sampling Approach Causal Explanation Under Indeterminism: A Sampling Approach Christopher A Merck and Samantha Kleinberg Stevens Institute of Technology Hoboken NJ Abstract However if we want to tell an individual why their blood sugar is low at 4 PM, we need to be able to automatically One of the key uses of causes is to explain why things happen. determine that it is due to the race they ran the day before Explanations of specific events, like an individual’s heart at- tack on Monday afternoon or a particular car accident, help plus their current insulin dosing. Runs from a week ago are assign responsibility and inform our future decisions. Com- not important here, but neither is a brief jog that morning. putational methods for causal inference make use of the vast To accurately and automatically explain events, we need amounts of data collected by individuals to better understand to handle both continuous time and state (e.g. glucose level), their behavior and improve their health. However, most meth- and go beyond only looking at whether an event happens and ods for explanation of specific events have provided theo- instead identify causes that change when and how the event retical approaches with limited applicability. In contrast we happens. Perhaps an individual had a genetic disposition to- make two main contributions: an algorithm for explanation ward lung cancer, but smoking led to diagnosis at a much that calculates the strength of token causes, and an evaluation earlier age than otherwise would have happened. It may based on simulated data that enables objective comparison be that two arsonists individually didn’t change whether a against prior methods and ground truth. We show that the approach finds the correct relationships in classic test cases fire happened (since either would have brought it about), but (causal chains, common cause, and backup causation) and in they increased the intensity of the fire and prevented it from a realistic scenario (explaining hyperglycemic episodes in a being extinguished. simulation of type 1 diabetes). In this work, we show how to compute answers to coun- terfactual queries in continuous-time systems using proba- bility trajectories. We then show how to test whether one Introduction event changes the probability, time, or intensity of another The past two decades have seen significant progress in com- event and compute quantitative strengths for these relation- putational discovery of causal relationships at the popula- ships. We first evaluate our method in a continuous-time tion level. Given a database of medical records, we can simulation of billiard ball collisions, showing that it rejects find causal relationships between variables like medications, spurious correlations when there is a common cause, finds lifestyle, and disease. Yet while causal inference can tell us hastening despite probability lowering in cases of backup what causes heart failure in general, it cannot tell us that causation, and identifies the most direct relationships in a specific patient’s heart failure is caused by their thyroid causal chains. Finally, we use it to explain a hypoglycemic disfunction rather than their uncontrolled diabetes — that is episode in a simulation of Type 1 Diabetes, demonstrating the role of causal explanation. One of the core approaches the technique’s readiness for real-world use. to explanation is based on counterfactuals, which capture that without the cause the effect would not have happened. Related Work However, this approach and other solutions have been pri- Causal explanation has been studied in philosophy, com- marily theoretical and since we only see what actually hap- puter science, and other fields including law (determining pened, it is difficult to determine what would have happened fault and culpability), medicine (diagnosing individuals to had things been different. Since the solutions to explana- identify the cause of their symptoms), and software engi- tion have been mainly theoretical, computational methods neering (finding causes of program bugs). We focus on re- for explanation have lagged behind those for inference. viewing the work in the first two areas since they provide The primary shortcoming of existing explanation meth- insight into what constitutes a causal explanation and how ods is their handling of time. Methods either ignore event we can realistically find these. timing entirely (e.g. Bayesian networks) or add time ad-hoc (e.g. dynamic Bayesian networks) at the expense of com- Philosophy putational complexity and large amounts of required input. We draw inspiration from two approaches to causal explana- Copyright c 2015, Association for the Advancement of Artificial tion, or token causality, that aim to evaluate or quantify how Intelligence (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. much of a difference a cause made to its effect. The first approach, due to Eells (1991), looks at the prob- to provide causal explanations automatically. Consider a ability of the effect over time (its probability trajectory) and model that shows that smoking causes lung cancer. A user examines how this changes after the cause happens up un- must interpret what it means for smoking to be true for an in- til the time of the effect. For example, if the probability dividual and which instances are relevant. Some issues with of hypoglycemia is raised after a run, and remains high un- the approach can be resolved by introducing variables to til hypoglycemia actually happens, then it is because of the model time (cf. the revised rock throwing model of (Halpern run. The probability trajectory approach explicitly incorpo- 2014)), but this becomes more difficult in cases like finding rates the timing of events, but it requires selecting so-called why a person’s blood glucose is raised since people tend to background contexts to hold fixed. This requires extensive give too much credence to recent events in causal explana- background knowledge that we normally do not have, mak- tion. As a result, the approach is susceptible to the same ing it difficult to translate into a computable model. biases as human reasoning, and it has only been evaluated Counterfactual methods, such as the concept of counter- conceptually. factual dependence introduced by Lewis (1973), stipulate One of the few computational methods for explanation that a cause is something without whose presence the effect that has been implemented and evaluated on simulated data would not have occurred. An event B is said to be caused by encodes the processes underlying relationships with logical A if both A and B occur in the actual world but B does not formulas (Dash, Voortman, and De Jongh 2013), links these occur in the not-A world most similar to the actual world. with a Bayesian network (BN), and then finds the most likely Despite the intuitive appeal of this approach, it is not directly path through the structure to the effect. However, this ap- reducible to an algorithm because the similarity function is proach does not explicitly model the timing of events and not specified by the theory. Furthermore, the main coun- cannot handle cases where multiple causes are responsible terfactual methods cannot handle overdetermination (when for an effect. Rather the approach finds only the most likely multiple causes occur). If a person who smokes is exposed causal sequence. Further, it does not distinguish between to asbestos, each factor individually may be enough to bring the significance of each component of the sequence. An- about lung cancer, leading to no counterfactual dependence. other logic-based approach (Kleinberg 2012) can handle the Yet it may be that exposure to both risk factors led to a more case of multiple causes, but it aims to rank the significance aggressive case of cancer or made it happen sooner than it of causes rather than test counterfactual queries. Methods otherwise would have (thus the cause changed the way in for fault detection (Poole 1994; Lunze and Schiller 1999; which cancer occurred). Paul (1998) and Lewis (2000) later Chao, Yang, and Liu 2001) aim to find why a system is extended the counterfactual theory to capture these types of behaving incorrectly, but are computationally complex and changes, though without a way of quantifying the similarity rely on an accurate mechanistic model. Finally, the causal between events, these approaches remained incomputable. impact method of Brodersen et al. (2015) computes the ef- We take inspiration from both of these approaches, us- fect of an intervention (advertising campaign) on a contin- ing change in probability to find relations such as because uous variable (market response), but requires a specified al- of and despite (making an event that actually occurs more ternative to the intervention rather than supporting general or less likely, respectively), and changes in timing (hasten- counterfactual queries. ing, delaying) and manner (intensifying, attenuating) to cap- ture other types of difference-making. This lets us find that Motivating Example while an event may have been inevitable, and a cause made As a running example, we discuss how to explain changes in no change to whether it occurred, it can still change when blood glucose (BG) of a person with type 1 diabetes mellitus and how it happens. For example, if we have a continuous (T1DM). This is challenging, since many factors affect BG variable that assesses severity of cancer, we can test how and can do so many hours after they occur. For example, much this is changed by each exposure in the prior exam- moderate exercise can lead to heightened insulin sensitivity ple. Similarly, a genetic predisposition may make cancer for up to 22 hours (Dalla Man, Breton, and Cobelli 2009). extremely likely, but an environmental exposure may bring Being able to find this and tell an individual why they have it about much earlier. By looking at changes in probability, low blood glucose (hypoglycemia) can help them prevent timing, and intensity, we can capture these differences.
Recommended publications
  • Indeterminism in Physics and Intuitionistic Mathematics
    Indeterminism in Physics and Intuitionistic Mathematics Nicolas Gisin Group of Applied Physics, University of Geneva, 1211 Geneva 4, Switzerland (Dated: November 5, 2020) Most physics theories are deterministic, with the notable exception of quantum mechanics which, however, comes plagued by the so-called measurement problem. This state of affairs might well be due to the inability of standard mathematics to “speak” of indeterminism, its inability to present us a worldview in which new information is created as time passes. In such a case, scientific determinism would only be an illusion due to the timeless mathematical language scientists use. To investigate this possibility it is necessary to develop an alternative mathematical language that is both powerful enough to allow scientists to compute predictions and compatible with indeterminism and the passage of time. We argue that intuitionistic mathematics provides such a language and we illustrate it in simple terms. I. INTRODUCTION I have always been amazed by the huge difficulties that my fellow physicists seem to encounter when con- templating indeterminism and the highly sophisticated Physicists are not used to thinking of the world as in- circumlocutions they are ready to swallow to avoid the determinate and its evolution as indeterministic. New- straightforward conclusion that physics does not neces- ton’s equations, like Maxwell’s and Schr¨odinger’s equa- sarily present us a deterministic worldview. But even tions, are (partial) differential equations describing the more surprising to me is the attitude of most philoso- continuous evolution of the initial condition as a func- phers, especially philosophers of science. Indeed, most tion of a parameter identified with time.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on Freedom of the Will: Not Determinism, Yet Not Indeterminism
    Wittgenstein on Freedom of the Will: Not Determinism, Yet Not Indeterminism Thomas Nadelhoffer This is a prepublication draft. This version is being revised for resubmission to a journal. Abstract Since the publication of Wittgenstein’s Lectures on Freedom of the Will, his remarks about free will and determinism have received very little attention. Insofar as these lectures give us an opportunity to see him at work on a traditional—and seemingly intractable—philosophical problem and given the voluminous secondary literature written about nearly every other facet of Wittgenstein’s life and philosophy, this neglect is both surprising and unfortunate. Perhaps these lectures have not attracted much attention because they are available to us only in the form of a single student’s notes (Yorick Smythies). Or perhaps it is because, as one Wittgenstein scholar put it, the lectures represent only “cursory reflections” that “are themselves uncompelling." (Glock 1996: 390) Either way, my goal is to show that Wittgenstein’s views about freedom of the will merit closer attention. All of these arguments might look as if I wanted to argue for the freedom of the will or against it. But I don't want to. --Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures on Freedom of the Will Since the publication of Wittgenstein’s Lectures on Freedom of the Will,1 his remarks from these lectures about free will and determinism have received very little attention.2 Insofar as these lectures give us an opportunity to see him at work on a traditional—and seemingly intractable— philosophical problem and given the voluminous secondary literature written about nearly every 1 Wittgenstein’s “Lectures on Freedom of the Will” will be abbreviated as LFW 1993 in this paper (see bibliography) since I am using the version reprinted in Philosophical Occasions (1993).
    [Show full text]
  • Is the Cosmos Random?
    IS THE RANDOM? COSMOS QUANTUM PHYSICS Einstein’s assertion that God does not play dice with the universe has been misinterpreted By George Musser Few of Albert Einstein’s sayings have been as widely quot- ed as his remark that God does not play dice with the universe. People have naturally taken his quip as proof that he was dogmatically opposed to quantum mechanics, which views randomness as a built-in feature of the physical world. When a radioactive nucleus decays, it does so sponta- neously; no rule will tell you when or why. When a particle of light strikes a half-silvered mirror, it either reflects off it or passes through; the out- come is open until the moment it occurs. You do not need to visit a labora- tory to see these processes: lots of Web sites display streams of random digits generated by Geiger counters or quantum optics. Being unpredict- able even in principle, such numbers are ideal for cryptography, statistics and online poker. Einstein, so the standard tale goes, refused to accept that some things are indeterministic—they just happen, and there is not a darned thing anyone can do to figure out why. Almost alone among his peers, he clung to the clockwork universe of classical physics, ticking mechanistically, each moment dictating the next. The dice-playing line became emblemat- ic of the B side of his life: the tragedy of a revolutionary turned reaction- ary who upended physics with relativity theory but was, as Niels Bohr put it, “out to lunch” on quantum theory.
    [Show full text]
  • PA As a Stochastic Process
    Anti-Essentialism in Public Administration Conference A decentering tendency has undermined the foundations of public administration theory Fort Lauderdale, FL March 2-3, 2007 Theorizing Public Administration as a Stochastic Process Catherine Horiuchi University of San Francisco Working Paper: Not for attribution or citation with author’s permission Abstract The capacity of information networks to capture and manipulate ever-larger streams of globally acquired, real-time data accelerates fragmentation of traditional public administration protocols, away from managing stable states toward temporary and permeable framing of governmental and corporate interests. Technologies simultaneously provide historic opportunities for dissent, individualism, and small-d democratic movements. Intermittent, overlapping governance – characterized by private government, small wars, state failures, and opportunistic shifts of power and capital from public stewardship to private parties – results in ideological or pragmatic retreats from and progressions of institutional boundaries. Ephemeral balances rather than negotiated long-term settlements demark the edges of public and private. This fluidity of realms increasingly affects the duration and allocation of administrative responsibilities between formerly firmly edged divisions of local, state, and national governments. The assumption of a static state in public administration theory does not hold. Government becomes a metaphorical fluid, an eddy that retains its shape more or less, long enough to become an object of analysis and action. The new assumption of administrative fluidity invokes a world of measurement estimating impacts of partially ordered and partially stochastic events. Sensemaking derives from sophisticated evaluative and probabilistic analyses. Traditional construction of the field with its assumption of durable governmental operations may no longer be a best-fit theory for multi-layered, ephemeral states.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Mechanics and Free Will: Counter−Arguments
    Quantum mechanics and free will: counter−arguments Martín López−Corredoira Astronomisches Institut der Universitaet Basel, Venusstrasse 7, CH−4102−Binningen, Switzerland E−mail: [email protected] Abstract Since quantum mechanics (QM) was formulated, many voices have claimed this to be the basis of free will in the human beings. Basically, they argue that free will is possible because there is an ontological indeterminism in the natural laws, and that the mind is responsible for the wave function collapse of matter, which leads to a choice among the different possibilities for the body. However, I defend the opposite thesis, that free will cannot be defended in terms of QM. First, because indeterminism does not imply free will, it is merely a necessary condition but not enough to defend it. Second, because all considerations about an autonomous mind sending orders to the body is against our scientific knowledge about human beings; in particular, neither neurological nor evolutionary theory can admit dualism. The quantum theory of measurement can be interpreted without the intervention of human minds, but other fields of science cannot contemplate the mentalist scenario, so it is concluded that QM has nothing to say about the mind or free will, and its scientific explanation is more related to biology than to physics. A fatalistic or materialist view, which denies the possibility of a free will, makes much more sense in scientific terms. 1. Definition of free will First of all, we must clarify the meaning of the term to which we refer: Free will: a source totally detached from matter (detached from nature) which is the origin (cause) of options, thoughts, feelings,..
    [Show full text]
  • What Psychodynamic Psychotherapists Think About Free Will and Determinism and How That Impacts Their Clinical Practice : a Qualitative Study
    Smith ScholarWorks Theses, Dissertations, and Projects 2012 What psychodynamic psychotherapists think about free will and determinism and how that impacts their clinical practice : a qualitative study Patrick J. Cody Smith College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.smith.edu/theses Part of the Social and Behavioral Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Cody, Patrick J., "What psychodynamic psychotherapists think about free will and determinism and how that impacts their clinical practice : a qualitative study" (2012). Masters Thesis, Smith College, Northampton, MA. https://scholarworks.smith.edu/theses/872 This Masters Thesis has been accepted for inclusion in Theses, Dissertations, and Projects by an authorized administrator of Smith ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Patrick Cody What Psychodynamic Psychotherapists Think about Free Will and Determinism and How that Impacts their Clinical Practice: A Qualitative Study ABSTRACT This qualitative study explored psychodynamic psychotherapists’ beliefs about free will and determinism and how these impact their work with clients. A secondary goal was to determine if and how knowledge of psychodynamic theory, neuropsychology and/or physics has shaped those views. Twelve clinicians were asked questions related to free will, determinism and clients’ behavioral change. All participants said that psychodynamic theory has influenced their beliefs, and a majority said that neuropsychology has done so. Major findings include that 11 of the 12 participants endorsed the concept of compatibilism, that free will and determinism can co- exist and are not mutually exclusive in impacting behavior. This finding compares to, but does not confirm, research that found psychodynamic clinicians were more deterministic than other clinicians (McGovern, 1986), and it contrasts with research that suggests that the science related to free will and determinism has not reached the field and influenced clinical practice (Wilks, 2003).
    [Show full text]
  • Karma Theory, Determinism, Fatalism and Freedom of Will
    Log. Univers. 11 (2017), 35–60 c 2016 Springer International Publishing 1661-8297/17/010035-26, published online August 17, 2016 DOI 10.1007/s11787-016-0154-z Logica Universalis Karma Theory, Determinism, Fatalism and Freedom of Will Ricardo Sousa Silvestre Abstract. The so-called theory of karma is one of the distinguishing aspects of Hinduism and other non-Hindu south-Asian traditions. At the same time that the theory can be seen as closely connected with the free- dom of will and action that we humans supposedly have, it has many times been said to be determinist and fatalist. The purpose of this paper is to analyze in some deepness the relations that are between the the- ory of karma on one side and determinism, fatalism and free-will on the other side. In order to do that, I shall use what has been described as the best formal approach we have to indeterminism: branching time theory. More specifically, I shall introduce a branching time semantic framework in which, among other things, statements such as “state of affairs e is a karmic effect of agent a”, “a wills it to be the case that e”and“e is inevitable” could be properly represented. Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03A05; Secondary 03B44, 03B45, 03B80, 03C55, 03C98. Keywords. Branching time theory, temporal logic, logic of action, karma theory, determinism, free-will, fatalism. 1. Introduction The so-called theory of karma, or law of karma, is one of the distinguish- ing aspects of Hinduism and other non-Hindu south-Asian traditions. There have been many descriptions of the theory of karma, from the usually obscure passages of the Upanishads and accounts made by several figures of Mahab- harata and puranas, to the sometimes overconfident descriptions of modern Indian gurus.
    [Show full text]
  • Are Deterministic Descriptions and Indeterministic Descriptions Observationally Equivalent?
    Charlotte Werndl Are deterministic descriptions and indeterministic descriptions observationally equivalent? Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Werndl, Charlotte (2009) Are deterministic descriptions and indeterministic descriptions observationally equivalent? Studies in history and philosophy of science part b: studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, 40 (3). pp. 232-242. ISSN 1355-2198 DOI: http://10.1016/j.shpsb.2009.06.004/ © 2009 Elsevier Ltd This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/31094/ Available in LSE Research Online: July 2013 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. Are Deterministic Descriptions And Indeterministic Descriptions Observationally Equivalent? Charlotte Werndl The Queen’s College, Oxford University, [email protected] Forthcoming in: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics Abstract The central question of this paper is: are deterministic and inde- terministic descriptions observationally equivalent in the sense that they give the same predictions? I tackle this question for measure- theoretic deterministic systems and stochastic processes, both of which are ubiquitous in science.
    [Show full text]
  • DICTIONARY of PHILOSOPHY This Page Intentionally Left Blank
    A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY This page intentionally left blank. A Dictionary of Philosophy Third edition A.R.Lacey Department of Philosophy, King’s College, University of London First published in 1976 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Second edition 1986 Third edition 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © A.R.Lacey 1976, 1986, 1996 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Lacey, A.R. A dictionary of philosophy.—3rd edn. 1. Philosophy—Dictionaries I. Title 190′.3′21 B41 ISBN 0-203-19819-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-19822-0 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-13332-7 (Print Edition) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available on request Preface to the first edition This book aims to give the layman or intending student a pocket encyclopaedia of philosophy, one with a bias towards explaining terminology. The latter task is not an easy one since philosophy is regularly concerned with concepts which are unclear.
    [Show full text]
  • Indeterminism Is a Modal Notion: Branching Spacetimes and Earman’S Pruning
    Indeterminism is a modal notion: branching spacetimes and Earman’s pruning Tomasz Placek and Nuel Belnap Contents 1 Three types of branching 4 1.1 Ensemble and individual branching defined . 5 1.2 BST branching . 6 2 BT/BST branching 8 2.1 BST: Our World and its point events . 8 2.2 BST: histories . 9 2.3 BST: axioms . 10 2.4 BST: space-like relatedness . 10 2.5 BST: modal thickness and thinness . 10 2.6 BST: applications . 11 2.7 Spatiotemporal locations . 12 3 Physically-motivated BST models 13 3.1 Minkowskian Branching Structures . 13 3.2 Defining MBS’s . 18 3.3 Takingstock............................ 22 3.4 Historical remarks . 23 4 Further replies to Earman 24 4.1 BST: Hausdorffproperty..................... 24 4.2 The thin red line . 31 4.3 Semantic rule (R)......................... 33 4.4 Past/future asymmetry . 35 5 Indeterminism 37 1 6 Final 40 2 Abstract The paper defends an Aristotelian notion of indeterminism, as rig- orously formulated in the framework of branching space-times (BST) of Belnap (1992), against criticism by Earman (2008) based on a model-theoretic characterization of indeterminism. It delineates BST branching against the background provided by Earman’s (2008) dis- tinction between individual vs. ensemble branching. Partly in order to motivate our responses to Earman, it describes a construction of physically-motivated BST models, in which histories are isomorphic to Minkowski spacetime. Finally it responds to Earman’s criticisms leveled against BST by addressing a topological issue, the question of an actual future, the past/future asymmetry, and some semantical questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Spacetime Singularities and a Novel Formulation of Indeterminism
    Spacetime singularities and a novel formulation of indeterminism Feraz Azhar∗ Department of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, 46556, USA & Black Hole Initiative, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, 02138, USA Mohammad Hossein Namjooy School of Astronomy, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences (IPM), Tehran, Iran (Dated: January 27, 2021) Spacetime singularities in general relativity are commonly thought to be problematic, in that they signal a breakdown in the theory. We address the question of how to interpret this breakdown, restricting our attention to classical considerations (though our work has ramifications for more general classical metric theories of gravity, as well). In particular, we argue for a new claim: spacetime singularities in general relativity signal indeterminism. The usual manner in which indeterminism is formulated for physical theories can be traced back to Laplace. This formulation is based on the non-uniqueness of future (or past) states of a physical system|as understood in the context of a physical theory|as a result of the specification of an antecedent state (or, respectively, of a subsequent state). We contend that for physical theories generally, this formulation does not comprehensively capture the relevant sense of a lack of determination. And, in particular, it does not com- prehensively capture the sense(s) in which a lack of determination (and so, indeterminism) arises due to spacetime singularities in general relativity. We thus present a novel, broader formulation, in which indeterminism in the context of some physical theory arises whenever one of the three following conditions holds: future (and/or past) states are (i) not unique|as for Laplacian notions of indeterminism; (ii) not specified; or (iii) `incoherent'|that is, they fail to satisfy certain desiderata that are internal to the theory and/or imposed from outside the theory.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 04, Number 2 Spring 2005 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND COMPUTERS FROM THE EDITOR, JON DORBOLO FROM THE CHAIR, MARVIN CROY ARTICLE ERIC STEINHART “Generating & Interpreting Metaphors with NETMET” BOOK REVIEWS L. Floridi, ed.: The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information L. Floridi, ed.: The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information Review of “Mind and AI” REVIEWED BY SUSAN A. J. STUART L. Floridi, ed.: The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information Review of “Science and Technology” REVIEWED BY MARVIN CROY L. Floridi, ed.: The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information Review of “Cybernetics” and “Artificial Life” REVIEWED BY RON BARNETTE © 2005 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Computers Jon Dorbolo, Editor Spring 2005 Volume 04, Number 2 committee. Dennett gave an intriguing presentation, and we ROM THE DITOR had plenty of discussion. Here are two photos of the event, F E one of Dan with the prize, and one of Dennett with current committee members who were able to attend (Peter Boltuc and Bruce Umbaugh), plus Ron and myself. Overall, it was a Editorial Board joyful event, and I’m looking forward to the next awarding of Jon Dorbolo, Editor the Barwise prize to Deborah Johnson in Chicago at the 2005 4140 The Valley Library Central Division meeting. Oregon State University In October 2004, I traveled to Corvallis, OR 97331-4502 the University of Delaware (home of the APA) for a meeting of APA [email protected] committee chairs.
    [Show full text]