Pollock's Theory of Defeasible Reasoning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pollock's Theory of Defeasible Reasoning Pollock’s Theory of Defeasible Reasoning Jonathan Weisberg University of Toronto Northern Institute of Philosophy June 18, 2010 Pollock Weisberg Motivations Graphs Outline Semantics Paradoxes 1 Motivations Worries Other 2 Inference Graphs References 3 Pollock’s Semantics 4 Success Stories: The Paradoxes of Acceptance 5 Worries 6 Other Topics Pollock Weisberg Motivations Graphs Semantics Paradoxes Worries Other Motivations References Motivations Pollock Weisberg 1 Problematic Bayesian Idealizations Motivations Graphs 1 Computational Demands 2 Semantics Storage Demands 3 Logical Omniscience Paradoxes Worries 2 Representing Sequential Reasoning Other 3 Paradoxes of Acceptance References 1 The Lottery Paradox 2 The Lottery Paradox Paradox 3 The Preface Paradox 4 The Epistemological Role of Non-Doxastic States 5 Dissatisfaction with Standard Non-Monotonic Logics Problematic Bayesian Idealizations Pollock É Computational Demands: a Bayesian agent updates all her Weisberg probabilities with each new piece of evidence. Motivations É Computationally demanding, often wasteful. Graphs É At odds with our actual reasoning. Semantics É Storage Demands: a Bayesian agent stores a real number for Paradoxes each conditional belief, a “combinatorial nightmare” Worries (Pollock 2008). Other É Suppose an agent has 300 beliefs. References É The number of conditional probabilities of the form 90 p(A B1 ...Bn) that must be stored is about 10 . 90j É 10 > the number of particles in the universe. É Logical Omniscience: a Bayesian agent assigns probability 1 to all logical truths, but we surely can’t and don’t. Pollock (2008) advertises his framework as avoiding the first two problems. É I’m advertising it as avoiding the last. Representing Sequential Reasoning Pollock Weisberg Motivations A lot of our reasoning appears to be sequential, in two ways: Graphs É Collecting reasons. Semantics Paradoxes É Deploying reasons. Worries Bayesianism, DST, ranking theory, etc. all ignore this reality. Other É As a result, they may fail to acknowledge beliefs that are References justified despite not taking account of all the evidence. É If other cognitive demands (pragmatic or epistemic) rationally interrupt a train of reasoning, you may be justified in believing the conclusions drawn so far. Paradoxes of Acceptance Pollock Weisberg Motivations Pollock’s treatment of the paradoxes of acceptance respects the Graphs following desiderata. Semantics Preface: you are justified in believing the claims in your Paradoxes É Worries book. Other É Lottery: you are not justified in believing your ticket will References win. É Conjunction: if you are justified in believing A and B, you are justified in believing A&B. This package is very hard to come by. The Epistemological Role of Non-Doxastic States Pollock Weisberg On many epistemological views, non-doxastic states play a role Motivations in justifying beliefs: Graphs É Perceptual states Semantics Paradoxes É Memories Worries É Module outputs Other On some views, non-doxastic states alone justify: References É Pollock, Pryor On others, they do so in conjunction with background beliefs: É Vogel, White? But formal epistemologies almost never address the justificatory role of non-doxastic states. Dissatisfaction with Standard Non-Monotonic Logics Pollock Weisberg Motivations Graphs Pollock’s reasons for dissatifaction with other non-monotonic Semantics formalisms vary from case to case: Paradoxes Worries É Too limited Other É Implausible results References É Off-topic For a survey, see (Pollock 1995: 104-9). Pollock Weisberg Motivations Graphs Semantics Paradoxes Worries Inference Graphs Other References Epistemic States Pollock Weisberg In Pollock’s system, an agent’s epistemic state is represented by Motivations an inference graph. Graphs É Nodes: reasons and the propositions they bear on. Semantics É Directed edges: relations of support and defeat. Paradoxes Worries Example: Other References F B P Defeat: Rebutting vs. Undercutting Pollock Pollock acknowledges two kinds of defeaters: Weisberg 1 Rebutters: R is a rebutting defeater of P if it is a reason for Motivations P. : Graphs 2 Undercutters: U is an undercutting defeater of P as a reason Semantics for Q if it is a reason for (P wouldn’t be true unless Q Paradoxes were true). : Worries É The negated conditional is symbolized P Q. ⊗ Other So the previous example is properly represented: References F B F ⊗ B P Example: Rebutting Defeat Pollock Weisberg Motivations Example: Pam says that Robert will be at the party, whereas Graphs Qbert says he won’t be: Semantics Paradoxes Worries R R : Other References P Q Inference Rules Pollock Weisberg Motivations Where do the arrows come from? That is, when is one thing a Graphs reason for another? Semantics É Pollock proposes a number of inference rules in various Paradoxes writings, but does not pretend to have a complete list. Worries Other É The methodology: propose rules that seem plausible and References test them on numerous examples. É Finding a list of complete rules that yield sensible results is a major burden of the theory. É Compare the Bayesian’s task of specifying rationality constraints on priors: Reflection, PP, Indifference, etc. Inference Rules: Some Examples1 Pollock Perceptual Justification x’s appearing R is a defeasible reason for Weisberg believing that x is R. (Pollock 1971, 1974) Motivations Temporal Projection Believing P@t is a defeasible reason for Graphs believing P@(t + ∆t), the strength of the reason Semantics being a monotonic decreasing function of ∆t (for Paradoxes appropriate P). (Pollock 2008) Worries Discontinuity Defeat P@t1 is an undercutting defeater for the Other : inference by Temporal Projection from P@t0 to References P@t2. (ibid) Statistical Syllogism If r > 1=2 then Fc & p(G F) r is a prima facie reason for Gc, the strengthj of≥ the reason being a monotonic increasing function of r. (Pollock 1990,1995) Subproperty Defeat Hc & p(G F&H) = p(G F) is an undercutting defeaterj for6 the Statisticalj Syllogism. 1NB: these are simplified glosses, omitting important qualifiers and details. Initial Nodes: Perception Pollock Inference rules tell us how to introduce new nodes into the Weisberg graph given initial nodes, but where do initial nodes come from? Motivations É In other words, what can be used as a reason without Graphs appeal to a supporting reason? Semantics Pollock is surprisingly brief on this point. Paradoxes Worries É Formally, we just help ourselves to a set of premises: input. Other É He does say, References “Epistemic reasoning starts with premises that are input to the reasoner. In human beings, these are provided by perception.” (Pollock 1995: 39) “Perception provides the premises in input from which epistemic cognition reasons forward [. ]” (ibid: 47) Initial Nodes: Further Candidates Pollock Should other things be included in input too? Weisberg É Existing (justified) beliefs Motivations Graphs É Memory states Semantics É Outputs of non-perceptual modules Paradoxes Fortunately, we can explore the formalism and many of its Worries applications without answering this question. Other But it does raise important, tricky questions about what an References É inference graph is supposed to represent. É An agent’s epistemic state at a time: the reasons and inferences she is currently aware of? É A record of her reasoning over time: all the reasons and inferences she has taken account of in her lifetime? É The framework’s appeal may depend heavily on our choice here. Pollock Weisberg Motivations Graphs Semantics Paradoxes Worries Other Pollock’s Semantics References Defeat Statuses Pollock We want to be able to figure out what beliefs are justified given Weisberg the reasons and inferences taken into account so far. Motivations É We want an algorithm for assigning the statuses defeated Graphs and undefeated to nodes in a given graph. Semantics Paradoxes Using to symbolize defeated and + to symbolize undefeated, − Worries we want results like: Other References + − − − F B F R R ⊗ : + + + + B P P Q Semantics: A First Attempt Pollock Weisberg Definition: D-initial Node Motivations A node is D-initial iff neither it nor any of its ancestors are Graphs Semantics termini of a defeat link. Paradoxes Then here’s a plausible, first attempt: Worries (1) D-initial nodes are undefeated. Other References (2) If the immediate ancestors of node A are undefeated, and all nodes defeating it are defeated, then A is undefeated. (3) If A has a defeated immediate ancestor, or there is an undefeated node that defeats A, then A is defeated. This proposal gets the right results for Tweety and other simple examples. A Problem: Collective Defeat Pollock Weisberg But it does poorly in cases of “collective defeat”, like our example of conflicting testimony. Motivations Graphs É The only assignments consistent with (1)–(3) are: Semantics Paradoxes + + Worries − − R R R R Other : : References + + + + P Q P Q É Both are counterintuitive and unjustifiably anti-symmetric. Another Problem: Self-Defeat Pollock Weisberg If we assign to Q, we violate (2): − Motivations Graphs − − Semantics R P Q Paradoxes ⊗ Worries Other References − Q + P Another Problem: Self-Defeat Pollock Weisberg If we assign + to Q, we violate (3): Motivations Graphs + + Semantics R P Q Paradoxes ⊗ Worries Other + References Q + P Partial & Maximal Assignments Pollock These complications (and others) motivate a more sophisticated Weisberg approach: Motivations Definition: Partial Status Assignments Graphs Semantics A partial status assignment assigns + and to at least some − Paradoxes nodes and satisfies: Worries (P1) All D-initial nodes are undefeated. Other (P2) A is undefeated iff the immediate ancestors of A are References undefeated, and all nodes defeating A are defeated. (P3) A is defeated iff A has a defeated immediate ancestor, or there is an undefeated node that defeats A. Definition: Maximal Status Assignment A status assignment is maximal iff it is partial and is not contained in any larger partial assignment. The Final Proposal Pollock Weisberg Motivations Proposal: Supervaluation Graphs Semantics A node is undefeated iff every maximal status assignment gives it Paradoxes a +; otherwise it is defeated.
Recommended publications
  • Defeasibility from the Perspective of Informal Logic
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 10 May 22nd, 9:00 AM - May 25th, 5:00 PM Defeasibility from the perspective of informal logic Ralph H. Johnson University of Windsor, Centre for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Johnson, Ralph H., "Defeasibility from the perspective of informal logic" (2013). OSSA Conference Archive. 84. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA10/papersandcommentaries/84 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Defeasibility from the perspective of informal logic RALPH H. JOHNSON Centre for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric University of Windsor 401 Sunset Ave, Windsor, Ontario Canada [email protected] ABSTRACT: The notions of defeasibility and defeasible reasoning have generated a great deal of interest in various research communities. Here I want to focus on their use in logic and argumentation studies. I will approach these topics from the perspective of an informal logician who finds himself struggling with some issues that surround the idea of and the deployment of the concept of defeasibility. My intention is to make those struggles as clear as I can. KEYWORDS: deductive, defeasible, defeasibility, Pollock, undercutting defeater, rebutting defeater, Informal Logic Initiative 1. INTRODUCTION The notions of defeasibility and defeasible reasoning have generated a great deal of interest in various research communities.
    [Show full text]
  • Bootstrapping, Defeasible Reasoning, Anda Priorijustification
    PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 24, Epistemology, 2010 BOOTSTRAPPING, DEFEASIBLE REASONING, AND APRIORIJUSTIFICATION Stewart Cohen The University of Arizona What is the relationship between (rationally) justified perceptual belief and (rationally) justified belief in the reliability of perception? A familiar argument has it that this relationship makes perceptual justification impossible. For on the one hand, pre-theoretically it seems reasonable to suppose: (1) We cannot have justified perceptual beliefs without having a prior justified belief that perception is reliable. If we are not justified in believing perception is reliable, then how can we trust its deliverances? On the other hand, it seems reasonable to suppose: (2) We cannot be justified in believing perception is reliable without having prior justified perceptual beliefs. It is a contingent matter whether perception is reliable. So how else could we be justified in believing perception is reliable other than by empirical investigation?1 Combining these two suppositions yields the disastrous result that we need justified perceptual beliefs prior to having justified perceptual beliefs. Unless we are content with a skeptical result, these two suppositions need to be reconsidered. Some theorists have elected to retain (1) and deny (2), by arguing that we have apriorijustification for believing perception is reliable.2 Others have elected to retain (2) and deny (1), allowing that we can have justified perceptual beliefs without having justification for believing perception is reliable.3 Denying (1) yields what I will call “basic justification” or “basic justified beliefs” — justified beliefs that are obtained without prior justification for believing that the processes that produces them are reliable.
    [Show full text]
  • From Logic to Rhetoric: a Contextualized Pedagogy for Fallacies
    Current Issue From the Editors Weblog Editorial Board Editorial Policy Submissions Archives Accessibility Search Composition Forum 32, Fall 2015 From Logic to Rhetoric: A Contextualized Pedagogy for Fallacies Anne-Marie Womack Abstract: This article reenvisions fallacies for composition classrooms by situating them within rhetorical practices. Fallacies are not formal errors in logic but rather persuasive failures in rhetoric. I argue fallacies are directly linked to successful rhetorical strategies and pose the visual organizer of the Venn diagram to demonstrate that claims can achieve both success and failure based on audience and context. For example, strong analogy overlaps false analogy and useful appeal to pathos overlaps manipulative emotional appeal. To advance this argument, I examine recent changes in fallacies theory, critique a-rhetorical textbook approaches, contextualize fallacies within the history and theory of rhetoric, and describe a methodology for rhetorically reclaiming these terms. Today, fallacy instruction in the teaching of written argument largely follows two paths: teachers elevate fallacies as almost mathematical formulas for errors or exclude them because they don’t fit into rhetorical curriculum. Both responses place fallacies outside the realm of rhetorical inquiry. Fallacies, though, are not as clear-cut as the current practice of spotting them might suggest. Instead, they rely on the rhetorical situation. Just as it is an argument to create a fallacy, it is an argument to name a fallacy. This article describes an approach in which students must justify naming claims as successful strategies and/or fallacies, a process that demands writing about contexts and audiences rather than simply linking terms to obviously weak statements.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence Graphs: Supporting Transparent and FAIR Computation, with Defeasible Reasoning on Data, Methods and Results
    bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/2021.03.29.437561; this version posted March 30, 2021. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY 4.0 International license. Evidence Graphs: Supporting Transparent and FAIR Computation, with Defeasible Reasoning on Data, Methods and Results Sadnan Al Manir1 [0000-0003-4647-3877], Justin Niestroy1 [0000-0002-1103-3882], Maxwell Adam Levinson1 [0000-0003-0384-8499], and Timothy Clark1,2 [0000-0003-4060-7360]* 1 University of Virginia, School of Medicine, Charlottesville VA USA 2 University of Virginia, School of Data Science, Charlottesville VA USA [email protected] *Corresponding author: [email protected] Abstract. Introduction: Transparency of computation is a requirement for assessing the va- lidity of computed results and research claims based upon them; and it is essential for access to, assessment, and reuse of computational components. These com- ponents may be subject to methodological or other challenges over time. While reference to archived software and/or data is increasingly common in publica- tions, a single machine-interpretable, integrative representation of how results were derived, that supports defeasible reasoning, has been absent. Methods: We developed the Evidence Graph Ontology, EVI, in OWL 2, with a set of inference rules, to provide deep representations of supporting and challeng- ing evidence for computations, services, software, data, and results, across arbi- trarily deep networks of computations, in connected or fully distinct processes. EVI integrates FAIR practices on data and software, with important concepts from provenance models, and argumentation theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Discourse Relations and Defeasible Knowledge`
    DISCOURSE RELATIONS AND DEFEASIBLE KNOWLEDGE* Alex Lascarides t Nicholas Asher Human Communication Research Centre Center for Cognitive Science University of Edinburgh University of Texas 2 Buccleuch Place, Edinburgh, EH8 9LW Austin, Texas 78712 Scotland USA alex@uk, ac. ed. cogsc£ asher@sygmund, cgs. utexas, edu Abstract of the event described in a, i.e. fl's event is part of the preparatory phase of a's: 2 This paper presents a formal account of the temporal interpretation of text. The distinct nat- (2) The council built the bridge. The architect ural interpretations of texts with similar syntax drew up the plans. are explained in terms of defeasible rules charac- terising causal laws and Gricean-style pragmatic Explanation(a, fl): For example the event de- maxims. Intuitively compelling patterns of defea,- scribed in clause fl caused the event described in sible entailment that are supported by the logic clause a: in which the theory is expressed are shown to un- derly temporal interpretation. (3) Max fell. John pushed him. Background(a, fl): For example the state de- The Problem scribed in fl is the 'backdrop' or circumstances under which the event in a occurred (so the event and state temporally overlap): The temporal interpretation of text involves an account of how the events described are related (4) Max opened the door. The room was pitch to each other. These relations follow from the dark. discourse relations that are central to temporal import. 1 Some of these are listed below, where Result(a, fl): The event described in a caused the clause a appears in the text before fl: the event or state described in fl: Narration(a,fl): The event described in fl is a consequence of (but not necessarily caused by) (5) Max switched off the light.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a Tale of Two Interpretations
    Notes 1 A Tale of Two Interpretations 1. As Georges Dicker puts it, “Hume’s influence on contemporary epistemology and metaphysics is second to none ... ” (1998, ix). Note, too, that Hume’s impact extends beyond philosophy. For consider the following passage from Einstein’s letter to Moritz Schlick: Your representations that the theory of rel. [relativity] suggests itself in positivism, yet without requiring it, are also very right. In this also you saw correctly that this line of thought had a great influence on my efforts, and more specifically, E. Mach, and even more so Hume, whose Treatise of Human Nature I had studied avidly and with admiration shortly before discovering the theory of relativity. It is very possible that without these philosophical studies I would not have arrived at the solution (Einstein 1998, 161). 2. For a brief overview of Hume’s connection to naturalized epistemology, see Morris (2008, 472–3). 3. For the sake of convenience, I sometimes refer to the “traditional reading of Hume as a sceptic” as, e.g., “the sceptical reading of Hume” or simply “the sceptical reading”. Moreover, I often refer to those who read Hume as a sceptic as, e.g., “the sceptical interpreters of Hume” or “the sceptical inter- preters”. By the same token, I sometimes refer to those who read Hume as a naturalist as, e.g., “the naturalist interpreters of Hume” or simply “the natu- ralist interpreters”. And the reading that the naturalist interpreters support I refer to as, e.g., “the naturalist reading” or “the naturalist interpretation”. 4. This is not to say, though, that dissenting voices were entirely absent.
    [Show full text]
  • On a Flexible Representation for Defeasible Reasoning Variants
    Session 27: Argumentation AAMAS 2018, July 10-15, 2018, Stockholm, Sweden On a Flexible Representation for Defeasible Reasoning Variants Abdelraouf Hecham Pierre Bisquert Madalina Croitoru University of Montpellier IATE, INRA University of Montpellier Montpellier, France Montpellier, France Montpellier, France [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] ABSTRACT Table 1: Defeasible features supported by tools. We propose Statement Graphs (SG), a new logical formalism for Tool Blocking Propagating Team Defeat No Team Defeat defeasible reasoning based on argumentation. Using a flexible label- ASPIC+ - X - X ing function, SGs can capture the variants of defeasible reasoning DEFT - X - X DeLP - X - X (ambiguity blocking or propagating, with or without team defeat, DR-DEVICE X - X - and circular reasoning). We evaluate our approach with respect Flora-2 X - X - to human reasoning and propose a working first order defeasible reasoning tool that, compared to the state of the art, has richer expressivity at no added computational cost. Such tool could be of great practical use in decision making projects such as H2020 Existing literature has established the link between argumenta- NoAW. tion and defeasible reasoning via grounded semantics [13, 28] and Dialectical Trees [14]. Such approaches only allow for ambiguity KEYWORDS propagation without team defeat [16, 26]. In this paper we propose a new logical formalism called State- Defeasible Reasoning; Defeasible Logics; Existential Rules ment Graph (SGs) that captures all features showed in Table 1 via ACM Reference Format: a flexible labelling function. The SG can be seen as a generalisa- Abdelraouf Hecham, Pierre Bisquert, and Madalina Croitoru. 2018. On a tion of Abstract Dialectical Frameworks (ADF) [8] that enrich ADF Flexible Representation for Defeasible Reasoning Variants.
    [Show full text]
  • Explanations, Belief Revision and Defeasible Reasoning
    Artificial Intelligence 141 (2002) 1–28 www.elsevier.com/locate/artint Explanations, belief revision and defeasible reasoning Marcelo A. Falappa a, Gabriele Kern-Isberner b, Guillermo R. Simari a,∗ a Artificial Intelligence Research and Development Laboratory, Department of Computer Science and Engineering, Universidad Nacional del Sur Av. Alem 1253, (B8000CPB) Bahía Blanca, Argentina b Department of Computer Science, LG Praktische Informatik VIII, FernUniversitaet Hagen, D-58084 Hagen, Germany Received 15 August 1999; received in revised form 18 March 2002 Abstract We present different constructions for nonprioritized belief revision, that is, belief changes in which the input sentences are not always accepted. First, we present the concept of explanation in a deductive way. Second, we define multiple revision operators with respect to sets of sentences (representing explanations), giving representation theorems. Finally, we relate the formulated operators with argumentative systems and default reasoning frameworks. 2002 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Belief revision; Change theory; Knowledge representation; Explanations; Defeasible reasoning 1. Introduction Belief Revision systems are logical frameworks for modelling the dynamics of knowledge. That is, how we modify our beliefs when we receive new information. The main problem arises when that information is inconsistent with the beliefs that represent our epistemic state. For instance, suppose we believe that a Ferrari coupe is the fastest car and then we found out that some Porsche cars are faster than any Ferrari cars. Surely, we * Corresponding author. E-mail addresses: [email protected] (M.A. Falappa), [email protected] (G. Kern-Isberner), [email protected] (G.R.
    [Show full text]
  • Reasoning Strategies for Diagnostic Probability Estimates in Causal Contexts: Preference for Defeasible Deduction Over Abduction?
    Reasoning strategies for diagnostic probability estimates in causal contexts: Preference for defeasible deduction over abduction? Jean-Louis Stilgenbauer1,2, Jean Baratgin1,3, and Igor Douven4 1 CHArt (P-A-R-I-S), Université Paris 8, EPHE, 4-14 rue Ferrus, 75014 Paris – France, http://paris-reasoning.eu/ 2 Facultés Libres de Philosophie et de Psychologie (IPC), 70 avenue Denfert-Rochereau, 75014 Paris – France [email protected] 3 Institut Jean Nicod (IJN), École Normale Supérieure (ENS), 29 rue d’Ulm, 75005 Paris – France [email protected] 4 Sciences, Normes, Décision (SND), CNRS/Université Paris-Sorbonne, 1 rue Victor Cousin, 75005 Paris – France [email protected] Abstract. Recently, Meder, Mayrhofer, and Waldmann [1,2] have pro- posed a model of causal diagnostic reasoning that predicts an interfer- ence of the predictive probability, Pr(Effect | Cause), in estimating the diagnostic probability, Pr(Cause | Effect), specifically, that the interfer- ence leads to an underestimation bias of the diagnostic probability. The objective of the experiment reported in the present paper was twofold. A first aim was to test the existence of the underestimation bias in in- dividuals. Our results indicate the presence of an underestimation of the diagnostic probability that depends on the value of the predictive probability. Secondly, we investigated whether this bias was related to the type of estimation strategy followed by participants. We tested two main strategies: abductive inference and defeasible deduction. Our re- sults reveal that the underestimation of diagnostic probability is more pronounced under abductive inference than under defeasible deduction. Our data also suggest that defeasible deduction is for individuals the most natural reasoning strategy to estimate Pr(Cause | Effect).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Reasoning View and Defeasible Practical Reasoning Samuel Asarnow Macalester College [email protected] Forthcoming In
    The Reasoning View and Defeasible Practical Reasoning Samuel Asarnow Macalester College [email protected] Forthcoming in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research ABSTRACT: According to the Reasoning View about normative reasons, facts about normative reasons for action can be understood in terms of facts about the norms of practical reasoning. I argue that this view is subject to an overlooked class of counterexamples, familiar from debates about Subjectivist theories of normative reasons. Strikingly, the standard strategy Subjectivists have used to respond to this problem cannot be adapted to the Reasoning View. I think there is a solution to this problem, however. I argue that the norms of practical reasoning, like the norms of theoretical reasoning, are characteristically defeasible, in a sense I make precise. Recognizing this property of those norms makes space for a solution to the problem. The resulting view is in a way analogous to familiar defeasibility theories of knowledge, but it avoids a standard objection to that theory. Introduction It is a commonplace to observe that there is a connection between the idea of a normative reason and the idea of good reasoning. As Paul Grice put it, “reasons […] are the stuff of which reasoning is made.”1 Using a consideration as a premise in a piece of reasoning—making an inference on the basis of it—is a paradigmatic way of treating that consideration as a reason. And, very often, when we engage in good reasoning we are responding to the considerations that really are the normative
    [Show full text]
  • Defeasible Inference in Natural Language
    Thinking Like a Skeptic: Defeasible Inference in Natural Language Rachel Rudingeryzx, Vered Shwartzyz, Jena D. Hwangy, Chandra Bhagavatulay, Maxwell Forbesyz, Ronan Le Brasy, Noah A. Smithyz, Yejin Choiyz yAllen Institute for AI zPaul G. Allen School of Computer Science & Engineering, University of Washington xUniversity of Maryland, College Park, MD [email protected] fvereds,jenah,chandrab,maxf,ronanlb,noah,[email protected] Abstract Premise: Two men and a dog are standing among rolling green hills. Defeasible inference is a mode of reasoning in which an inference (X is a bird, therefore X Hypothesis: The men are farmers. flies) may be weakened or overturned in light They are wearing backpacks. The men are facing their granary. of new evidence (X is a penguin). Though One man is using his binoculars. The men are holding pitchforks. long recognized in classical AI and philoso- The men are studying a tour map. The dog is a sheep dog. phy, defeasible inference has not been exten- sively studied in the context of contemporary Figure 1: Examples from the δ-SNLI portion of the data-driven research on natural language infer- δ-NLI dataset. A neutral premise-hypothesis pair from ence and commonsense reasoning. We intro- SNLI is augmented with three update sentences that duce Defeasible NLI (abbreviated δ-NLI), a weaken the hypothesis (left, red) and three update sen- dataset for defeasible inference in natural lan- tences that strengthen it (right, blue). guage. δ-NLI contains extensions to three existing inference datasets covering diverse modes of reasoning: common sense, natural of new evidence, is known as defeasible reasoning language inference, and social norms.
    [Show full text]
  • An Appreciation of John Pollock's Work on the Computational Study Of
    Argument and Computation Vol. 3, No. 1, March 2012, 1–19 An appreciation of John Pollock’s work on the computational study of argument Henry Prakkena* and John Hortyb aDepartment of Information and Computing Sciences, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands & Faculty of Law, University of Groningen, Groningen, The Netherlands; bPhilosophy Department, Institute for Advanced Computer Studies and Computer Science Department, University of Maryland, College Park, MD, USA (Received 12 January 2012; final version received 19 January 2012) John Pollock (1940–2009) was an influential American philosopher who made important con- tributions to various fields, including epistemology and cognitive science. In the last 25 years of his life, he also contributed to the computational study of defeasible reasoning and prac- tical cognition in artificial intelligence. He developed one of the first formal systems for argumentation-based inference and he put many issues on the research agenda that are still relevant for the argumentation community today. This paper presents an appreciation of Pol- lock’s work on defeasible reasoning and its relevance for the computational study of argument. In our opinion, Pollock deserves to be remembered as one of the founding fathers of the field of computational argument, while, moreover, his work contains important lessons for current research in this field, reminding us of the richness of its object of study. Keywords: formal models of argumentation; non-monotonic accounts of argument; defeasible reasoning 1. Introduction John Pollock (1940–2009) was an influential American philosopher who made important contri- butions to various fields, including epistemology and cognitive science. In the last 25 years of his life, he also contributed to artificial intelligence (AI), first to the study of defeasible reasoning and then to the study of decision-theoretic planning and practical cognition.
    [Show full text]