Boundary-Work and the Demarcation of Science from Non-Science: Strains and Interests in Professional Ideologies of Scientists Author(S): Thomas F

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Boundary-Work and the Demarcation of Science from Non-Science: Strains and Interests in Professional Ideologies of Scientists Author(S): Thomas F Boundary-Work and the Demarcation of Science from Non-Science: Strains and Interests in Professional Ideologies of Scientists Author(s): Thomas F. Gieryn Source: American Sociological Review, Vol. 48, No. 6 (Dec., 1983), pp. 781-795 Published by: American Sociological Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2095325 . Accessed: 20/10/2014 20:34 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Sociological Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.173.127.127 on Mon, 20 Oct 2014 20:34:19 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOUNDARY-WORK AND THE DEMARCATION OF SCIENCE FROM NON-SCIENCE: STRAINS AND INTERESTS IN PROFESSIONAL IDEOLOGIES OF SCIENTISTS* THOMAS F. GIERYN Indiana University The demarcation of science from other intellectual activities-long an analytic problemfor philosophersand sociologists-is here examinedas a practicalproblem for scientists. Construction of a boundary between science and varieties of non-science is useful for scientists' pursuit of professional goals: acquisition of intellectual authority and career opportunities; denial of these resources to "pseudoscientists"; and protection of the autonomy of scientific research from political interference. "Boundary-work"describes an ideological style found in scientists' attempts to create a public imagefor science by contrastingit favorably to non-scientific intellectual or technical activities. Alternativesets of characteristics availablefor ideological attributionto science reflect ambivalences or strains within the institution:science can be made to look empiricalor theoretical,pure or applied. However, selection of one or another descriptiondepends on which characteristics best achieve the demarcationin a way thatjustifies scientists' claims to authorityor resources. Thus, "science" is no single thing: its boundariesare drawnand redrawn inflexible, historicallychanging and sometimesambiguous ways. Philosophersand sociologists of science have a demarcation between scientific and other long struggled with the "problem of demar- knowledgeis a poor heuristicfor the sociology cation": how to identify unique and essen- of science (Collins, 1982:300).Characteristics tial characteristicsof science that distinguishit once proposed as capable of distinguishingsci- from other kinds of intellectual activities. ence from non-science are found to be common Comte ([1853] 1975:72)distinguished positive among intellectual activities not ordinarily science from theology and metaphysics in his labeled scientific, or they are found not to be evolutionarylaw of three stages, arguingthat typical features of science-in-practice (e.g., only science used "reasoningand observation" Knorret al., 1980;Elkana, 1981:41;Broad and to establish laws of "succession and re- Wade, 1982:8-9). Some dismiss demarcation semblance." Popper (1965:34, 41) proposed as a "pseudo-problem"(Laudan, 1983:29). "falsifiability"as a criterionof demarcation:if Continuing debates over the possibility or a theory cannot, in principle, be falsified (re- desirabilityof demarcatingscience from non- futed) by empirical data, it is not scientific. science are, in one sense, ironic. Even as Merton (1973: Chap. 13) explains the special sociologists and philosophers argue over the abilityof modernscience to extend "certified" uniqueness of science among intellectual ac- knowledge as a result, in part, of the in- tivities, demarcationis routinelyaccomplished stitutionalizationof distinctive social norms in practical, everyday settings: education ad- (communism, universalism, disinterestedness ministrators set up curricula that include and organized skepticism). chemistry but exclude alchemy; the National Recent studies, however, suggest that at- Science Foundationadopts standardsto assure tempts to demarcate science have failed that some physicists but no psychics get (Bohme, 1979:109), and that the assumption of funded; journal editors reject some manu- scriptsas unscientific. How is the demarcation of science accomplishedin these practicalset- *Direct all correspondence to: Thomas F. Gieryn, tings, far removed from apparentlyfutile at- Department of Sociology, Indiana University, tempts by scholars to decide what is essential Bloomington, IN 47405. and unique about science? Demarcationis not Many people provided helpful suggestions, among just an analytical problem: because of consid- them: David Zaret, Robert Althauser, Howard erable materialopportunities and professional Becker, George Bevins, William Corsaro, Elihu Ger- son, Allen Grimshaw, Robert Merton, Nicholas Mul- advantagesavailable only to "scientists," it is fins, Bernice Pescosolido, Whitney Pope, Charles no mere academic matter to decide who is Powers, Sal Restivo, and Stephen Zehr. My devel- doing science and who is not. opment of the concept of "boundary-work" bene- This paper restates the problemof demarca- fited from conversations with Steve Woolgar. tion: characteristics of science are examined American Sociological Review 1983, Vol. 48 (December:781-795) 781 This content downloaded from 128.173.127.127 on Mon, 20 Oct 2014 20:34:19 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 782 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW not as inherentor possibly unique, but as part [their]privilege" through "expediential ration- of ideologicalefforts by scientists to distinguish alizations of . material interests" (Bendix, their work and its productsfrom non-scientific 1963:xi,449). The two theories are sometimes intellectual activities. The focus is on presented as mutually exclusive and compet- boundary-workof scientists: their attribution ing: Sutton et al. (1956:12)"reject" the theory of selected characteristicsto the institutionof that "ideologies simply reflect . economic science (i.e., to its practitioners, methods, self-interest,"while Seider (1974:812)finds the stock of knowledge, values and work organi- "Marx-Mannheimtheory was . more useful zation) for purposes of constructing a social than Sutton's role-strain theory in predicting boundarythat distinguishes some intellectual the content of public political ideology" of activities as "non-science." Boundary-workis business leaders. analyzed as a rhetorical style common in The effectiveness of strain and interest "public science" (Turner, 1980:589;cf. Men- theories has been impeded by "theoretical delsohn, 1977:6), in which scientists describe clumsiness" (Geertz, 1973:196) resulting, in science for the public and its political au- part, from an "anarchy of linguistic dif- thorities, sometimes hopingto enlarge the ma- ferences" (Oakeshott, 1980:viii;on the diverse terialand symbolic resourcesof scientists or to definitionsof "ideology," cf. Mannheim,1936; defend professional autonomy. The paper ex- Birnbaum, 1960; Lichtheim, 1967; Gouldner, amines both style and content of professional 1976; Larrain, 1979). The two theories agree ideologies of scientists, as illustratedin three substantially:both see ideologies as symbolic examples: first, public addresses and popular representations(whether sets of ideas, beliefs, writings of John Tyndall, an effective "states- values, wishes, consciousnesses or world- man for science" in late Victorian England; views); both suggest that ideologies selectively second, argumentsover the scientific status of distort social "reality";both assume that ade- phrenology in early 19th-centuryEdinburgh; quate explanationrequires examinationof the third, a 1982 policy report by the National social context of ideological statements, Academy of Sciences on scientific communi- focusing on structuralsources and functional cation and national security. consequences of ideas. To add to the confu- sion, followers of Parsons allow that interests are SOCIOLOGICALTHEORIES OF "certainly an important determinant of IDEOLOGY ideological reaction" (White, 1961:9), while Marx traced the origins of ideology to the de- Two long-standing theoretical orientations sire of rulingclasses to conceal contradictions dominatesociological studies of ideology, and between the means and the social relations of these are especially visible in analyses of occu- production(cf. Larrain, 1979:45-61). pationalor professionalideologies (cf. Carlton, Geertz has taken two steps towardclarifying 1977:24-28;Geertz, 1973:201).Strain theories sociological theories of ideology. First, he are associated with Parsons (1967:139-65, rightlysuggests that strainand interesttheories 1951:331-54): ideologies provide "evaluative need not be incompatible:an ideology can, at integration"in the face of conflictingdemands, once, smooth inconsistencies and advance competing expectations and inevitable am- interests (Geertz, 1973:201). Second, Geertz bivalences of social life. They are symp- recommends that sociologists examine the toms-as well as symbolic resolutions-of rhetorical style of ideological statements (cf. role strain, contradiction, and disequilibrium Dibble, 1973). Both strainand interesttheories (White, 1961; Sutton et al.,
Recommended publications
  • Miguel García-Sancho Talks with Karin Knorr Cetina
    Engaging Science, Technology, and Society 4 (2018), 246-266 DOI:10.17351/ests2018.239 “These Were Not Boring Meetings”: Miguel García-Sancho Talks with Karin Knorr Cetina MIGUEL GARCÍA-SANCHO1 UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH KARIN KNORR CETINA2 UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO Abstract In this interview, Karin Knorr Cetina evokes the first Annual Meeting of the Society for Social Studies of Science at Cornell University in 1976 as a foundational moment for science and technology studies (STS). This conference consolidated a new approach to the study of science based on the anthropological observation of scientists at work in the laboratory. Knorr Cetina argues that, despite geographically cementing in the United States, this approach originated mainly through the work of European scholars. The years that followed the Cornell meeting were marked by intense debates between the defenders of this anthropological approach and other scholars more focused on ideas than on scientific practice. Knorr Cetina describes these debates as “bloodbaths” and recalls having first coined the term “constructivist” as applied to science studies in 1977. For Knorr Cetina, STS is now shifting its attention from the production to the consumption of technoscientific knowledge. Her current interest in the financial markets and other forms of screen technologies is an example of this transition. She argues that STS needs to overcome its current fragmentation and emphasis in isolated case studies. The establishment of basic research centers with the financial resources to develop collective and long-term programs would help scholars to expand their horizons. In his following reflection, Miguel García-Sancho explores the connections between STS and travel in both a sense of intellectual shift and a more mundane meaning of physical movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Malte Ziewitz Talks with Michael Lynch Keywords
    Engaging Science, Technology, and Society 4 (2018), 366-385 DOI:10.17351/ests2018.220 It’s Important to Go to the Laboratory: Malte Ziewitz Talks with Michael Lynch MALTE ZIEWITZ1 CORNELL UNIVERSITY MICHAEL LYNCH2 CORNELL UNIVERSITY Abstract Why would anyone still want to go to the laboratory in 2018? In this interview, Michael Lynch answers this and other questions, reflecting on his own journey in, through, and alongside the field of science and technology studies (STS). Starting from his days as a student of Harold Garfinkel’s at UCLA to more recent times as editor of Social Studies of Science, Lynch talks about the rise of origin stories in the field; the role of ethnomethodology in his thinking; the early days of laboratory studies; why “turns” and “waves” might better be called “spins”; what he learned from David Edge; why we should be skeptical of the presumption that STS enhances the democratization of science; and why it might be time to “blow up STS”––an appealing idea that Malte Ziewitz takes up in his reflection following the interview. Keywords history of STS; Michael Lynch; interview; laboratory; ethnomethodology; parasites; explosive STS MZ The field of STS now seems to be at a point where people enjoy a good origin story. Do you have one you would like to share? ML I’ll give you one that’s very familiar, which gives a lot of credit to Edinburgh. I think there’s a solid basis for this story, certainly other people will tell a different one and we all know that these things are constructed in light of where we are in the present.
    [Show full text]
  • Bourdieu and Latour in STS: “Let’S Leave Aside All the Facts for a While”
    Bourdieu and Latour in STS: “Let’s Leave Aside All the Facts for A While” by Lee Claiborne Nelson M.A., Aarhus University, 2011 B.A., Dalhousie University, 2008 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in The Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies (Science and Technology Studies) THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA (Vancouver) September 2014 © Lee Claiborne Nelson, 2014 Abstract Through the lens of the English-speaking Science and Technology Studies (STS) community, the relationship between Pierre Bourdieu and Bruno Latour has remained semi-opaque. This thesis problematizes the Anglo understanding of the Bourdieu-Latour relationship and unsettles the resolve that maintains the distance that STS has kept from Bourdieu. Despite many similarities between these two scholars, Bourdieu has remained a distant figure to STS despite his predominance in disciplines from which STS frequently borrows and the relevance of his corpus to topics dear to the heart of STS. This is in part due to Latour's frequent criticisms of Bourdieu by name, Latour’s philosophical disagreements with Kant and neoKantians, and Latour’s prestige in STS, and partially due to Bourdieu’s somewhat indirect or orthogonal ways of addressing natural and physical sciences and technology. Due to the fact that the writings of both needed to be translated from the original French to be received by Anglo audiences, important cultural, stylistic, and rhetorical nuances were lost, mistranslated, or not translated across the linguistic and geographical divides. Including these distinctions is invaluable to understanding their relationship and further weakens the justification for Bourdieu's absence from STS.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    FORUM: QUALITATIVE Volume 3, No. 3, Art. 15 SOCIAL RESEARCH September 2002 SOZIALFORSCHUNG Signing for Reflexivity: Constructionist Rhetorics and Its Reflexive Critique in Science and Technology Studies Tarja Knuuttila Key words: Abstract: I argue that reflexivity should not be seen as being primarily about the relationship of reflexivity, Science scientific writing to the realities studied—as it is often understood. In trying to establish this point I and Technology examine the discussion about reflexivity in science and technology studies (STS). The STS reflexiv- Studies, ists claimed that the relativist and constructionist STS undermined reflexively themselves by argu- representation, ing that all knowledge is situated and socially constructed. In the face of this reflexive problematics constructionism, they suggested that "new literary forms", which manifest the constructed nature of scientific text, relativism should be adopted. It seems to me that this program of inscribing reflexivity was semiotically misguided, which contributed to its demise. On the other hand, I argue that the basic reflexive point about the paradoxicality of making general claims about the local and contingent "nature" of knowl- edge is sound and that it should have deserved more attention in the constructionist rhetoric. The second part of my paper draws some more general methodological points from the STS case presented. I am especially interested in the performative aspects of signing for methodological novelties and ask whether it is sensible to talk about "reflexive methodology". Table of Contents 1. Introduction 2. Turn, Turn, Turn—Reflexivity in STS 2.1 Science "as it actually happens"? 2.2 The possibility of a writerly mode of STS writing 2.3 Reflexivity re-examined 3.
    [Show full text]
  • On Sociological Reflexivity © American Sociological Association 2021
    STXXXX10.1177/0735275121995213Sociological TheoryKrause 995213research-article2021 Original Article Sociological Theory 2021, Vol. 39(1) 3 –18 On Sociological Reflexivity © American Sociological Association 2021 https://doi.org/10.1177/0735275121995213DOI: 10.1177/0735275121995213 st.sagepub.com Monika Krause1 Abstract This article offers a critique of the self-observation of the social sciences practiced in the philosophy of the social sciences and the critique of epistemological orientations. This kind of reflection involves the curious construction of wholes under labels, which are the result of a process of “distillation” or “abstraction” of a “position” somewhat removed from actual research practices and from the concrete claims and findings that researchers produce, share, and debate. In this context, I call for more sociological forms of reflexivity, informed by empirical research on practices in the natural sciences and by sociomaterial approaches in science and technology studies and cultural sociology. I illustrate the use of sociological self-observation for improving sociological research with two examples: I discuss patterns in how comparisons are used in relation to how comparisons could be used, and I discuss how cases are selected in relation to how they could be selected. Keywords reflexivity, sociology of the social sciences, philosophy of the social sciences, participant objectification, comparison, case selection When practicing social scientists discuss divisions among themselves, and choices open to them, they routinely
    [Show full text]
  • It STITUTI 7N Harvard Univ.,Cambridge.,,Mass: Program Cr Aciencei
    MD160 4311 51 025. 069 AUTHOR' Shelanski, Vivien.E.,. Ed. TITLE: Newsletter on Science,. Technolegy - Human Values, Number 2.117-J,une 1978. - ; It STITUTI 7N Harvard Univ.,Cambridge.,,Mass: Program cr aciencei. Technology. and Publicjc110. sppms- AGENCY National Endowment for the Humanities (NFIH) , Washington, D.C. PUE.DATE Jun 78 NOTE 75p.; Not available in hard copy due tc copyright restrictions AVAILABLE FROM Newsletter on Science, Technology & Buman Values, Aiken Computation Lab. 232, Harvard Univ., Cambridge, NA/ 02138 (Subscription individual $10.00) E _4ipRICE NF- $0.8.3 Plus Pos hge. EC Not Availatle fret EDES. RIPTORS *Activism;-Ethical_yalues*HUmanisp; *Newsletters; Nuclear Warfare; -*POlitical Attitudes; Politics; Science Education; acience History; Sciences; *Scientists; *Technology; Values ABSTRACT- Two papers ale presented in this mew4 titter: one on thepolitical activity 'Of scientists following, world ar II as a result of the Manhattan Project, and cne cr the politicalactivity of scientists today. These papers are followed by two cestenta:ries which coat:Care the two rrapers. Also included in this iEsuefiare net's items, a calendar of events, a report on a conference on ethical guidelines for research and clinical perspectives en human sexuality,arff annotated bibliography, and an index.ft the previous eight issues or this newsletter. (BE) _** * * * * * * * *x * * * * ** ********* Re produ ionssupplied by EDRS are the best at car Le made ) from the original doctimert. ** * ** * ** ************* SIB DEPARTm OF HEALTH, ,IDUCAtII WElFARE NATION* NSTITOTE OF EDUCATION . THIS DOCUMENT HAS BEEN REPRO- CIUCED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED FROM TOE PdFISON OR ORGANIZATION ORIGIN- ' ATING IT POINTS OF VIEW OR OPINIONS STATED DO NOT NECESSARILY REPRE- SENT OFFICIAL NATIONAL INSTITUTE OF EDUCATION POSITION OR POLICY PERMISSION To REPRODUCE THIS,.
    [Show full text]
  • Law, Science, and Science Studies: Contrasting the Deposition of a Scientific Expert with Ethnographic Studies of Scientific Practice*
    LAW, SCIENCE, AND SCIENCE STUDIES: CONTRASTING THE DEPOSITION OF A SCIENTIFIC EXPERT WITH ETHNOGRAPHIC STUDIES OF SCIENTIFIC PRACTICE* DAV I D S. CAUDILL** I. INTRODUCTION [These scientists] appear to have developed considerable skills in setting up devices which can pin down elusive figures, traces, or inscriptions in their craftwork, and in the art of persuasion. The latter skill enables them to convince others that what they do is important, that what they say is true . They are so skillful, indeed, that they manage to convince others not that they are being convinced but that they are simply following a consistent line of interpretations of available evidence . Not surprisingly, our anthropological observer experienced some dis-ease in handling such a tribe. Whereas other tribes believe in gods or complicated mythologies, the members of this tribe insist that their activity is in no way to be associated with beliefs, a culture, or a mythology.1 The appropriation, from anthropology, of ethnographic methodology by scholars in science studies—including Science and Technology Studies (STS), the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge (SSK), and cultural studies of scientific practices—is now commonplace. While the term “ethnography” has various meanings,2 it usually refers to social science research that (i) explores “the nature of particular social phenomena, rather than setting out to test hypotheses about them,” (ii) works with “unstructured” data, rather than data “coded at the point of data collection * This article is a modified version of a paper delivered (i) October 3, 2002, for the Schrader, Harrison, Segal & Lewis Lecture Series in Law and Psychology, Villanova University School of Law J.D./Ph.D.
    [Show full text]
  • References.Pdf
    REFERENCES (References to primary articles examined in chapters 2, 3, 6, 7, 9, and 10 are provided in end-of-chapter reference lists and appendices or are mentioned in passing within the text.) Abt, Helmut A. “Some Trends in American Astronomical Publications.” Publica- tions of the Astronomical Society of the Pacific 93 (1981): 269-73. Agassi, Joseph. Faraday as a Natural Philosopher. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971. American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1976. Aristotle. Posterior Analytics. 2. Hugh Tredennick. Cambridge: Harvard Univer- sity Press, 1960. Aristotle. Rhetoric. Tr. Lane Cooper. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1932. Austin, J. L. How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1962. Bacon, Francis. The Advancement of Learning. London, 1603. Bacon, Francis. Magna Instauratio. London, 1620. Bachelard, G. Le Materialisme Rationnel. Paris: PUF, 1953. Baddam. Memoirs of the Royal Society, vol. 1. London, 1738. Baldauf, R. B., and B. H. Jernudd. “Language of Publications as a Variable in Scientific Communication.” Australian Review of Applied Linguistics 6 (1983): 97-108. Barnes, Barry, Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974, Barnes, Barry, and Steven Shapin. Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture. Beverly Hills: Sage, 1979. Barnes, Sherman B. “The Editing of Early Learned Journals.” Osiris I (1936): 155-72. Bazerman, Charles. “How Natural Philosophers Can Cooperate.” In Text and Profession, ed. Bazerman and Paradis, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, forthcoming. Bazerman, Charles. The Informed Writer. 3d edition. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1989. Bazerman, Charles. “Scientific Writing as a Social Act.” In New Essays in Tech- nical Writing and Communication, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • On Being a Scientist: a Guide to Responsible Conduct in Research: Third Edition
    THE NATIONAL ACADEMIES PRESS This PDF is available at http://nap.edu/12192 SHARE On Being a Scientist: A Guide to Responsible Conduct in Research: Third Edition DETAILS 82 pages | 6 x 9 | PAPERBACK ISBN 978-0-309-11970-2 | DOI 10.17226/12192 CONTRIBUTORS GET THIS BOOK Committee on Science, Engineering, and Public Policy; National Academy of Sciences; National Academy of Engineering; Institute of Medicine FIND RELATED TITLES Visit the National Academies Press at NAP.edu and login or register to get: – Access to free PDF downloads of thousands of scientific reports – 10% off the price of print titles – Email or social media notifications of new titles related to your interests – Special offers and discounts Distribution, posting, or copying of this PDF is strictly prohibited without written permission of the National Academies Press. (Request Permission) Unless otherwise indicated, all materials in this PDF are copyrighted by the National Academy of Sciences. Copyright © National Academy of Sciences. All rights reserved. On Being a Scientist: A Guide to Responsible Conduct in Research: Third Edition ON BEING A SCIENTIST A GUIDE TO RESPONSIBLE CONDUCT IN RESEARCH THIRD EDITION Committee on Science, Engineering, and Public Policy Copyright National Academy of Sciences. All rights reserved. On Being a Scientist: A Guide to Responsible Conduct in Research: Third Edition THE NATIONAL ACADEMIES PRESS 500 Fifth Street, N.W. Washington, DC 20001 NOTICE: The project that is the subject of this report was approved by the Gov- erning Board of the National Research Council, whose members are drawn from the councils of the National Academy of Sciences, the National Academy of Engineer- ing, and the Institute of Medicine.
    [Show full text]
  • PER, Vol. X, No. 3, Summer 1997
    Professional Ethics Report Volume X, Number 3, Summer 1997 Publication of the AAAS Scientific Freedom, Responsibility and Law Program, in collaboration with the Cover Story Committee on Scientific Freedom and Responsibility In the News Professional Society Ethics Group In the Societies Editor: Mark S. Frankel Deputy Editor: Alexander Fowler Letter to the Editor Managing Editor: Kamla Butaney Ethics, Law and Public Policy Column ISSN: 1045-8808 Resources URL: http://www.aaas.org/spp/sfrl/sfrl.htm Announcements The Role of Scientific and Engineering Societies in Eastern Europe By Mark S. Frankel The democratic and economic transition in Eastern Europe has far-reaching implications for science and for scientists, who have gained greater professional autonomy and new possibilities to participate in policymaking and to develop standards of conduct. As they emerge from the clutches of communism, scientists and engineers will need to develop mechanisms of professional self-regulation that will foster a commitment to high standards of research and professional ethics, consider ways to participate in the policymaking process in a manner that transcends professional self-interest, and find ways to inform the public about the technical aspects of policy issues and to address the public concerns regarding the social and ethical implications of advances in science and technology. Scientific and technical societies have a major role to play in these processes. Under communism, the activities of scientific and technical societies in Eastern Europe were circumscribed--albeit to varying degrees, by country and by discipline--by the exigencies of single party rule and central planning. These societies benefited from the relatively high priority accorded to science and technology by the ruling communist parties; scientific conferences and journals were heavily subsidized by the state, as were educational programs designed to explain science to the public.
    [Show full text]
  • Ontography As the Study of Locally Organized Ontologies
    Ontography as the Study of Locally Organized Ontologies Michael Lynch I first used the term »ontography« in the postscript of a special issue of the journal Social Studies of Science on »the turn to ontology« in the field of Science and Technology Studies (STS).1 In their introduction to the special issue, the guest editors, Steve Woolgar and Javier Lezaun, noted that there had been an upsurge in the use of the term »ontology« in STS, anthropology, and other social science fields.2 Woolgar, Lezaun, and other contributors to the special issue expressed both heightened interest in and skepticism about this »turn to ontology.« The »turn« in question was not a turn back to an ancient branch of metaphysics concerned with the constitution of reality, though some of the authors who embraced it did indulge in metaphysical discourse. To the extent that it was a metaphysical movement, the turn to ontology was a turn from one metaphysical orientation to another; from a humanist treatment of representation and meaning-making, to a post-humanist (re)distribution of agency among humans, non-human beings, and material things. This turn was an empirical turn that aimed to investigate particu- lar domains of social action (including but not limited to scientific, technical, and medical actions) in which things (though not necessarily things-as-such; self-suf- ficient, non-relational entities) were highly salient, not only as objects but also as agents, agencies, and intermediaries. The turn to ontology is sometimes presented as a reaction to an over-emphasis on epistemology in earlier work in STS and related fields, particularly work asso- ciated with social constructionism in the sociology of scientific knowledge, which seemed to reduce obdurate material realities to historically, socially, and cultur- ally situated practices and knowledges.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy, Individual Rights and the Regulation of Science
    Sci Eng Ethics (2009) 15:407–429 DOI 10.1007/s11948-009-9145-2 ORIGINAL PAPER Democracy, Individual Rights and the Regulation of Science J. Weinstein Received: 21 January 2006 / Accepted: 8 April 2009 / Published online: 13 June 2009 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009 Abstract Whether the US Constitution guarantees a right to conduct scientific research is a question that has never been squarely addressed by the United States Supreme Court. Similarly, the extent to which the First Amendment protects the right to communicate the results of scientific research is an issue about which there is scant judicial authority. This article suggests that a crucial guidepost for exploring both these uncharted areas of constitutional law should be whether restrictions on scientific research or communication truly implicate fundamental individual rights or instead primarily concern issues of general social welfare—issues that in a democracy are properly decided by the representative branches of government or their delegates, not by the judiciary. Keywords First Amendment Á Freedom of speech Á Judicial scrutiny Á Scientific speech Á Scientific research Á Freedom of thought and inquiry Á Substantive due process Introduction Does the United States Constitution recognize a right to engage in scientific research? Does the First Amendment protect communication of the results of such research? Neither of these related questions has ever been squarely addressed by the United States Supreme Court. In this paper I will not attempt to fully explore either of these uncharted areas of the law or come to any definite conclusion. Instead, I will discuss various approaches to these questions and offer a few tentative suggestions about how to decide cases that are likely to arise in these areas.
    [Show full text]