Human Souls and the Triad of Intellectual Operations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Human Souls and the Triad of Intellectual Operations chapter 6 Human Souls and the Triad of Intellectual Operations As we have seen, all animals are superior to plants in that they have not only vegetative powers but also sensory, that is, cognitive powers. The possession of cognition is what establishes a psychological continuity between nonhuman and human animals. However, there is also a crucial discontinuity and it is this discontinuity that brings us closer to theories of animal rationality. In short, the discontinuity between humans and other animals consists in the fact that only the former have rational or intellectual souls. Consequently, humans are not simply animals but a very peculiar kind of animals, namely, ‘rational animals’ (animalia rationalia).1 They are, so to speak, ‘animals plus x’ with ‘x’ being the faculties of intellect and reason. Nonhuman animals are, in turn, ‘animals without x’. This lack of intellect and reason is why they were often called ‘ irrational animals’ (animalia irrationalia) or ‘brute animals’ (animalia bruta), as mentioned before. The possession of a rational soul thus establishes what modern scholars usually call an anthropological difference because it sets humans apart from all other animals. Medieval philosophers stressed this point. In his commentary on De ani- malibus, Peter of Spain, for instance, states that ‘humans excel any other ani- mal by the nobility of intellect and reason’ (homo enim excellit quodlibet animal nobilitate intellectus et rationis).2 In his Sentences commentary, Peter of John Olivi defines human beings as ‘intellectual animals or animals having intellect’ (bestiae intellectuales seu intellectum habentes).3 On the one hand, this shows that the animal nature of human beings was not denied. On the other hand, it emphasises that something crucial is added to this animal nature, namely, intellectual or rational faculties. Consequently, if these faculties are subtracted from a human animal, one no longer has a human animal. All that remains is an 1 ‘Animal rationale’ is simply the Latin translation of Aristotle’s Greek ‘zoon logon echon’ from Politica I.2, 1253a7-10. 2 Peter of Spain, Questiones super libro ‘De animalibus’ Aristotelis, lib. i, q. 4, ed. Navarro Sánchez (2015), 117. See also Köhler (2008), 191. 3 Peter of John Olivi, Quaestiones in secundum librum Sententiarum, q. 57, ed. Jansen (1924), 338. © Anselm Oelze, 2018 | doi 10.1163/9789004363779_009 This is an open access chapter distributed under the terms of the CC BY-NC 4.0 license. Anselm Oelze - 9789004363779 Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 03:08:12AM via free access <UN> Human Souls and the Triad of Intellectual Operations 37 animal, as Henry of Ghent points out in his Quaestiones quodlibetales.4 There- fore, it is obviously the rational soul that defines humans qua humans and so ‘in reality, mankind is nothing else but the rational soul’, as Thomas Aquinas puts it in the Summa contra gentiles.5 Since this definition of humans was usu- ally taken for granted by medieval philosophers, one can rightly say that it was a fundamental ontological presupposition or a fundamental metaphysical and anthropological presupposition to which they subscribed.6 Yet, the most inter- esting question is, how do the rational souls of humans compare to the sensory souls of nonhuman animals? If having a soul means having certain capacities or engaging in certain operations that are characteristic of this soul, what are the specific operations of rational souls? In order to answer these questions one might first need to ask whether there is actually a difference between ‘intellect’ (intellectus) and ‘reason’ (ra- tio) because, on the one hand, they seem to be used interchangeably, and yet, on the other hand, it would be superfluous to speak of intellect and reason if they were not distinct powers. This question seemed to puzzle medieval au- thors, too. In the Summa theologiae, Thomas Aquinas, for example, explicitly addresses the question of whether intellect and reason are ‘separate powers’ ( diversae potentiae).7 He first presents a number of opinions from other authors who seem to suggest that intellect and reason are indeed distinct powers. The author of the influential De spiritu et anima, for instance, says that there is a clear hierarchy: first come the external senses, then the internal senses, then comes reason and then comes the intellect. Hence, the intellect is superior to reason. Augustine, in contrast, employs them synonymously and so do others. Aquinas’ tries to solve this contradiction by arguing that intellect and reason are not separate powers. Nonetheless, he concedes that there is a certain dif- ference between rational and intellectual cognition, between ‘ratiocinari’ and ‘intelligere’. While the latter means ‘to apprehend an intelligible truth per se’ (simpliciter veritatem intelligibilem apprehendere), the former means ‘to pro- ceed from one intelligible object to another in order to cognise an intelligible truth’ (procedere de uno intellecto ad aliud, ad veritatem intelligibilem cogno- scendam). One could illustrate this difference by comparing it to the differ- ence between solving a mathematical problem by intensive thinking or by 4 Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones quodlibetales i, q. 15, ed. Macken (1979), 93: “Excepto enim eo quod intellectus est, non manet homo nisi bestia […].” 5 Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, lib. iv, c. 81, ed. Leonina xv (1930), 253: “Et secun- dum hoc, humanitas non est aliud realiter quam anima rationalis.” 6 This is how Köhler (1992), 718, and (2008), 295, puts it. 7 See Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae i, q. 79, a. 8, ed. Leonina v (1889), 274f. Anselm Oelze - 9789004363779 Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 03:08:12AM via free access <UN> 38 chapter 6 sudden inspiration. If one solves the problem by intensive thinking it takes some time until one arrives at the solution. One might have to search for the right approach, take notes, and so forth. That is, one makes various steps and so jumps from one partial solution to another. In the case of a sudden inspira- tion, however, the solution immediately appears. One sees the problem and – in a flash of insight – knows the solution. The latter is certainly a much more impressive way of solving mathematical problems. In this sense, intelligere is somehow superior to ratiocinari. Still, both ways lead to the same result and both cognitive acts are brought about by one and the same cognitive power, according to Aquinas. Admittedly, Aquinas’ view is only one among many. Other medieval au- thors had (slightly) different thoughts about the distinction between reason and intellect.8 For the present study, however, the more decisive question is whether this distinction matters for the aspect of animal rationality. On the one hand, it seems to be negligible because neither of these faculties of the soul was ascribed to nonhuman animals by any of the authors covered here. So even if some of them held the view that there is a difference between the two, it remains relatively insignificant if one is looking at animals which, by definition, lack both of these powers. On the other hand, the distinction might not be entirely irrelevant insofar as there were at least some authors who as- cribed the capacity of ‘reasoning’ (ratiocinari) to other animals, as we will see in Part 4. Thus, the slight inferiority of rational cognition in comparison to in- tellectual cognition might actually imply a greater proximity to the powers and operations of the sensory soul (see Chapter 33). But before dealing with these details we first need to see what kind of operations and capacities were usu- ally taken to come along with the possession of a ‘rational’ or ‘intellective soul’ (anima rationalis; anima intellectiva). What are the typical tasks or operations of the higher faculties? In most accounts there are three main intellectual operations, namely, (i) universal cognition and concept formation, (ii) judging, and (iii) reason- ing. These operations built upon each other, as, once again, Thomas Aqui- nas points out.9 First of all, the intellect ‘apprehends the quiddity of a thing’ ( apprehendit quidditatem rei), say, the quiddity of a rose. Apprehending the quiddity of a rose significantly differs from apprehending a rose via the senses. 8 For the full picture from Augustine to Buridan see Enders (2001); Speer (2001); Hoenen (2001). On the Aristotelian and Neoplatonic origins of the distinction see also briefly Sorabji (1993b), 74f. 9 See Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae i, q. 85, a. 5 co., ed. Leonina v (1889), 341. On this article see also the analysis by Pasnau (2002), 273. Anselm Oelze - 9789004363779 Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 03:08:12AM via free access <UN> Human Souls and the Triad of Intellectual Operations 39 If one sees, smells, or touches a rose, for example, one perceives certain features of a particular thing. It is this or that rose one sees or smells or touches and one would not have any of these perceptions if no rose were presently there. Hence, sensory cognition is of present and particular things. But what if one remembers or imagines a rose? In this case, one does not presently perceive a rose but still has a sensory impression. In fact, one can have sensory impres- sions without presently perceiving things. But these sensory impressions are nonetheless the impressions of a particular thing such as of the particular rose one saw yesterday in the garden. To apprehend the quiddity of a rose, however, means to abstract from any material and temporal conditions because the quiddity of a rose is what is common to all roses, not only to this or that particular rose one has perceived at this or that particular time and place. The colour red, for instance, does not belong to the quiddity of roses because there are also white or yellow roses.
Recommended publications
  • Platonic Theology: Books 1-4 V.1 Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    PLATONIC THEOLOGY: BOOKS 1-4 V.1 PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Marsilio Ficino,Michael J.B. Allen,John Warden,James Hankins,William Bowen | 448 pages | 08 May 2001 | HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS | 9780674003453 | English | Cambridge, Mass, United States Platonic Theology: Books 1-4 v.1 PDF Book His Platonic evangelizing was eminently successful and widely influential, and his Platonic Theology , translated into English in this edition, is one of the keys to understanding the art, thought, culture, and spirituality of the Renaissance. This is six-volume edition and translation of Ficino's eighteen- book Platonic Theology. Platonic Theology: v. Platonic Theology Letters Platonic Commentaries. The "notes to the translation" are other possible translations, needed explanations of the text, sources of quotations or allusions. Ficino devoted his life to reviving the philosophy of Plato and gathered around him a group of distinguished disciples and devotees sometimes referred to as the "Florentine Academy. What God is not. The descent of the soul into the body. He had sought to show that revelation was necessary because, although philosophy could demonstrate the existence of God and man's immortality, knowledge of God's essence and man's true destiny was beyond its comprehension and belonged to the realm of supernatural theology. Allen and Hankins have begun a work of scholarship of the highest calibre, whose continuation is eagerly awaited. Book XIII demonstrates the soul's immortality by four signs : phantasy, reason and prophecy, arts, and miracles. Laurentianus Pluteus As previously shown by Marcel Marsile Ficin. This was dangerous ground, obviously shading into magic, and protesting that he was vindicating Free Will against astrological determinism was not much of a cover.
    [Show full text]
  • 199 Henry of Ghent Summa of Ordinary Questions: Articles Six To
    Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 3 Henry of Ghent Summa of Ordinary Questions: Articles Six to Ten on Theology, translated and with an introduction by Roland J. Teske, SJ. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press 2011. 226 pages $25.00 (paper ISBN 978–087462255–3) This translation of selected articles from Henry of Ghent’s Summa of Ordinary Questions is part of the Medieval Philosophy Texts in Translation series from Marquette University. The translator, Roland Teske, is the current series editor, and he is to be commended for including this volume in the series as it makes available in English an invaluable text for those with a professional interest in medieval philosophy and theology. Henry of Ghent is a little known figure outside the (growing) circle of professional philosophers with an interest in Scholasticism. But he was pivotal in the last thirty years of the 13th century, playing a major role in one of the key events of the period, viz., the Condemnations of 1270 and 1277. Anyone interested in understanding Henry’s thought, particularly his views on the relationship between theology and philosophy, will thank Teske for making this text available at such an affordable price, and for his accurate rendering of Henry’s Latin. The translated articles contain Henry’s considered views on meta-theology. The leading issue of the day concerned the place of theology within the sciences. Prior to the 13th century, theology enjoyed pride of place in the curriculum, with all the other disciplines being seen as preparatory to work in theology. This position came under threat in the 13th century as all the works of Aristotle were gradually rediscovered and assimilated by scholars working in the universities.
    [Show full text]
  • These Disks Contain My Version of Paul Spade's Expository Text and His Translated Texts
    These disks contain my version of Paul Spade's expository text and his translated texts. They were converted from WordStar disk format to WordPerfect 5.1 disk format, and then I used a bunch of macros and some hands-on work to change most of the FancyFont formatting codes into WordPerfect codes. Many transferred nicely. Some of them are still in the text (anything beginning with a backslash is a FancyFont code). Some I just erased without knowing what they were for. All of the files were cleaned up with one macro, and some of them have been further doctored with additional macros I wrote later and additional hand editing. This explains why some are quite neat, and others somewhat cluttered. In some cases I changed Spade's formatting to make the printout look better (to me); often this is because I lost some of his original formatting. I have occasionally corrected obvious typos, and in at least one case I changed an `although' to a `but' so that the line would fit on the same page. With these exceptions, I haven't intentionally changed any of the text. All of the charts made by graphics are missing entirely (though in a few cases I perserved fragments so you can sort of tell what it was like). Some of the translations had numbers down the side of the page to indicate location in the original text; these are all lost. Translation 1.5 (Aristotle) was not on the disk I got, so it is listed in the table of contents, but you won't find it.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and Humanities
    Philosophy and Humanities LT 502 - Elementary Latin II (3) Students advance to the more complex syntax and irregular morphology of classical Latin as well as to the rudiments of rhetorical stylistics. Tools of historical linguistics are introduced so that students can master the changes in orthography that occur to the language between the classical and medieval period. PH 512 - Medieval Philosophy (3) In this course students will read important philosophic works by medieval authors as well as some historical and critical studies by more recent writers. St. Thomas Aquinas will receive special attention. The aim will be to bring medieval philosophers to light and to see the continuing relevance of the issues they raised and the answers they proposed. PH 514 - Recent Philosophy (3) This course appraises the various intellectual developments that emerged in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries – an era that has been marked by a declining confidence in achievements of systematic achievements of philosophical reasoning. It begins with a careful overview of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, perhaps one of the last works in the Western canon to offer a synoptic overview of human experience and knowledge. Though generally rejected in its scope and organization, a number of its chapters have served as the basis of some of the particular problems that have drawn the attention of later thinkers. Thus, this course proceeds with the study of various philosophical movements of later modernity which include: Existentialism, Phenomenology, Analytical Philosophy, Hermeneutics, Deconstructionism, Pragmatism. Concluding the historical survey of Western philosophy, it considers many of the same topics of inquiry, but does so, as the previous three historical courses, in the light of the various cultural and scientific factors that determine its context.
    [Show full text]
  • Pico, Plato, and Albert the Great: the Testimony and Evaluation of Agostino Nifo EDWARD P
    Pico, Plato, and Albert the Great: The Testimony and Evaluation of Agostino Nifo EDWARD P. MAHONEY Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463-1494) is without doubt one of the most intriguing figures of the Italian Renaissance. It is thus no surprise that he has attracted the attention of many modern scholars. By reason of the varied interests that are reflected in his writings, contrasting interpretations of Pico have been proposed.1 Our purpose here is not to present a new and different picture of Pico but, rather, to offer a contribution to one fruitful area of research pursued by some recent historians of philosophy, namely, Pico's debt to, and 1. For general presentations of Pico's life and thought, see the classic study of Eugenio Garin, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola: Vita e dottirina (Florence: F. Le Monnier, 1937); Garin's magisterial Storia della filosofia italiana, 2d ed. (Turin: G. Einaudi 1966), 1:458-495. Among more recent general accounts are Pierre-Marie Cordier, Jean Pic de la Mirandole (Paris: Debresse, 1958); Engelbert Monnerjahn, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (Wiesbaden: F. Steiner, 1960); Paul Oskar Kristeller, Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1964), pp. 54-71; Giovanni di Napoli, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola e laproblemaύca dottrinale del suo tempo (Rome: Desclee, 1965); Charles Trinkaus, In Our Image and Likeness (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), 2:505-526; and Henri de Lubac, Pic de la Mirandole: Etudes et discussions (Paris: Aubier Montaigne, 1974). 165 166 EDWARD P. MAHONEY use of, medieval philosophy in his overall philosophical enterprise.2 Of particular concern will be the influence of Albert the Great on Pico, which can be established by a connection that has apparently not been noticed by Pico's historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry of Ghent on Platonic and Aristotelian Forms
    THE ROOTS OF LOVE OF WISDOM: HENRY OF GHENT ON PLATONIC AND ARISTOTELIAN FORMS Juan Carlos Flores I. Introduction At the very beginning of his Summa quaestionum ordinariarum,1 Henry of Ghent provides a brief history of philosophy to convey more adequately his own orientation and approach. Henry himself later describes his approach as a synthesis of Platonic and Aristotelian thought in the light of faith.2 This synthesis, as developed in the whole Summa and in his Quodlibeta, is quite original and at the same time inspired by many sources, above all Augustine.3 The purpose of this paper is to capture an important aspect of Henry’s synthesis, namely the significance of love of wisdom in his thought. What is the basic source of love of wisdom in Plato, Aristotle and Henry of Ghent (who synthesizes Plato and Aristotle)? What is the ultimate meaning of this drive or motive force in these thinkers? In order to capture the nature of love of wisdom in Henry of Ghent, we shall first look at the nature of this love in the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle.4 Concerning this topic, we shall analyze Plato and Aris- totle (and Henry, of course) on their own terms. In the case of Plato, we shall consider texts that were not available directly to Henry, who knew Plato chiefly through Augustine. Our goal is not to trace the textual sources of Henry’s account of love of wisdom, nor to evalu- ate Henry’s historical accuracy. Rather, the goal is to understand the 1 Cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Suggestions for Further Reading
    MP_D01.qxd 11/23/06 2:43 AM Page 382 Suggestions for Further Reading GENERAL SURVEYS OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Armstrong, A. H., ed. 1970. The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Copleston, Frederick. 1950. A History of Philosophy, vol. 2: Medieval Philosophy: From Augustine to Duns Scotus. Westminster, MD: The Newman Press (many subsequent reprintings by various presses). Copleston, Frederick. 1953. A History of Philosophy, vol. 2: Late Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy. Westminster, MD: The Newman Press (many subsequent reprintings by various presses). Gilson, Étienne. 1955. History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. New York: Random House. Gracia, Jorge J. E., and Timothy B. Noone, eds. 2003. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell. Kenny, A. 2005. A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 2: Medieval Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kretzmann, Norman, et al., eds. 1982. The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy: From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Luscombe, David E. 1997. History of Western Philosophy, vol. 2: Medieval Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marenbon, John. 1981. From the Circle of Alcuin to the School of Auxerre: Logic, Theology and Philosophy in the Early Middle Ages. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Marenbon, John. 1983. Early Medieval Philosophy (480–1150): An Introduction. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Marenbon, John. 1991. Later Medieval Philosophy (1150–1350): An Introduction. London: Routledge. Marenbon, John, ed. 1998. The Routledge History of Philosophy, vol. 3: The Middle Ages. London: Routledge. McGrade, A.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinianism.Pdf
    Augustinianism. This term is used to characterize philosophical, theological and political political ideas which were more or less close to those of S. Augustine of Hippo. The term came into use relatively recently, and can cover a spectrum of views: Augustinianism has never been a homogeneous movement. In particular, it is necessary to distinguish between a broad and a strict sense of the word, In the broad sense, the whole of Latin theology of the medieval and early modern period was strongly influenced by Augustine, as emerges very clearly from the Summae of the twelfth century and above all from Hugh of St Victor and from the authoritative Book of Sentences of Peter Lombard. The early generations of theologians of the mendicant orders – Hugh of St Cher, Alexander of Hales, Bonaventura of Bagnoregio – developed a close bond with Augustine, but they interpreted him in the light of neoplatonic or Aristotelian theories (for example, divine illumination of the intellect, the ‘agent intellect’, matter, rationes seminales [seminal principles]. In the strict sense one must distinguish between the following. #1. Augustinianism from the end of the thirteenth and the beginning of the fourteenth century emerged - especially in the Franciscan School (William de la Mare) and among Augustinian Hermits (“the old Augustinian School according to Giles of Rome) - as a reaction to the widespread reception of Aristotle in the work of Thomas Aquinas, after the condemnations of 1277 at Paris and 1284 at Oxford. Consciously drawing on Augustinian on Augustinian ideas (illumination, the form of created things in the mind of God), Henry of Ghent [a member of the secular clergy] created a coherent new system of speculative theology which would provide a a basis for acute critical analysis and the new order introduced by John Duns Scotus, who substituted for illumination the idea of an intuitive grasp of the essence of things.
    [Show full text]
  • Chaucer and the Disconsolations of Philosophy: Boethius, Agency, and Literary
    Chaucer and the Disconsolations of Philosophy: Boethius, Agency, and Literary Form in Late Medieval Literature by Jack Harding Bell Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ David Aers, Supervisor ___________________________ Sarah Beckwith ___________________________ Thomas Pfau ___________________________ Nancy Armstrong Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2016 ABSTRACT Chaucer and the Disconsolations of Philosophy: Boethius, Agency, and Literary Form in Late Medieval Literature by Jack Harding Bell Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ David Aers, Supervisor ___________________________ Sarah Beckwith ___________________________ Thomas Pfau ___________________________ Nancy Armstrong An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2016 Copyright by Jack Harding Bell 2016 Abstract This study argues that Chaucer's poetry belongs to a far-reaching conversation about the forms of consolation (philosophical, theological, and poetic) that are available to human persons. Chaucer's entry point to this conversation was Boethius's Consolation of Philosophy , a sixth-century dialogue that tried to show how the Stoic ideals of autonomy and self-possession are not simply normative for human beings but remain within the grasp of every individual. Drawing on biblical commentary, consolation literature, and political theory, this study contends that Chaucer's interrogation of the moral and intellectual ideals of the Consolation took the form of philosophical disconsolations: scenes of profound poetic rupture in which a character, sometimes even Chaucer himself, turns to philosophy for solace and yet fails to be consoled.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry of Ghent and the Inevitable Failure of Divine Illumination〔1〕
    Henry of Ghent and the Inevitable Failure of Divine Illumination〔1〕 YingyingZHANG (DepartmentofWorldReligions,GraduateSchool,ChineseAcademyofSocialSciences) Author :YingyingZhang,DepartmentofWorldReligions,GraduateSchool,ChineseAcademyofSocialSciencesAddress: No.11,ChangyuDajie,FangshanDist.,Beijing102488,P.R.China.Tel:+86G137G6452G1028.Email:vinessazy@163.com Abstract :HenryofGhentattemptedtointegrateanAristotelianempiricism,PlatonicexemplarismandanAugustinian doctrineofDivineIllumination,toformafirmphilosophicalbasisforAugustineƳstheoryofknowledge,meanwhiletrying torestoreitstheologicalconnotations.However,hisnewsynthesiswasdoomedtofail,becausethetensionsbetweenthe ChristianmetaphysicalworldviewandtheepistemologicalrequirementsoftheAristoteliansystem wereunsolvable.The th needfordivineilluminationwaswaninginthefaceofencroachingAristotelianismattheendof13 century. KeyWords :DivineIllumination,Augustine,Platonism,Aristotelianism,exemplar 1.IntroductionDivineIlluminationGAuustinianEistemolo before13Centur : g p gy y DivineIlluminationisthetheoryofknowledgewhichSt.AugustineappropriatedfromtheNeoG PlatonismandcombinedwithChristianfaith,todecipherhumanƳscognitiveactivities.AsTimothy NooneputinTheCambridgeHistoryofMedievalPhilosophy(Vol.I):“(DivineIlluminationis)the theoryofhowGodƳslightisrequiredtoaccountfullyforhowhumansarecapableofattainingthe 〔2〕 truththattheymanagetoattainthroughtheirintellectualactivities.” St.Augustinedevelopedhis viewofDivineIlluminationinhisvariouswritings,butheneversystematicallyillustratedthetheory, whichresultsinmanyconflictinginterpretationsbybothhisfollowersandopponents.
    [Show full text]
  • L'homme Et Son Univers Aumoyen Äge
    PHILOSOPHES MEDIEVAUX -------- TOME XXVII ----- _ L'HOMME ET SON UNIVERS AUMOYEN ÄGE Actes du septieme congres international de philosophie medievale (30 aoüt - 4 septembre 1982) edites par Christian WEN IN 11 LOUVAIN-LA-NEUVE EDITIONS DE L'INSTITUT SUPERIEUR DE PHILOSOPHIE 1986 FREDERICK PURNELL, JR. HENRY OF GHENT AS MEDIEVAL PLATONIST IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF JACOPO MAZZONI The connections between Renaissance Platonism and medieval Scholasticism have been the object of ongoing scholarly interest for many years. Attention has focused, for example, upon the extent to which medieval Augustinianism provided a paradigm for the Christianized Neoplatonism expounded by Marsilio Ficino and his associates in the Florentine Academyt '). Less attention has been paid to the influence of medieval sources on later Renaissance Platonists, many of whom developed philosophical positions which differed quite notably from those of Ficino and his circle. The present paper will examine the way in which Jacopo Mazzoni of Cesena (1548-98), a philosopher who sought to combine elements of both Platonism and Aristotelianism in his own system, relied for his interpretation of several important Platonic doctrines on the writings of the thirteenth-century secular master of arts and theology at Paris, Henry of Ghent. Jacopo Mazzoni has largely escaped the attentions of modern his- torians of philosophy, although he was an important figure in his own day. His facility in philosophy, first demonstrated in his student days at the University of Padua under the celebrated Aristotelians Federigo Pendasio and Jacopo Zabarella, was augmented by an insatiable appetite for independent study and a capacious memory. At the height of his powers during the last decade of his life Mazzoni held chairs in philosophy successively at the Universities of Macerata, Pisa and Rome, commanding an unprecedented salary at the latter institution as the successor to Francesco Patrizi.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry of Ghent and the Power of Inspiration a Chapter in Neoplatonism
    J. Spruyt / PsyArt 19 (2015) 68–84 Henry of Ghent and the Power of Inspiration A Chapter in Neoplatonism Joke Spruyt Dept. of Philosophy Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences Maastricht University Abstract In the Middle Ages it was only natural to believe in a celestial, absolute, eternal, non- material world beyond our everyday experiences. Yet for many medievals, theolo- gians and philosophers alike, the existence of such a transcendent reality posed a prob- lem, for how can human beings, who after all belong to the world down here, ever get in touch with that splendid reality high above? While conceding that it is possible to have some sort of knowledge of the divine realm, the thirteenth-century theologian Henry of Ghent (1217(?)-1293) warns us that rational thinking is of limited use here. Instead he suggests another, more direct approach. Like his great predecessor Plato, Henry of Ghent seems to be aware of the, albeit limited, value of artistic inspiration as a means to connect with eternity. As I hope to show, some of his accounts on this elusive subject bring to mind the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. They are also surprisingly similar to the views of the psychologist Carl Gustav Jung. To cite as Spruyt, J., 2015, ‘Henry of Ghent and the Power of Inspiration. A Chapter in Neoplatonism’, PsyArt 19, pp. 68-84. Introduction Theologians of the thirteenth century were the heirs of two completely opposite philosophical traditions. By that time, most of the works of Aristotle, which had been lost for centuries, had been rediscovered. They had gained wide pop- ularity amongst scholars and were considered the auctoritates (authoritative texts) on epistemology.
    [Show full text]