Anthropology & Materialism, Special Issue
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
HERMANN COHEN and LEO STRAUSS Leora Batnitzky
JJTP_addnl_186-213 4/26/06 4:00 PM Page 187 HERMANN COHEN AND LEO STRAUSS Leora Batnitzky Princeton University Introduction Leo Strauss concluded both his first and last major works with ref- erence to Hermann Cohen.1 The arguments of Strauss’s first pub- lished book—Spinoza’s Critique of Religion—are rooted in Strauss’s initial work on Cohen’s interpretation of Spinoza. Strauss’s second book— Philosophy and Law—begins and ends by declaring that Cohen is right that the philosophy of Maimonides represents “true rationalism” and more particularly that Maimonides is better understood as a Platonist than as an Aristotelian. Strauss’s last published work, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, published posthumously, ends with an essay on Cohen, which was also the introduction to the English translation of Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism. Interestingly, though this essay on Cohen is the final essay in Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, it doesn’t have much to say about Plato. Although Strauss claims in this essay not have read Religion of Reason for forty years, those familiar with Strauss’s project will recognize that it is from an engagement with Cohen that Strauss forms his basic reading of Maimonides and then Plato. These readings changed in emphasis throughout Strauss’s career but they nevertheless remained funda- mental to his philosophical program. In this essay, I explore Strauss’s philosophical relation to Cohen. It is not an overstatement to suggest that Cohen is responsible for Leo Strauss’s turn to medieval Jewish philosophy. The focus of this essay, however, is not primarily on the details of Cohen and Strauss’s Presented at “Hermann Cohen’s Ethics,” the University of Toronto, August 2001. -
1 Thomas Meyer Leo Strauss's Religious Rhetoric
Thomas Meyer Leo Strauss’s Religious Rhetoric (1924-1938) Although he had been regarded as shy and restrained since his period of study in Marburg, Strauss was a master of religious rhetoric in his letters and [published] texts. This rhetoric was, for him, neither a [form of] compensation [for insufficient argument], nor a superficial adornment. On the contrary, he deployed religious rhetoric in same way that he analysed [its function] in Plato and Aristotle, through Maimonides and Abravanel, into Spinoza and Hobbes, and up to Hermann Cohen and Julius Guttmann: as an expression of the complex contest between philosophy and religion. After his engagement with Hermann Cohen’s critique of Spinoza in 1924, religious rhetoric was, for Strauss, no longer a feature of Zionist debates alone. Instead, it was a constitutive element of a problematic that Strauss strikingly and provocatively dubbed the “querelle des anciens et des modernes.” In order to understand this change in the function of religious rhetoric [in Strauss’ work], I shall consider three stations of Strauss’ intellectual development. First of all, I shall present several articles that I found in the “Jewish Weekly for Cassel, Hessen, and Waldeck”, which have remained unknown to scholarship until now. Strauss published these articles between February 1925 and January 1928. If we connect these texts with Strauss’s conclusions regarding Spinoza, we can develop a stable account of his religious rhetoric up to about 1934. But [Strauss’s use of religious rhetoric in these texts] can be understood only if we consider it in light of Strauss’ translation of a different religious rhetoric [into the terms of his own thought]: namely, the way Strauss enriched his religious rhetoric through an understanding of, and in dialogue with, the most radical position in Protestant [thought]—that of the dialectical theologian Friedrich Gogarten. -
Against the Heteronomy of Halakhah: Hermann Cohen's Implicit Rejection of Kant's Critique of Judaism
Against the Heteronomy of Halakhah: Hermann Cohen’s Implicit Rejection of Kant’s Critique of Judaism George Y. Kohler* “Moses did not make religion a part of virtue, but he saw and ordained the virtues to be part of religion…” Josephus, Against Apion 2.17 Hermann Cohen (1842–1918) was arguably the only Jewish philosopher of modernity whose standing within the general philosophical developments of the West equals his enormous impact on Jewish thought. Cohen founded the influential Marburg school of Neo-Kantianism, the leading trend in German Kathederphilosophie in the second half of the nineteenth and the first decade of the twentieth century. Marburg Neo-Kantianism cultivated an overtly ethical, that is, anti-Marxist, and anti-materialist socialism that for Cohen increasingly concurred with his philosophical reading of messianic Judaism. Cohen’s Jewish philosophical theology, elaborated during the last decades of his life, culminated in his famous Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism, published posthumously in 1919.1 Here, Cohen translated his neo-Kantian philosophical position back into classical Jewish terms that he had extracted from Judaism with the help of the progressive line of thought running from * Bar-Ilan University, Department of Jewish Thought. 1 Hermann Cohen, Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des Judentums, first edition, Leipzig: Fock, 1919. I refer to the second edition, Frankfurt: Kaufmann, 1929. English translation by Simon Kaplan, Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism (New York: Ungar, 1972). Henceforth this book will be referred to as RR, with reference to the English translation by Kaplan given after the German in square brackets. -
Einstein and the Development of Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science
Einstein and the Development of Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science Don Howard University of Notre Dame Introduction What is Albert Einstein’s place in the history of twentieth-century philosophy of science? Were one to consult the histories produced at mid-century from within the Vienna Circle and allied movements (e.g., von Mises 1938, 1939, Kraft 1950, Reichenbach 1951), then one would find, for the most part, two points of emphasis. First, Einstein was rightly remembered as the developer of the special and general theories of relativity, theories which, through their challenge to both scientific and philosophical orthodoxy made vivid the need for a new kind of empiricism (Schlick 1921) whereby one could defend the empirical integrity of the theory of relativity against challenges coming mainly from the defenders of Kant.1 Second, the special and general theories of relativity were wrongly cited as straightforwardly validating central tenets of the logical empiricist program, such as verificationism, and Einstein was wrongly represented as having, himself, explicitly endorsed those same philosophical principles. As we now know, logical empiricism was not the monolithic philosophical movement it was once taken to have been. Those associated with the movement disagreed deeply about fundamental issues concerning the structure and interpretation of scientific theories, as in the protocol sentence debate, and about the overall aims of the movement, as in the debate between the left and right wings of the Vienna Circle over the role of politics in science and philosophy.2 Along with such differences went subtle differences in the assessment of Einstein’s legacy to logical empiricism. -
LYDIA PATTON CURRICULUM VITAE Associate Professor 231 Major Williams Hall Virginia Tech 220 Stanger St
LYDIA PATTON CURRICULUM VITAE Associate Professor 231 Major Williams Hall Virginia Tech 220 Stanger St. (MC 0126) http://www.lydiapatton.com Blacksburg, VA 24061 http://www.phil.vt.edu/lpatton/lpatton.html [email protected] AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Science, History of Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mathematics AREAS OF COMPETENCE Kant and Neo-Kantianism, History of Analytic Philosophy, Early Modern Philosophy EDUCATION Ph.D. in Philosophy, McGill University, 2004 B.A. in Philosophy, University of Kentucky, 1996 ACADEMIC POSITIONS Virginia Tech Department of Philosophy Associate Professor, 2012-present Virginia Tech Department of Philosophy Assistant Professor, 2007-2012 Pittsburgh Center for Philosophy of Science Visiting Fellow, fall 2009 University of Notre Dame Visiting Professor, spring 2006 University of Chicago Harper-Schmidt Collegiate Assistant Professor and Postdoctoral Fellow, 2004-2007 EDITORIAL POSITIONS HOPOS: The Journal of the International Editor-in-Chief, 2017- Society for the History of Philosophy of Science Associate Editor, 2014-2016 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Associate Editor, 2014- PUBLICATIONS Books and Journal Issues Edited Laws of Nature, co-edited with Walter Ott. Forthcoming, Oxford University Press (UK). Philosophy, Science, and History: A Guide and Reader. Routledge, 2014. “Ontology and Methodology,” special issue of Synthese, edited with Deborah Mayo and Benjamin Jantzen. Vol. 92, no. 11, November 2015. 1 PUBLICATIONS Invited Work 13. “Russell’s Method of Analysis and the Axioms of Mathematics,” in Innovations in the History of Analytical Philosophy, edited Sandra Lapointe and Christopher Pincock. Palgrave McMillan, forthcoming 2017. 12. “Helmholtz’s Physiological Psychology,” in Philosophy of Mind in the Nineteenth Century, edited by Sandra Lapointe. -
Marburg Neo-Kantianism As Philosophy of Culture
SamanthaMatherne (Santa Cruz) Marburg Neo-Kantianism as Philosophy of Culture 1Introduction Although Ernst Cassirer is correctlyregarded as one of the foremost figures in the Neo-Kantian movement thatdominated Germanyfrom 1870 – 1920,specifying ex- actlywhat his Neo-Kantianism amountstocan be achallenge. Not onlymustwe clarify what his commitments are as amember of the so-called MarburgSchool of Neo-Kantianism, but also giventhe shift between his earlyphilosophyof mathematics and naturalscience to his later philosophyofculture, we must con- sider to what extent he remained aMarburgNeo-Kantian throughout his career. With regard to the first task, it is typical to approach the MarburgSchool, which was foundedbyHermann Cohen and Paul Natorp, by wayofacontrast with the otherdominant school of Neo-Kantianism, the Southwest or Baden School, founded by Wilhelm Windelband and carried forward by Heinrich Rick- ert and Emil Lask. The going assumption is that these two schools were ‘rivals’ in the sense that the MarburgSchool focused exclusively on developing aKantian approach to mathematical natural sciences(Naturwissenschaften), while the Southwest School privileged issues relatingtonormativity and value, hence their primary focus on the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften). If one accepts this ‘scientist’ interpretation of the MarburgSchool, one is tempted to read Cas- sirer’searlywork on mathematicsand natural science as orthodoxMarburgNeo- Kantianism and to then regardhis laterwork on the philosophyofculture as a break from his predecessors, veeringcloser -
Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science"
"Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science" Lydia Patton Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal October, 2004 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree ofPh.D. © Lydia Patton 2004 Library and Bibliothèque et 1+1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de l'édition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada Your file Votre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 Our file Notre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant à la Bibliothèque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par télécommunication ou par l'Internet, prêter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des thèses partout dans loan, distribute and sell th es es le monde, à des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non sur support microforme, papier, électronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriété du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protège cette thèse. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation. -
Hermann Cohen - Kant Among the Prophets1
The Journal ofJewish Thought and Philosphy, Vol. 2, pp. 185-199 © 1993 Reprints available directly from the publisher Photocopying permitted by licence only Hermann Cohen - Kant among the Prophets1 Gillian Rose University of Warwick, UK The selective reception by general philosophy and social scientific methodology in the European tradition of the mode of neo- Kantianism founded by Hermann Cohen (1842-1918) has con- tributed to the widespread undermining of conceptual thinking in favour of the hermeneutics of reading. To assess Cohen's thought as a reading and re-originating of the Jewish tradition involves a predicament of circularity: for the question of reading and origin is not neutral but derives from the partial reception of the object addressed. The task of reassessment changes from a methodologi- cally independent survey to a challenge posed by current thought, unsure of its modernity or post-modernity, to re-establish contact with a formative but long-forgotten part of itself. No longer solely academic, this exercise will have to confront two especially difficult aspects of Cohen's thought. First, he did not "read" Kant, he destroyed the Kantian philosophy. In its place, he founded a "neo- Kantianism" on the basis of a logic of origin, dif- ference and repetition. As a logic of validity, this neo-Kantian math- esis is often at stake when its practitioners prefer to acknowledge 1 This paper was originally prepared for the Symposium, "The Playground of Textuality: Modern Jewish Intellectuals and the Horizon of Interpretation," First Annual Wayne State University Press Jewish Symposium, held in Detroit, 20-22 March, 1988. -
Hermann Cohen's Das Princip Der Infinitesimal-Methode
Hermann Cohen’s Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode: The History of an Unsuccessful Book Marco Giovanelli Abstract This paper offers an introduction to Hermann Cohen’s Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode (1883), and recounts the history of its controversial reception by Cohen’s early sympathizers, who would become the so-called ‘Marburg school’ of Neo-Kantianism, as well as the reactions it provoked outside this group. By dissecting the ambiguous attitudes of the best-known represen- tatives of the school (Paul Natorp and Ernst Cassirer), as well as those of several minor figures (August Stadler, Kurd Lasswitz, Dimitry Gawronsky, etc.), this paper shows that Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode is a unicum in the history of philosophy: it represents a strange case of an unsuccessful book’s enduring influence. The “puzzle of Cohen’s Infinitesimalmethode,” as we will call it, can be solved by looking beyond the scholarly results of the book, and instead focusing on the style of philosophy it exemplified. Moreover, the paper shows that Cohen never supported, but instead explicitly opposed, the doctrine of the centrality of the ‘concept of function’, with which Marburg Neo-Kantianism is usually associated. Long Draft 24/12/2015 Introduction Hermann Cohen’s Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode (Cohen, 1883) was undoubtedly an unsuccessful book. Its devastating reviews are customarily mentioned in the literature, but less known and perhaps more significant, is the lukewarm, and sometimes even hostile, reception the book received from Cohen’s early sympathizers. Some members of the group dissented publicly, while others expressed their discomfort in private correspondence. -
Hermann Cohen in Russian History of Philosophy to 100 Years Since Death of Marburg Philosopher
Peoples' Friendship University of Russia In association with Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University Hermann Cohen in Russian history of philosophy To 100 years since death of Marburg philosopher 4 June 5 June 2018 ., Moscow PROGRAMM Of international scientific conference Peoples' Friendship University of Russia Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences International scientific conference Hermann Cohen in Russian history of philosophy To 100 years since death of Marburg philosopher 4 June œ 5 June 2018 ., Moscow Conference program Moscow 2018 Steering committee board 1. Belov V.N., head of depart ent of ontology and theory of knowledge RUDN, Russia œ chair of steering co ittee( 2. Tzvyk V.A., dean of ,aculty of -umanities and .ocial .ciences RUDN, Russia œ co-chair of steering co ittee( 3. 1ank M., professor of Boston University, U.A œ e ber of steering co ittee. 4. 3opchukh 4., professor of institute of philosophy of University 56789:;7<9<= 4ublin, Poland œ e ber of steering co ittee( 5. Gershowitz U., professor of -ebrew University of Jerusale , Israel e ber of steering co ittee( 6. .okuler 1.A., professor of depart ent of ontology and theory of knowledge of philosophic depart ent of MGU, Russia œ secretary of steering co ittee. embers of Program committee 1. D itrieva N.A., .cientific Director I anuel 3ant Baltic ,ederal University, Russia œ chair person of Progra co ittee( 2. Dvorkin I..., professor -ebrew University of Jerusale , Israel œ co-chair of Progra co ittee( 3. Nizhnikov ..A., professor of depart ent of history of philosophy of ,aculty of -u anities and .ocial .ciences RUDN, Russia œ e 2er Progra co ittee( 4. -
Nietzsche's Critique of Kant's Thing in Itself
PENULTIMATE DRAFT OF A PAPER TO APPEAR IN NIETZSCHE-STUDIEN 2010. PLEASE QUOTE ONLY THE FINAL, PUBLISHED VERSION! Mattia Riccardi Nietzsche’s critique of Kant’s thing in itself 1 Abstract: This paper investigates the argument that substantiates Nietzsche’s refusal of the Kantian concept of thing in itself. As Maudemarie Clark points out, Nietzsche dismisses this notion because he views it as self-contradictory. The main concern of the paper will be to account for this position. In particular, the two main theses defended here are (a) that the argument underlying Nietzsche’s claim is that the concept of thing in itself amounts to the inconsistent idea of a propertyless thing and (b) that this argument is a sound one. Finally, I will show that the reading proposed allows a deflationary response to the objection that Nietzsche’s will to power is simply a new version of the post-Kantian thing in itself. Keywords: thing in itself, Kant, will to power, relational vs. intrinsic properties Zusammenfassung: Dieser Aufsatz untersucht die Argumentation, die Nietzsches Zurückweisung des kantischen Begriffs des Dings an sich untermauert. Wie Maudemarie Clark betont, verwirft Nietzsche diesen Begriff als selbstwidersprüchlich. Hauptanliegen des Aufsatzes ist, dies deutlich zu machen. Insbesondere werden folgende zwei Thesen vertreten: (a) dass das Nietzsches Position zugrundeliegende Argument darin besteht, der Begriff des Dings an sich sei der inkonsistente Begriff eines eigenschaftslosen Dings; (b) dass dieses Argument stichhaltig ist. Schließlich wird gezeigt, dass diese Interpretation eine deflationäre Antwort auf den Einwand ermöglicht, Nietzsches Wille zur Macht sei einfach eine neue Variante des postkantischen Dings an sich. -
Friedrich Albert Lange on Objective Inference Lydia Pattona a Department of Philosophy, Virginia Tech, Blacksburg, VA, USA
This article was downloaded by: [Patton, Lydia] On: 13 May 2011 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 937485231] Publisher Taylor & Francis Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37- 41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK History and Philosophy of Logic Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713812075 Anti-psychologism about Necessity: Friedrich Albert Lange on Objective Inference Lydia Pattona a Department of Philosophy, Virginia Tech, Blacksburg, VA, USA Online publication date: 11 May 2011 To cite this Article Patton, Lydia(2011) 'Anti-psychologism about Necessity: Friedrich Albert Lange on Objective Inference', History and Philosophy of Logic, 32: 2, 139 — 152 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/01445340.2010.541183 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2010.541183 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.