PRELIMINARY SYLLABUS Metaphysics And

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PRELIMINARY SYLLABUS Metaphysics And Hartford Seminary 77 Sherman Street, Hartford, CT 06105-2260 PRELIMINARY SYLLABUS Metaphysics and the Quest(ion) of God After Kant (TH-626 – Fall Semester 2016) Instructor: Prof. Dr. Fábio Henrique de Abreu Visiting Professor of Philosophical Theology and Philosophy of Religion Email: [email protected] COURSE DESCRIPTION The starting point for modern philosophy in general and the philosophy of religion in particular belongs to Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). It is well recognized in the secondary literature that Kant’s “Copernican Revolution” has placed traditional (pre-critical) metaphysics and, by extension, the philosophical problem of religion – including his critique of the metaphysical doctrine of God – under such pervasive criticism that religion is now threatened up to the point of becoming nothing more than an illusion. The best example of the powerful and influent character of the Kantian criticism of religion is, perhaps, Ludwig A. Feuerbach’s (1804-1872) understanding of religion as a human projection. One is no longer able to speak of God by means either of the authority of the Scriptures or through an appeal to any kind of supernatural source. The reality of God, as such, is now at stake. This course aims firstly at investigating, historically, the fundamental nature of Kant’s criticism both of religion and of the idea of God. Secondly, it will investigate some selected writings by the young Georg W. F. Hegel (1770-1831) and Friedrich D. E. Schleiermacher (1768-1834) as critical responses to Kant’s transcendental philosophical standpoint that have led to a consequent repositioning of the Kantian problematic on religion and the idea of God. Finally, the course will present the repercussions of this critical tradition in the contemporary – and basically German – philosophical and theological landscape and its significance for a critical reconstruction of the possibility of a meaningful discourse about God today. REQUIRED TEXTBOOKS KANT, Immanuel. Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998. ISBN-13: 978- 0521599641. HEGEL, Georg W. F. Early Theological Writings. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1975. ISBN-13: 978-0812210224. SCHLEIERMACHER, Friedrich D. E. On the Highest Good. (Schleiermacher Studies and Translations). Book 10. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press, 1992. ISBN-13: 978- 0773495852. Hartford Seminary 77 Sherman Street, Hartford, CT 06105-2260 SCHLEIERMACHER, Friedrich D. E. On Freedom. (Schleiermacher Studies and Translations). Book 9. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press, 1992. ISBN-13: 978- 0773495838. HENRICH, Dieter. The Unity of Reason: Essays on Kant’s Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994. ISBN-13: 978-0674929050. HENRICH, Dieter. “The Origins of the Theory of the Subject”. In: HONNETH, Axel et al. (Ed.). Philosophical Interventions in the Unfinished Project of Enlightenment. (Studies in Contemporary German Social Thought). Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992, p. 29- 87. ISBN-13: 978-0262581097. RECOMMENDED TEXTBOOKS ANDERSON, Pamela Sue and BELL, Jordan. (Ed.). Kant and Theology. London: T & T Clark, 2010. ISBN-13: 978-0567034151. BEISER, Frederick C. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. ISBN-13: 978-0521387118. BEISER, Frederick C. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. ISBN-13: 978-0521539388. BERKHOF, Hendrikus. Two Hundred Years of Theology: Report of a Personal Journey. Grand Rapids, MI.: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1993. ISBN-13: 978-0802804730. BLACKWELL, Albert L. Schleiermacher’s Early Philosophy of Life: Determinism, Freedom, and Phantasy. (Harvard Theological Studies 33). Chico, Calif.: Scholars Press, 1982. ISBN- 13: 978-0891305071. DANZ, Christian. Religion als Freiheitsbewußtsein: Eine Studie zur Theologie als Theorie der Konstitutionsbedingungen individueller Subjektivität bei Paul Tillich. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2000. ISBN-13: 978-3110169430. DESPLAND, Michel. Kant on History and Religion. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1973. ISBN-13: 978-0773501256. FREUNDLIEB, Dieter. Dieter Henrich and Contemporary Philosophy: The Return to Subjectivity. (Ashgate New Critical Thinking in Philosophy). Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Limited, 2003. ISBN-13: 978-0754613442. GRÄB, Wilhelm and SOCKNESS, Brent W. (Ed.). Schleiermacher, the Study of Religion, and the Future of Theology: A Transatlantic Dialogue. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2010. ISBN-13: 978-3110216332. GUYER, Paul. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. ISBN-13: 978-0521367684. Hartford Seminary 77 Sherman Street, Hartford, CT 06105-2260 GUYER, Paul. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006. ISBN-13: 978-0521529952. HENRICH, Dieter. “Fichte’s Original Insight”. In: CHRISTENSEN, Darrel. E. et al. (Ed.). Contemporary German Philosophy. Volume 1. University Park, PA: Penn State University Press, 1966/1990, 15-53. ISBN-13: 978-0271003368. HENRICH, Dieter. Between Kant and Hegel. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2008. ISBN-13: 978-0674027374. HÖFFE, Otfried. Immanuel Kant. Albany, NY.: State University of New York Press, 1994. ISBN-13: 978-0791420942. HÖFFE, Otfried. Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: The Foundation of Modern Philosophy. London/New York: Springer, 2009. ISBN-13: 978-9048127214. JAESCHKE, Walter. Reason in Religion: The Foundations of Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion. Berkeley/Oxford: University of California Press, 1990. ISBN-13: 978-0520065185. JAESCHKE, Walter and ARNDT, Andreas. Die Klassische Deutsche Philosophie nach Kant: Systeme der reinen Vernunft und ihre Kritik 1785-1845. München: Verlag C. H. Beck, 2012. ISBN-13: 978-3406630460. MARIÑA, Jacqueline. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Friedrich Schleiermacher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005. ISBN-13: 978-0521891370. NEUHOUSER, Frederick. Fichte’s Theory of Subjectivity. (Modern European Philosophy). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990. ISBN-13: 978-0521399388. PANNENBERG, Wolfhart. Theologie und Philosophie. Ihr Verhältnis im Lichte ihrer gemeinsamen Geschichte. Stuttgart: UTB, 1996. ISBN-13: 978-3825219253. PANNENBERG, Wolfhart. Metaphysics and the Idea of God. Grand Rapids, MI.: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 2001. ISBN-13: 978-0802836816. SCHAEFFLER, Richard. Religionsphilosophie. Freiburg/München: Verlag Karl Alber, 2002. ISBN-13: 978-3495480724. SCHLEIERMACHER, Friedrich D. E. On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers. (Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN-13: 978-0521479752. SCHLEIERMACHER, Friedrich D. E. Christian Faith (Two-Volume Set): A New Translation and Critical Edition. Philadelphia: Westminster John Knox Press, 2016. ISBN-13: 978- 0664226206. Or: SCHLEIERMACHER, Friedrich D. E. The Christian Faith. Berkeley: Apocryphile Press, 2011. ISBN-13: 978-1937002039. THANDEKA. The Embodied Self: Friedrich Schleiermacher’s Solution to Kant’s Problem of the Empirical Self. Albany, NY.: State University of New York Press, 1995. ISBN-13: 978- 0791425763. Hartford Seminary 77 Sherman Street, Hartford, CT 06105-2260 TILLICH, Paul. Systematic Theology. Volume Three: Life and Spirit, History and the Kingdom of God. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1976. ISBN-13: 978-0226803395. WAGNER, Falk. Was ist Religion: Studien zu ihrem Begriff und Thema in Geschichte und Gegenwart. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus Mohn, 1986. ISBN-13: 978-3579002675. WESTPHAL, Kenneth R. “Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Moral Worldview.” Philosophical Topics 19 (1991): 133-176. ASSESSMENT EXPECTATIONS During sessions students will read and present on assigned chapters and/or articles. Presentations have to be concise, no longer than 30 minutes. During the presentations, students are expected to be able to delineate with due precision the general outline and the main concepts advanced by the authors. Most of the required texts are available in the library, especially the most expensive ones. Other texts not available in the library will be provided by the instructor. The recommended literature will supplement the required books as supporting exegetical material. Students are not obliged, however, to purchase any of them. The recommended books will also be provided by the instructor during the course. A final essay, no longer than 15 pages and no less than 10 pages (bibliography and footnotes excluded), will be prepared by the students based on the required texts with the help of the supplementary literature provided during the course. IMPORTANT: Plagiarism, the failure to give proper credit for the words and ideas of another person, whether published or unpublished, is strictly prohibited. All written material submitted by students must be their own original work; where the words and ideas of others are used they must be acknowledged. Credit will not be given for work containing plagiarism, and plagiarism will lead to failure of a course. Please see the Hartford Seminary Catalogue for the full plagiarism policy. ATTENDANCE POLICY FOR WEEKLY CLASSES Attendance in class is required. If you know you will be unable to attend a class session please inform the professor in advance. Missing two sessions will result in an automatic lowering of your final grade by 10%. Missing three or more sessions will result in automatic failure of the course. EMAIL POLICY The instructor will use the official Hartsem student email addresses for all communications. Please check your Hartsem email account regularly. OFFICE HOURS Office hours will be scheduled by appointment. .
Recommended publications
  • Dieter Henrich's Turn
    The Problem of Subjectivity: Dieter Henrich’s Turn 189 The Problem of Subjectivity: Dieter Henrich’s Turn Gerhard Preyer The German philosopher Dieter Henrich has worked on the problem of subjectivity since the 1950s.1 In his lecture at the “Kolleg Friedrich Nietzsche der Stiftung Weimarer Klassik” (2003) he has reformulated the problem of subjectivity in the context of a revisionary approach. This is worth emphasiz- ing, since Henrich’s analysis is focused on the limits of the position of subjec- tivity in the world. He calls his turn a revisionary metaphysics because he sees subjectivity not as self-grounded but as part of an All-Einheit (all-unity), thus evoking a motive of Plato’s philosophy.2 In the present article, I will first deal with Henrich’s turn to the question of subjectivity. Secondly, I re-interpret his analysis of conscious self-reference (subjectivity) which starts from the condition of primary self-consciousness as immediate consciousness. Henrich also claims to give an answer to the mind-body problem in the context of the much changed questions of philosophy of mind since the 1950s. Thirdly, I consider Henrich’s view of the body (Leib) as a position in the world which goes along with subjectivity. Fourthly, this leads me to his discussion of the principle of consequence and of free choice as well as to the interplay between subjectiv- ity and practical self-reference considered as self-determination (Selbstbestim- mung) and self-relationship (Selbstverhältnisse).3 Studying the philosophical work of Henrich again I read it, in the current philosophical context, as a contribution to an existenzial phenomenology, given from the subject’s point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • Fichte's Position
    Fichte’s Position: Self-Awareness and the Space of Reasons Paul Franks I: Introduction Of all the famous figures in the history of philosophy, Johann Gottlieb Fichte may perhaps have the worst reputation. Others have been accused of equivocations, inconsistencies, non sequiturs and other blunders. But Fichte’s view has the distinction that it has regularly been described as verging upon insanity, sometimes even as attaining it. Here, for example, is Bertrand Russell: “Kant’s immediate successor, Fichte, abandoned ‘things in themselves’ and carried subjectivism to a point which seems almost to involve a kind of insanity. He holds that the Ego is the only ultimate reality, and that it exists because it posits itself; the non-Ego, which has a subordinate reality, also exists only because the Ego posits it. The Ego as a metaphysical concept easily became confused with the empirical Fichte . .”i Later, I will cite Jean Paul, a contemporary of Fichte’s, who also associates Fichteanism with a literally crazy subjectivism. Now I want to note that a view of Fichte surprisingly like Russell’s -- and indeed a view of the development of modern philosophy somewhat similar to Russell’s -- can also be found on what we Englishmen quaintly call the continent. Thus Heidegger, like Russell, sees the development of philosophy since Descartes as the ascent of subjectivism, and, again like Russell, Heidegger regards Fichte’s philosophy as a high-point of a regrettable journey.ii For all their differences, both Anglo-American and continental traditions of twentieth century philosophy have shared a common enemy: subjectivism.iii By subjectivism, I think it is fair to say, both traditions have meant the extension of the Cartesian view of the mind to the whole of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • FU/BEST Program
    FU/BEST Program Name: Dr. Detlef von Daniels Email address: [email protected] Course title: The Promise of German Philosophy: Between Kant and Hegel Course number: FU-BEST 9a Language of instruction: English Contact hours: 45 ECTS-Credits: 6 U.S. semester credits: 3 Course description Philosophy has constituted a central element in the development of modern German culture. In the late eighteenth century, German philosophy participated in the broader European Enlightenment culture, which has in turn been connected to the development of modern empirical science. Under the impression of the historical changes brought about by the French Revolution and by the ‘Industrial Revolution’ in Great Britain, a special constellation of German philosophy emerged at the end of the eighteenth century, which has deeply left its mark on subsequent philosophical thinking far beyond Germany. In the course, we follow the emergence and full deployment of German philosophy from its beginnings in Kant’s theoretical and moral philosophy to Hegel’s grand but fragile synthesis. We will also discuss the critique by the Young Hegelians as well as by the late Schelling, trying to understand the richness as well as the limitations of this tradition of German philosophy. The course is based upon contemporary attempts at rethinking a global philosophical perspective. Therefore, the contextual reading of key texts is related to contemporary feminist and postcolonial discussions. Course work/expectations Midterm exam: 20% Term-Paper: 25% Final Exam: 20% Attendance and participation: 25% (including weekly reading responses) Independent Project: 10% Student profile Second-semester sophomore or above Prerequisites Prior knowledge of philosophy is not required, however, an eagerness to engage with densely written texts is indispensable.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Transcendental Deduction
    Kant’s Transcendental Deduction Professors James Conant & Robert Pippin Spring 2010 *** Syllabus *** Description of the Seminar This seminar will be devoted to a close reading and discussion of Kant’s First Critique, focusing on the Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding. We will also explore carefully explore a handful of proposals for how to interpret the First Critique and especially the Transcendental Deduction, including especially those put forward by Allison, Strawson, and Strawson. We will end the course with a close look at Wilfrid Sellars’s and John McDowell’s respective interpretations of Kant, with special attention to how each of their own philosophies of perception inherit, modify, and explore Kant’s criticisms of traditional empiricism, and how each of them it rework a number of Kantian themes – most notably Kant’s conception of intuition and his account of the relation between intuitions and concepts. The aim of the course is both to use certain central texts of recent Kant commentary and contemporary analytic Kantian philosophy to illuminate some the central aspirations of Kant’s theoretical philosophy and to use certain central Kantian texts in which those aspirations were first pursued to illuminate some recent developments in epistemology and the philosophy of mind. Instructors James Conant Robert Pippin Office: Stuart 208 Office: Foster 307 Office Phone: 773 702 6146 Office Phone: 773 702 5453 e-mail: [email protected] e-mail: [email protected] 1 Texts All of the following textbooks have been ordered through the Seminary Co-op and are all required texts for the course: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Problems and Challenges in Gadamer's Hermeneutics
    Between Enlightenment and Romanticism: Some Problems and Challenges in Gadamer’s Hermeneutics KRISTIN GJESDAL* for post-analytical philosophers such as Richard Rorty and John McDowell, Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Truth and Method (1960) has played an important role in their battles against Cartesian epistemology.1 In this context, it is little known that when Gadamer started working on Truth and Method in the early 1930s, he did not want only to criticize the framework of modern epistemology. Rather, the initial intention of his work was to “demonstrate that art can convey truth.”2 In Gadamer’s view, such a demonstration could not be of a merely systematic na- ture, but also had to engage with the historical development of aesthetics; it had to overcome the way in which Kant and the romantics had come to deny art any significance as knowledge. Since the publication of Truth and Method, Gadamer’s discussion of art and aesthetics—his critique of Kant, the romantics, and the general philosophical paradigm that he terms ‘aesthetic consciousness’—has received only scant atten- tion.3 By contrast, the second and third parts of the work—addressing, respectively, 1For Rorty’s reading of Gadamer, see Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 357–95; and “Der Vorlesungsgast,” in Begegnungen mit Hans-Georg Gadamer, ed. Günter Figal, trans. Joachim Schulte (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2000), 87–92. For McDowell’s application of Gadamerian insights and concepts, see John McDowell, Mind and Nature (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1996), xi–xxiv and 108–26; and “Gadamer, Davidson, and the Ground of Understanding,” in Gadamer’s Century: Essays in Honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer [Gadamer’s Century], ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Rosenkranz's Report on Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit: a Short Analysis
    DePauw University Scholarly and Creative Work from DePauw University Philosophy Faculty publications Philosophy 3-2021 Rosenkranz's Report on Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit: A Short Analysis Daniel E. Shannon DePauw University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.depauw.edu/phil_facpubs Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Shannon, D. (2021). Rosenkranz’s Report on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Short Analysis. Academia Letters, Article 243. Doi: 10.20935/AL243 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholarly and Creative Work from DePauw University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarly and Creative Work from DePauw University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ACADEMIA Letters Rosenkranz’s Report on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Short Analysis Daniel Shannon Karl Rosenkranz was the editor-in-chief of Hegel’s Collected Works, vols. 1-12(1832-44). He wrote Hegel’s Life (1844) as a supplement to these Works.1 He has an advantage over most other commentators on Hegel. Not only did he speak with Hegel about his philosophy, but he also had access to his manuscripts, letters, and the recollections of students, family members, and acquaintances. Rosenkranz was himself an adept and prolific philosopher. He is remembered primarily today for his work on Hegel, but in his own right he is still considered for his Encyclopedia of Theological Sciences (1831), Pedagogy as System (1848)–which was translated into English under the title Philosophy of Education (1886)—Aesthetics of the Ugly (1853) and the Science of the Logical Idea (1858).2 By virtue of his close ties to Hegel and his own philosophical abilities he appears able to understand and express the complexity and subtly of Hegel’s philosophical thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism, Edited by David Pacini
    BOOK REVIEWS medieval thought has exerted a strong infl uence. This omission appears to have resulted from the editorial decision to spread discussion of issues in phi- losophy of religion over various chapters (analogous language in Ashworth, the existence of God in Menn, eternity and foreknowledge and necessity in Marenbon, creation in Sylla and Dobbs-Weinstein). This was not, in my opin- ion, a good idea. So important an intersection between medieval and contem- porary thought as philosophy of religion deserved its own chapter, where the reader could readily fi nd an account of medieval treatments not only of the topics just mentioned but also of the nature of faith, the divine attributes, the problem of evil, and so forth. Neil Lewis Georgetown University Philosophical Review, Vol. 115, No. 1, 2006 DOI 10.1215/00318108-2005-005 Dieter Henrich, Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism, edited by David Pacini. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003. liv + 341 pp. Recent decades have seen a surge of interest in the development of German philosophy from Kant to Hegel. A remarkable share of responsibility for this rests with Dieter Henrich, whose infl uence stems from his unequaled histori- cal learning and unfailing philosophical sophistication. In 1973, Henrich gave a course of lectures on German idealism at Harvard. David Pacini and others transcribed the lectures, Pacini edited the transcripts, and they have now been published as Between Kant and Hegel. Those looking for a broad introduction to Henrich’s approach will fi nd one that is both sophisticated and a pleasure to read.
    [Show full text]
  • The Copernican Turn in Early German Romanticism
    chapter 1 The Copernican Turn in Early German Romanticism Jane Kneller This essay addresses the complex relationship of early German romantic philosophy to the so-called “Copernican” turn Kant took in his critical phi- losophy. I defend the claim that the early German Romantics assumed Kant’s Copernican insight had been firmly established, and went on to expand and transform the critical philosophy into something uniquely their own and not subsumable under standard “realist/idealist” distinctions used to describe this period. I preface the argument by suggesting that early German Romanticism’s most innovative philosophical contributions are methodological rather than metaphysical, and that they represent philosophical “break” between Kant and German post-Kantian Idealism in much the same way that a musical intermezzo functions between larger movements in musical compositions. Section I applies the metaphor by suggesting that Kant’s Copernican Revolution represents the first movement of Classic German philosophy, setting the stage for early German Romanticism’s reception and transformation of it, particu- larly in the philosophical work of Friedrich von Hardenberg, known as Novalis. Section II draws conceptual connections and also points of departure between Novalis and Kant, and concludes in Section III that on balance the disconnects between the Copernican turn and early German Romanticism underscore the independence of the latter, and separates early German Romanticism in a fun- damental way from both Kantian and the post-Kantian Idealism. 1 Between Kant and Post-Kantian Idealism: Romanticism as Intermezzo The brilliant collaboration of writers, critics, and philosophers who shared philosophical dialogue and projects—the so-called “Jena Circle”—was short- lived: It lasted only from the mid-1790’s into the early 1800’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Figuring the Self Subject, Absolute, and Others in Classical German Philosophy
    SUNY Series in Philosophy George R . Lucas, Editor Figuring the Self Subject, Absolute, and Others in Classical German Philosophy David E. Klemm and Giinter Zoller, Editors State University of New York Press Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 1997 State University of New York Contents All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission . No part of this book may he stored in aa retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, Introduction vii photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the David E. Klenmi and Ganter Zbller prior permission in writing of the publisher . Pan 1 For information, address State University of New York Self and Subject Press, State University Plaza, Albany, NY, 12246 1 . Subjectivity and Individuality Production by E . Moore : Survey of a Problem 3 Manfred Frank Marketing by Fran Keneston Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data 2. Self as Matter and Form : Some Reflections on Kant's View of the Soul 31 Figuring the self : subject, absolute, and others in classical German Richard E. Aquila philosophy / David E . Klemm and Ganter Zoller, editors . p. cm. - (SUNY series in philosophy) 3. Kant and the Self: A Retrospective 55 Chiefly proceedings of a conference held Apr. 9-11, 1992, at the Karl Ameriks University of Iowa. Includes index . 4. An Eye for an I: Fichte's Transcendental Experiment 73 ISBN 0-7914-3199-1 (he : alk. paper) . - ISBN 0-7914-3200-9 (pbk .
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Manfred Frank, the Philosophical Foundations of Early
    Bryn Mawr Review of Comparative Literature Volume 5 Article 8 Number 2 Winter 2006 Winter 2006 Review of Manfred Frank, The hiP losophical Foundations of Early German Romanticism, trans. Elizabeth Millán-Zeibert. Azade Seyhan Bryn Mawr College Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.brynmawr.edu/bmrcl Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Recommended Citation Seyhan, Azade (2006). Review of "Review of Manfred Frank, The hiP losophical Foundations of Early German Romanticism, trans. Elizabeth Millán-Zeibert.," Bryn Mawr Review of Comparative Literature: Vol. 5 : No. 2 Available at: https://repository.brynmawr.edu/bmrcl/vol5/iss2/8 This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. https://repository.brynmawr.edu/bmrcl/vol5/iss2/8 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Seyhan: Seyhan on Frank Manfred Frank, The Philosophical Foundations of Early German Romanticism, trans. Elizabeth Millán-Zeibert. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2004. 286 pp. ISBN 0791459470. Reviewed by Azade Seyhan Bryn Mawr College The Philosophical Foundations of Early German Romanticism is the third part of a series of lectures by Manfred Frank that were originally published as Unendliche Annäherung: Die Anfänge der philosophischen Frühromantik. Frank, professor of philosophy at the University of Tübingen, has published extensively on the philosophical genesis of early German romanticism, known as the Frühromantik. This English translation by Elizabeth Millán- Zaibert comprises the final twelve of Frank's thirty-six lectures. In the "Introduction," Millán-Zeibert writes that the first part of the lectures treats the critique of Immanuel Kant's legacy by Johann Gottlieb Fichte and other philosophers whose Kant reception set the stage for the critical work of the Frühromantiker.
    [Show full text]
  • Modern Philosophy and the Emergence of Aesthetic Theory: Kant
    1 Modern philosophy and the emergence of aesthetic theory: Kant Self-consciousness, knowledge and freedom The importance attributed to aesthetic questions in recent philosophy becomes easier to grasp if one considers the reasons for the emergence of modern aes- thetic theory. Kant’s main work on aesthetics, the ‘third Critique’, the Critique of Judgement (CJ) (1790), forms part of his response to unresolved questions which emerge from his Critique of Pure Reason (CPR) (1781) and Critique of Practical Reason (1787).1 In order to understand the significance of the CJ one needs therefore to begin by looking at the first two Kantian Critiques.2 The essential problem they entail, which formed the focus of reactions to Kant’s work at the time, lies in establishing how the deterministic natural world, whose mechanisms are becoming more and more accessible to the methods of the natural sciences, relates to the world in which we understand ourselves as auton- omous beings. The third Critique tries to suggest ways of bridging the divide between these apparently separate worlds by giving an account of natural and artistic beauty, relating beauty to natural teleology, the purposiveness of indi- vidual organisms and the possible purposiveness of nature as a whole. In doing so, however, it threatens to undermine essential tenets of the first two Critiques. The third Critique is not least significant because of the ways in which it informs subsequent attempts in German Idealism to integrate Kant’s philos- ophy into an overall system, some of which give a major role to aesthetics. The CJ has, furthermore, become increasingly important in contemporary discus- sions of Kant’s work, appealing on the one hand to those who wish to question the perception of Kant’s enterprise as merely an exercise in legitimating the natural sciences, and on the other to those who see the need to extend the scope of epistemology if it is not to founder on the problems that become apparent in the first two Critiques.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Read the Development from Kant to Hegel
    Inquiry, Vol. 49, No. 1, 80–102, February 2006 The Question of System: How to Read the Development from Kant to Hegel PIRMIN STEKELER-WEITHOFER University of Leipzig, Germany (Received 31 October 2005) ABSTRACT In order to understand Hegel’s approach to philosophy, we need to ask why, and how, he reacts to the well-known criticism of German Romantics, like Novalis and Friedrich Schlegel, against philosophical system building in general, and against Kant’s system in particular. Hegel’s encyclopedic system is a topical ordering of categorically different ontological realms, corresponding to different conceptual forms of representation and knowledge. All in all it turns into a systematic defense of Fichte’s doctrine concerning the primacy of us as actors with respect to any knowledge claim or scientific theory. Hegel’s limitations of the principle of causality and of the possibility of using mathematical methods in science show, in fact, how a merely compatibilist solution of Kant’s third antinomy can be overcome. I. Criticism of philosophical theories Long before Wittgenstein criticized theory-building in philosophy, Friedrich Schlegel and Novalis, romantic followers of Fichte in Jena, had launched a similar critique against philosophical systems in their writings. Novalis says in a famous text with the working title ‘‘Pollen’’ (Blu¨thenstaub) that all those who construct ready-made systems in philosophy do so in order to avoid the difficult task of reflection. Furthermore, he adds that the more narrow- minded a system is, the more it will please the public. As examples, Novalis refers to the doctrines of Helvetius and Locke, which he calls ‘‘materi- alistic’’, and says that Kant’s system will always find more adherents than Fichte’s.1 Correspondence Address: Pirmin Stekeler-Weithofer, Universita¨t Leipzig, Institut fu¨r Philosophie, Beethovenstr.
    [Show full text]