Ment of Book 1, Part 4 of the 1739 a Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume (1711–1776)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ment of Book 1, Part 4 of the 1739 a Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume (1711–1776) 348 Book Reviews Donald C. Ainslie Hume’s True Scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015. Pp. xiv + 286. isbn 978-0-19-959386-6. Donald C. Ainslie’s Hume’s True Scepticism presents the first book-length treat- ment of Book 1, Part 4 of the 1739 A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume (1711–1776). In doing so, the volume represents an important accomplishment, and one can reasonably expect it to become required reading for those wishing to come to terms with Hume’s skepticism. Treatise 1.4 marks perhaps the most literary account of skeptical crisis in the western philosophical corpus—and also one of its most difficult. It is perhaps for this reason that the crisis is not reprised in the Enquiries or other later texts. Unpacking the logic and upshot of the dense passages of T 1.4 remains one of the most controversial but also one of the most important tasks of Hume studies, as well as of the study of skepti- cism per se. Ainslie’s contribution to that work is considerable. Ainslie’s line of interpretation is in the first place biographical. In 1734, Hume wrote to an unnamed physician in London how he had suffered “the Disease of the Learned,” brought on by his immersion in philosophical work, and that he had sought therapy from his intellectual paralysis in “Business & Diversion” (Letter 1:14, #3, in Hume 1932). In Ainslie’s view, the exposition of Treatise 1.4 was “inspired by the personal experiences detailed in” that letter (5). “The cli- max” of T 1.4, in Ainslie’s medicalized reading, “amounts to a nervous break- down” (218). Ainslie shows how “Medical theorists, from the Greeks onwards, linked scholarliness to melancholia” (12), and that “Hume would have known of a general link between melancholy, hypochondria, and the life of study from a variety of sources, both popular and more specialized” (13)—perhaps George Cheyne’s The English Malady (1733) or, in John Wright’s (1980) view, Mandev- ille’s 1730 Treatise on the Hypochonodriack and Hysterick Diseases (Mandeville 1976). Hume would have also known that exercise and sociable concourse were commonly prescribed remedies. The idea that skepticism marks a kind of self- induced madness has also been advanced recently by Lisa Levers (2015), which for her explains why Hume answers the skeptical moment not with argument but with therapy. More philosophically, Ainslie distinguishes his own reading from four other general lines of interpretation that have characterized the Hume literature. (1) “Skeptical” readings, such as that of James Beattie and most of Hume’s earli- est interpreters have in Ainslie’s nomenclature argued that the skeptical sub- version of reason and the senses is correct and that therefore we ought not to invest what they show us with belief—even though we cannot do so. (2) “Naturalistic” readings such as those of Norman Kemp Smith (1905) and Don © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2018 | doi 10.1163/22105700-20181303Downloaded from Brill.com09/27/2021 07:24:16AM via free access <UN> Book Reviews 349 Garrett (1997) are, in contrast, anti-skeptical. In their view, Hume invests the way nature overwhelms skepticism’s negative conclusions with positive epis- temic significance. Nature, properly mixed with reason, entitles reason and be- lief. (3) Dialectical readings such as those of Annette Baier (1991) and Donald W. Livingston (1984, 1989) read the skeptical crisis as a moment on the way to a better non-skeptical view. (4) Moral interpretations of Hume’s skepticism, such as those of Michael Ridge (2003) read Hume as advocating skepticism not because it is logically compelling but instead because it serves the moral projects of opposing religious and political pathologies. Ainslie’s more “philosophical” interpretation of Hume’s true skepticism reads it as making positive discoveries about the epistemic and logical limits of philosophical inquiry that nevertheless endorse reason, science, and the vulgar beliefs of common life. Ainslie argues that Hume discovers that the traditional philosophical project of self-understanding through “reflection” is intrinsically problematic, that it cannot transcend common life and that at- tempts to surpass those limitations inevitably lead to incoherence, crisis, and “false philosophy.” It is a moral Ainslie emphasizes by placing François Lem- oyne’s 1728 painting of “Narcissus” staring into his own reflection on the jack- et of the book. Ainslie’s is, however, not an entirely new line of interpretation. Barry Stroud preceded Ainslie in 1977, writing in a similar albeit narrow- er vein that for Hume, “Philosophical reflection on the nature of perception inevitably leads to scepticism” (115). Yves Michaud concurred in 1985 report- ing that while he found at first blush that Hume’s “skepticism stemmed from the defects in the analysis of natural beliefs and from the deliberate attack against metaphysical systems,” he later came “to realise that it also is the result of this self-reference of philosophical research: we do not know how to assess our philosophical beliefs themselves” (36). Michaud followed this claim with another similar to Ainslie’s about Hume’s return to common life, maintaining that turning away from reflection “implies that we stop insisting on the radical unsteadiness of beliefs and that we do not scrutinize any longer the puzzling self-reference of philosophical statements. Actually, …the escape from pyr- rhonism requires a relative blindness to the question of the nature of philo- sophical inquiry and, on the contrary, a renewed dogmaticism [sic] concerning the certainty of the science of human nature qua empirical science” (46). Mar- tin Bell in 2002 also diagnosed “the reflective standpoint” itself as the cause of “sceptical doubts” (184), but he maintained that at least in “one species” of philosophy (i.e., the natural science of the “anatomist”) “natural belief can be harmonized with profound reflection” (185). Ainslie’s exposition exceeds these precedents, however, not only in the detail and complexity of his textanalyse but also in the way he distinguishes international journal for the study of skepticismDownloaded 8 (2018) from 343-353Brill.com09/27/2021 07:24:16AM via free access <UN> 350 Book Reviews Hume’s account of reflection from Locke’s. While others such as Malebranche hold that reflection can take a (a) detached, virtually transcendent position (b) in relation to the field of perception as a whole, Ainslie finds (§4.3) Hume arguing instead that reflection discovers that it can achieve no such position. Instead reflection must remain “immersed” (133, 253). Ainslie finds in this remark from the “Introduction” to the Treatise a prefig- uring summary of what he determines to be Hume’s limiting objective in T 1.4: “Moral philosophy has, indeed, this peculiar disadvantage, which is not found in natural, that in collecting its experiments, it cannot make them purposely, with premeditation, and after such a manner as to satisfy itself concerning ev- ery particular difficulty which may arise. When I am at a loss to know the ef- fects of one body upon another in any situation, I need only put them in that situation, and observe what results from it. But should I endeavour to clear up after the same manner any doubt in moral philosophy, by placing myself in the same case with that which I consider, ’tis evident this reflection and premedi- tation would so disturb the operation of my natural principles, as must render it impossible to form any just conclusion from the phaenomenon” (Intro 10, in Hume 2007). Cicero had maintained along similar lines that “it is possible that [the organs of the body] are changed by the process of dissection and uncov- ering” (Academica [Acad.] 2.39.122, in Cicero 2006); and so it goes for Hume’s anatomy of the mind. The proper lesson Hume draws from this insight, Ainslie concludes, is that we should both (a) retreat from philosophical self-reflection into a standard, dogmatic, empirical science and (b) abandon the philosophical attempt to justify or locate an ultimate ground for our epistemic claims about the world. The negative theses about reason and the senses are not the lessons of skepti- cism. Rather, escaping through the horns of the so-called “dangerous dilemma” (T 1.4.7.6), the true skeptical upshot is a gain in self-understanding that philo- sophical self-reflection is internally incoherent but that empirical science is epistemically sound (204), even though it must remain ultimately unjustified. We must suffer an “irremediable vulgarity” about perception (241; a position influenced by Livingston 1984), while also accepting that we cannot penetrate into nature “beyond human experience” (242; following Kenneth Winkler’s 1991 anti-New Humean position). Ainslie argues that for Hume the vulgar are guilty of a “constitutive” but not an “epistemic” error with regard perceptual objects. Mistaking the image of a man on a television screen for the real man it depicts is a constitutive “illu- sion” but not an epistemic error, since one nevertheless, says Ainslie, does in that situation still know the real man (107–108). Of course, one can know the real man in such a situation—or not. Ainslie does not explain how we can international journal for the study of skepticismDownloaded from 8 Brill.com09/27/2021 (2018) 343-353 07:24:16AM via free access <UN> Book Reviews 351 decide whether or not the vulgar actually do know the real man. In the case of a television screen, one can go to the studio and check. One can compare the television-screen-man with the actual-man. With the screen of perception, however, as Hume acknowledges, one cannot (T 2.2.6.2). As Hume famously writes: “Let us fix our attention out of ourselves as much as possible: Let us chace our imagination to the heavens, or to the utmost limits of the universe; we never really advance a step beyond ourselves, nor can conceive any kind of existence, but those perceptions, which have appear’d in that narrow compass.
Recommended publications
  • Hume's Objects After Deleuze
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School March 2021 Hume's Objects After Deleuze Michael P. Harter Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Harter, Michael P., "Hume's Objects After Deleuze" (2021). LSU Master's Theses. 5305. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/5305 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME’S OBJECTS AFTER DELEUZE A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Michael Patrick Harter B.A., California State University, Fresno, 2018 May 2021 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Human beings are wholly dependent creatures. In our becoming, we are affected by an incredible number of beings who aid and foster our growth. It would be impossible to devise a list of all such individuals. However, those who played imperative roles in the creation of this work deserve their due recognition. First, I would like to thank my partner, Leena, and our pets Merleau and the late Kiki. Throughout the ebbs and flows of my academic career, you have remained sources of love, joy, encouragement, and calm.
    [Show full text]
  • Elizabeth S. Radcliffe Department of Philosophy William & Mary P.O
    Curriculum Vitae, September 2019 Elizabeth S. Radcliffe Department of Philosophy William & Mary P.O. Box 8795 Williamsburg, VA 23187-8795 Office: James Blair Hall 134 · Department Phone: 757-221-2716 · E-mail: [email protected] Webpage: http://wmpeople.wm.edu/site/page/eradcliffe/home EDUCATION Ph.D. in Philosophy, Cornell University, 1985 (Adviser: Nicholas L. Sturgeon) M.A. in Philosophy, Cornell University, 1980 B.A. in Philosophy, Fort Hays State University, summa cum laude, 1977 ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS Tenure-Track & Tenured Appointments The College of William and Mary, Professor of Philosophy, 2009-present Santa Clara University, Professor of Philosophy, 2006-2009 Santa Clara University, Associate Professor of Philosophy, 1996-2006 Santa Clara University, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 1989-96 Visiting & Temporary Appointments UNC-Chapel Hill, Visiting Scholar, Fall 1991 UNC-Chapel Hill, Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Spring 1992 University of Southern California, Lecturer in Philosophy, 1988-89 Loyola Marymount University, Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 1987-88 UCLA, Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Summer 1986 California State University, Los Angeles, part-time Lecturer in Philosophy, 1985-86 Fort Hays State University, part-time Instructor in Philosophy, 1982-83 MAJOR ADMINISTRATIVE POSITIONS The College of William & Mary, Department Chair, 2013-14, 2015-18 Hume Society President, 2010-2012 (calendar years, inclusive) Santa Clara University, Department Chair 2003-08 Co-editor and Managing
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae RICHARD H
    Curriculum Vitae RICHARD H. DEES Department Department of Philosophy University of Rochester P.O. Box 270078 Rochester, NY 14627-0078 Phone: (585)-275-8110 Current position Associate Professor of Philosophy, Neurology, and Medical Humanities Chair, Interdisciplinary Cluster in Health and Human Values University of Rochester Areas of Specialization Social and Political Philosophy Medical Ethics P Public Health Ethics History of Moral and Political Philosophy Areas of Competence Ethics Feminist Philosophy History of Modern Philosophy Publications Book Trust and Toleration (London: Routledge, 2004). Articles 1. “Moral Philosophy and Moral Enhancements.” American Journal of Bioethics: Neuroscience, forthcoming. 2. with Ronnie Guillet, “Will My Baby Walk?: The Predictive Value of Cranial Imaging,” Neurology 76 (2011): 2048-49. 3. “Rawlsian ‘Neutrality’ and Enhancement Technologies,” American Journal of Bioethics: Neuroscience 1, no. 2 (2010): 54-55. 4. with Jennifer Kwon, “Pediatric Screening and the Public Good.” Cerebrum 2009, ed. Dan Gordon (New York: Dana Press, 2009), pp. 121-29. See http://www.dana.org/news/cerebrum/detail.aspx?id=14300 5. with Eric Singer, “KidneyMatch.com: The Ethics of Solicited Organ Donations,” Journal of Clinical Ethics 19 (2008): 141-49. Winner of the 2008 Library Award 1 2 from the Rochester Academy of Medicine for the best essay in ethics or the history of medicine. 6. “‘One of the Finest and Most Subtile Inventions’: Hume’s Theory of Government,” in Blackwell Companion to Hume, ed. Elizabeth Radcliffe (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2008), 388-405. 7. “Soldiers as Agents,” American Journal of Bioethics 8 no. 2 (2008): 46-47. 8. "Of Socinians and Homosexuals: Trust and the Limits of Toleration," in Toleration on Trial, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Misreading Skepticism in the Long Eighteenth Century: Studies in the Rhetoric of Assent
    Misreading Skepticism in the Long Eighteenth Century: Studies in the Rhetoric of Assent By Adam Sneed A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (English Language and Literature) in the University of Michigan 2018 Doctoral Committee: Professor Marjorie Levinson, Chair Professor Gregg Crane Associate Professor Sean Silver Professor Silke Maria-Weineck Adam Sneed [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0002-9205-1715 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My first thanks must be to the University of Michigan for the opportunity and privilege to pursue the life of the mind. I am deeply grateful for the tremendous and constant support provided by faculty and staff of the UM English Department. I am indebted to the Rackham School of Graduate Studies for two timely dissertation fellowships and to the U-M LSA International Institute for the opportunity to pursue archival research in Scotland. I thank the members of my dissertation committee: Sean Silver for providing a constant model of passionate, creative scholarship; Gregg Crane for first dislodging me from a neo-Kantian, Skeptical perspective; Silke Maria-Weineck for cheering on the polemic; and my wonderful chair, Marjorie Levinson, for supporting and encouraging me at every stage of the dissertation process and for bearing with me as the project evolved over time. I would like to thank my dear friends Samuel Heidepriem, Emily Waples, Logan Scherer, Kristin Fraser Geisler, Ryan Hampstead, Joe Chapman, Anthony Losapio, Sarah Mass, Alice Tsay, Lizzy Mathie, and Amrita Dhar for their love and support through the years in Ann Arbor. Special thanks to my dear friends Kathryne Bevilacqua, John Paul Hampstead, and Julia Hansen, who read and commented on drafts in the final stages.
    [Show full text]
  • Pleasure As the Standard of Virtue in Hume's Moral Philosophy
    Running:left: PACIFIC PLEASURE PHILOSOPHICAL AS THE STANDARD QUARTERLY OF VIRTUE IN HUME’S PLEASURE AS THE STANDARD OF VIRTUE IN HUME’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY1 by JULIA DRIVER Abstract: David Hume provides several accounts of moral virtue, all of which tie virtue to the experience of pleasure in the spectator. Hume believed that the appropriate pleasure for determinations of virtue was pleasure corrected by “the general point of view.” I argue that common ways of spelling this out leave the account open to the charge that it cannot account adequately for mistaken judgments of virtue. I argue that we need to see Hume as offering both a metaphysics and an epistemology of virtue, and that Hume’s account of virtue can adequately account for mistakes if he is understood as offering a definition of virtue tied to pleasure, but pleasure understood externally. But in many orders of beauty, particularly those of the finer arts, it is requisite to employ much reasoning, in order to feel the proper sentiment; and a false relish may frequently be corrected by argument and reflection. There are just grounds to conclude, that moral beauty partakes much of this latter species, and demands the assistance of our intellectual faculties, in order to give it a suitable influence on the human mind (EPM, 173).2 David Hume provides several distinct definitions of moral virtue: (V1) “. whatever mental action or quality gives to a spectator the pleasing sentiment of approbation” (EPM, 289). And, (V2) “. virtue . is a quality of the mind agreeable to or approved of by every one, who considers or con- templates it” (EPM, 261n) Even more simply, (V3) “.
    [Show full text]
  • Interoffice MEMORANDUM To: Senate Committee for Quality Assurance From: Anthony Clarke, Assistant V.P
    Office of Assistant Vice-President (Program Quality Assurance) x54124 interoffice MEMORANDUM to: Senate Committee for Quality Assurance from: Anthony Clarke, Assistant V.P. (PQA) subject: Periodic Review of the Department of Philosophy date: 12 March 2013 Please find attached the documents for the periodic review of the Department of Philosophy: Final Assessment Report, the Executive Summary which includes the responses of the Chair and Dean, and the responses of the Chair, Dean, and Provost as separate documents. As per section IV.4.A.(vii) of our IQAP for the review of departments and schools, the Executive Summary has been prepared for the information of Senate, and submission to the Ontario Universities Council for Quality Assurance. SENATE COMMITTEE FOR QUALITY ASSURANCE PERIODIC REVIEW OF THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY EXECUTIVE SUMMARY of FINAL ASSESSMENT REPORT March 2013 Membership of Internal Review Subcommittee (IRS) External Reviewers: Dr. Andrew Hunter, Ryerson University Dr. Eduardo Mendieta, Stony Brook University, New York Facilitator: Dr. Michèle Preyde, The Internal Review Committee (IRC) received the Final Assessment Report for the Department of Philosophy from the IRS on 05 February 2013. The IRC now presents an Executive Summary of the review, which includes the following: - Introduction - Summary of the review process - Review Committee’s recommendations - Administrative responses to the report from the Chair, Dean, and Provost INTRODUCTION The Department of Philosophy is a community of dedicated teachers and productive philosophical researchers. It was founded in 1965 with an initial complement of five male faculty (John Bruce (chair), Brian Calvert, Michael Ruse, Donald Stewart, George Todd) which quickly grew: in 1975 there were 21 regular faculty (1 female).
    [Show full text]
  • John I. Biro Education 1957-59 City of Westminster College, London 1961
    John I. Biro Education 1957-59 City of Westminster College, London 1961-65 University of Nottingham B.A. (Honours) in Philosophy, 1964 1968-73 Syracuse University M.A. in Philosophy, 1971 (Thesis: The Place of Rational Argument in Moral Disputes) Ph.D. in Philosophy, 1973 (Dissertation: Meaning, Speech-Acts and Intentions) Academic appointments 1964-5 Lecturer in liberal studies, Nottingham Regional College of Technology 1965-6 Lecturer in liberal studies, South-west Essex Technical College (London) 1967-8 Deputy Warden, Huntercombe Manor Adult Education Centre (Buckinghamshire) 1969-72 Teaching assistant, Department of Philosophy, Syracuse University 1972-3 Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, Syracuse University 1973-5 University Post-doctoral Fellow, University of Auckland 1975-6 Acting assistant professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Oklahoma 1976-81 Assistant professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Oklahoma 1978 Visiting lecturer, Victoria University of Wellington 1981-5 Associate professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Oklahoma 1981-9 Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Oklahoma; Chair, 1985-89 1989-98 Professor and Chair, Department of Philosophy, University of Florida 1989- Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Florida Fellowships and awards University of Oklahoma, Arts and Sciences Summer Research Fellow, 1980 NEH Summer Fellow, Institute on Psychology and the Philosophy of Mind, 1981 Centre for Cognitive Science, University of Western Ontario, Research Associate, Spring, 1983 University of Oklahoma, Associates Distinguished Lecturer, 1984-5, 1988-9 NEH Summer Fellow, Institute on Epistemology, 1986 ACLS travel grant, 1987 (declined) CNPq (Research Council of Brazil) travel grant, 1987 University of Oklahoma, Faculty Development Award, Summer, 1988 University of Edinburgh, Fellow, Institute for Advanced Studies in the Humanities, May-July, 1990 Humanities Scholarship Enhancement Award, University of Florida, 2003 Papers 1.
    [Show full text]
  • STEPHEN DARWALL Department of Philosophy, Yale University, P.O
    STEPHEN DARWALL Department of Philosophy, Yale University, P.O. Box 208306, New Haven, CT 06520-8306 (203) 432-1672 (office) • (734) 709-8803 (cell) • [email protected] • www.yale.edu/darwall EDUCATION B.A., YALE UNIVERSITY, 1968, magna cum laude, Phi Beta Kappa, Honors in Philosophy Ph.D., UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH, 1972 EMPLOYMENT YALE UNIVERSITY Andrew Downey Orrick Professor, 2008- (Chair, 2013-2017) UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN John Dewey Distinguished University Professor Emeritus, 2008- John Dewey Distinguished University Professor, 2007-2008 John Dewey Collegiate Professor, 2000-2007 Professor, 1984- (Chair, 1988-1993, 1999-2002, Associate Chair, 1987-88, Director of Graduate Studies, 1985-86, 95-96) Visiting Associate Professor, 1982 UNIVERSITY OF NORTH CAROLINA AT CHAPEL HILL Professor, 1983-84 Associate Professor, 1977-83 (Acting Chair, 1981) Assistant Professor, 1972-77 (Assistant Chair, 1976-77) TELLURIDE ASSOCIATION/UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN Summer program for academically-talented high school students from across the nation: “J. S. Mill: Ethics, Aesthetics, and Society,” Summer 1998 HONORS, GRANTS, AND AWARDS Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 2001- Past President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 2004-05 President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 2003-04 Vice-President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 2002-2003 Stanley Grean Distinguished Visiting Professor of Philosophy, Ohio University, Spring, 2003 Nominee for Vice-President, American Philosophical
    [Show full text]
  • Bell Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Jeffrey A. Bell Departmental address and phone Home address and phone History and Political Science 557 Pelican Ridge Drive Southeastern Louisiana University Madisonville, LA 70447 Hammond, LA 70402-0895 (985) 549-3918 email: [email protected] Areas of Specialization European philosophy since Kant, Deleuze, Hume, Spinoza, intellectual history, political theory, aesthetics. Education: Ph.D., Philosophy, Tulane University, 1992. A.B., Philosophy, Occidental College, 1985. Publications: Books - Authored Deleuze’s Hume: Philosophy, Culture and the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2009). Philosophy at the Edge of Chaos: Gilles Deleuze and the Philosophy of Difference (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2006). The Problem of Difference: Phenomenology and Poststructuralism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1998). Books - Edited Deleuze and Things, editor, with Levi Bryant (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, forthcoming). Deleuze and History, editor, with Claire Colebrook (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2009). Industrialization and Imperialism: 1800-1914. A Biographical Dictionary, editor (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 2002). Manuscripts in Preparation Spinoza and the Problem of History Conceptual Nomadism: an Intellectual History of Philosophy since Kant Articles – Peer-Reviewed “Between Realism and Anti-Realism: Deleuze and the Spinozist Tradition in Philosophy,” in Deleuze Studies 5.1, March, 2011: pp. 1-17. “Beyond Beautiful and Ugly: Non-dual Thinking and Aesthetic Theory,” in Analysis and Metaphysics, Volume 9, 2010: pp. 19-34. “Charting the Road of Inquiry: Deleuze’s Humean Pragmatics and the Challenge of Badiou,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 44(3), 2006: pp. 399-425. "The Director-function: Auteur theory and Poststructuralism," Fotogenia (Vol. 3, 1998). Translated into Italian and published under the title, “La funzione regista.
    [Show full text]
  • Online Access to Essential Research in the Humanities!
    Online access to essential research in the humanities! Browse dozens of scholarly journals, series, and conference proceedings in applied ethics, philosophy, and religious studies. Enjoy online research in huge selections of material dating back to 1890. All articles are fulltext searchable and OpenURL ready. Many titles in the following categories: and free page previews are available to non- subscribers. Open access provided for • Analytic Philosophy select titles. Content is displayed in either • Ancient Philosophy HTML or PDF format. Institutions may order • Applied Philosophy single titles, bundles, or the entire collection. • Business and Professional Ethics Pricing is modest, and multi-campus and • Catholic Tradition consortia pricing is available. • Conference Proceedings • Contemporary Philosophy • Continental Philosophy • General Interest • History of Philosophy • Major Philosophers • Philosophy and Religion • Semiotics • Social and Political Philosophy • Teaching Philosophy Fulltext E-Collection – hosted by the Philosophy Documentation Center Since 1966 the Philosophy Documentation Center (PDC) has earned a reputation for excellence with the non-profit publication of scholarly journals, series, and conference proceedings, and reference works. We also provide membership and publishing services for learned societies in philosophy and related Coverage expands as new issues are fields. Our goal is to increase access to published. Subscribers have access to current humanities scholarship in a fair and issues and complete archives. Free search sustainable manner. Philosophy Documentation Center, P.O. Box 7147, Charlottesville, Virginia 22906-7147 USA, www.pdcnet.org Over 200 titles in English and other languages. 200 ,000+ articles, reviews, and other documents! Most titles available exclusively through PDC. www.pdcnet.org /ecollection •The Acorn (Vol. 1, 1986, to present) •The New Scholasticism (Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Kevin Meeker ADDRESS Department of Philosophy Kmeekeratsouthalabamadotedu 5991 USA DR N RM124 (251) 460-6248 University of South Alabama Mobile, AL 36688
    Kevin Meeker ADDRESS Department of Philosophy kmeekerATsouthalabamaDOTedu 5991 USA DR N RM124 (251) 460-6248 University of South Alabama Mobile, AL 36688 POSITIONS Tenured Full Professor of Philosophy, University of South Alabama (8/2013-present) Tenured Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of South Alabama (8/2004-8/2013) Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of South Alabama (8/1999–8/2004) Post-Doctoral Research Fellow in Epistemology in Amsterdam with the Faculteit der Wijsbegeerte (Philosophy) at the Vrije Universiteit (Free University) (1998-1999) EDUCATION PhD, Philosophy 1998 University of Notre Dame Dissertation: Knowledge and Norms: A Defense of Epistemic Justification Director: Philip L. Quinn MA, Philosophy 1994 University of Notre Dame BA, Summa Cum Laude, 1991 Wheaton College, Wheaton, Illinois Major: Philosophy (Departmental Honors) AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Epistemology, Early Modern Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion AREAS OF COMPETENCY Metaphysics, Ethics, Logic, Philosophy of Science PUBLICATIONS BOOKS Hume’s Radical Scepticism and the Fate of Naturalized Epistemology (Palgrave Macmillan, 2013) The Philosophical Challenge of Religious Diversity, edited with Philip L. Quinn (Oxford University Press, 2000) REFEREED PAPERS “Ethics and Epistemology in Hume”, The European Legacy 18, 4 (2013): 457-466. “Quine on Hume and the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction”, Philosophia 39,2 (2011): 369- 373. “Skeptics without Borders”, (co-authored with Ted Poston) American Philosophical Quarterly (July 2010) 47, 3:223-238.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Affinities Between Hume and Kierkegaard
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Jyrki Kivelä On the Affinities Between Hume and Kierkegaard Academic dissertation to be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII (Main Building, Unioninkatu 34), on the 16th of March, 2013 at 10 o’clock. Filosofisia tutkimuksia Helsingin yliopistosta Filosofiska studier från Helsingfors universitet Philosophical Studies from the University of Helsinki Publishers: Theoretical Philosophy and Philosophy (in Swedish) Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies Social and Moral Philosophy Department of Political and Economic Studies P.O. box 24 (Unioninkatu 40 A) 00014 University of Helsinki Finland Editors: Panu Raatikainen Tuija Takala Bernt Österman Jyrki Kivelä On the Affinities Between Hume and Kierkegaard ISBN 978-952-10-8613-7 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-8614-4 (PDF) ISSN 1458-8331 Kopio Niini Oy Helsinki 2013 Contents Acknowledgements..............................................................................................................................7 List of Abbreviations and Methods of Citation....................................................................................8 1. Introduction....................................................................................................................................14 1.1 Background..............................................................................................................................14
    [Show full text]