Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection. -
The Coherence of Stoic Ontology
UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title The Coherence of Stoic Ontology Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3wg7m1w0 Author de Harven, Vanessa Publication Date 2012 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Prof. Dorothea Frede, Co-chair Prof. Klaus Corcilius, Co-chair Prof. A.A. Long Spring 2012 Abstract The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professors Dorothea Frede and Klaus Corcilius, Co-chairs Any thoroughgoing physicalist is challenged to give an account of immaterial entities such as thoughts and mathematical objects. The Stoics, who eagerly affirmed that only bodies exist, crafted an elegant solution to this challenge: not everything that is Something (ti) exists. Rather, some things have a derivative mode of reality they call subsistence: these entities are non-existent in that they are not themselves solid bodies, but they are nonetheless Something physical because they depend on bodies for their subsistence. My dissertation uncovers the unifying principles of Stoic subsistence, and shows how they can account for thoughts and other immaterial entities without running afoul of their physicalist commitments. While all commentators agree that the Stoics posited Something as the highest category of being, they have failed to find a coherent physicalist account of Stoic ontology. -
Nous As the Ground of Aristotle's Metaphysics?
Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1993 Nous as the Ground of Aristotle's Metaphysics? John J. Cleary Boston College Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Cleary, John J., "Nous as the Ground of Aristotle's Metaphysics?" (1993). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 164. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/164 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Nous as the Ground of Aristotle's Metaphysics? — John J. Cleaiy Introduction: This paper explores the implications of Aristotle's puzzling suggestions that the possibility of first philosophy somehow depends on whether part of the soul is separable from material body. My Conjecture1 is that for Aristotle the science of metaphysics depends on a special activity of nous that grasps die self-identical essences which are objects of first philosophy, as distinct from physics and mathematics. From Aristotle's perspective, of course, it is the existence of such essences that makes metaphysics possible, but it is arguable that without a corresponding mode of cognition this would not be a human science. It is a moot question whether it could be a divine science either, though one can argue that for Aristotle the divine mode of cognition, involving the complete identity of knower and known, represents the ideal to which human noetic activity aspires. -
Aristotle's Theory of Powers
Aristotle’s Theory of Powers by Umer Shaikh A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2019 Doctoral Committee: Professor Victor Caston, chair Professor Sara Abhel-Rappe Professor David Manley Professor Tad Schmaltz Umer Shaikh [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0002-8062-7932 © Umer Shaikh 2019 TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract ....................................... v Chapter 1 Introduction ................................... 1 1.1 The Question ............................... 1 1.2 Powers and Dispositions ......................... 2 1.3 Remark on Translation and Texts .................... 3 1.4 Preliminary Answers ........................... 3 1.4.1 Powers are Efficient Causes ................... 4 1.4.2 Powers and Change ....................... 5 1.4.3 Being in Potentiality and Possibility .............. 6 1.4.4 The Foundation of Modality .................. 8 1.4.5 Possibilities from Powers .................... 9 1.4.6 Conclusion ............................ 11 1.5 Remarks About Scope of Discussion and About the Development of the δύναμις Concept ........................... 12 1.5.1 Scope ............................... 12 1.5.2 Δύναμις in Various Texts .................... 12 1.5.3 Previous Attempts to Find Consistency ............ 18 1.5.3.1 Kenny .......................... 18 1.5.3.2 Hintikka ......................... 21 1.5.4 Drawing Some Morals ..................... 22 2 Powers and Efficient Causation ......................... 24 2.1 -
Plotinus' Epistemology and His Reading of the Theaetetus
Plotinus' epistemology and his reading of the Theaetetus Sara Magrin Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal July 2009 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Copyright Sara Magrin 2009 Abstract: Plotinus' epistemology and his reading of the Theaetetus The thesis offers a reconstruction of Plotinus’ reading of the Theaetetus, and it presents an account of his epistemology that rests on that reading. It aims to show that Plotinus reads the Theaetetus as containing two anti-sceptical arguments. The first argument is an answer to radical scepticism, namely, to the thesis that nothing is apprehensible and judgement must be suspended on all matters. The second argument is an answer to a more moderate form of scepticism, which does not endorse a universal suspension of judgement, but maintains nonetheless that scientific knowledge is unattainable. The first chapter opens with a reconstruction of Plotinus’ reading of Theaet., 151e-184a, where Socrates examines the thesis that knowledge is sensation in light of Protagoras’ epistemology. In this chapter it is argued that Plotinus makes a polemical use of the discussion of Protagoras’ epistemology. Plotinus takes Plato to show that Protagoras’ views imply radical scepticism; and he attack the Stoics’ epistemological and ontological commitments by arguing that they imply Protagoras’ views, and thus lead to radical scepticism, too. The second chapter examines Plotinus’ interpretation of the ontology of the Timaeus. In Theaet., 151e-184a Plato shows that Protagoras’ epistemology leads to radical scepticism by arguing that it implies an allegedly Heracleitean conception of the sensible world. -
SAGP Newsletter 1999-2000.2 November Anthony Preus
Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 11-1999 SAGP Newsletter 1999-2000.2 November Anthony Preus Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Preus, Anthony, "SAGP Newsletter 1999-2000.2 November" (1999). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 226. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/226 This Announcement is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. SOCIETY FOR ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY Founded 1951 Executive Office: President: Fred Miller, Jr. Binghamton University, Philosophy Bowling Green State University Binghamton, NY 11902-6000 Secretary: Anthony Preus (607) 777-2886 FAX [email protected] Binghamton University http://philosophv.binghamton.edu/ssips/sagpnews.html NEWSLETTER 1999/2000.2 You are invited to attend the meeting of the Society with the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association, December 28, 5:15 p.m. in the Wellesley Room of the Marriott Copley Place Hotel in Boston: Meeting of the SAGP Chair: Patricia Curd, Purdue University Patricia Sakezles, University o f Akron, “ The Socratic Fallacy in the Early Dialogues” David Levy, University o f Rochester, “ The ‘Digression’ in the Theaetetus: A New Interpretation” Geert van Cleemput, University o f South Florida at Tampa, “ Aristotle on the Philosophical and Political Life” You are also invited to attend the meeting of the Society with the American Philological Association,at 11 a.m. -
Katja Vogt Stoic Virtue&Happiness.Pages
Katja Maria Vogt, katjavogt.com, Columbia University "1 The Virtues and Happiness in Stoic Ethics, for ed. Chris Bobonich, Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics The Virtues and Happiness in Stoic Ethics1 ! ! The Stoics hold that virtue is knowledge, and that knowledge is one: the good state of the rational soul. Unlike the rest of us, a person who is in this state of mind is happy. Today and throughout much of antiquity, Stoic ethics is compared to Platonic and Aristotelian views. The Stoics’ immediate interlocutors, however, are skeptics.2 With them the Stoics discuss how hard it is to think straight, to arrive at carefully considered views and stable insights. The skeptics regularly suspend judgment, assessing disputes as unresolved. The questions of what is good and bad and how to live appear to them difficult and deserving of extensive study.3 The Stoics largely agree with the skeptics: these questions appear to them to be in need of further investigation. The Stoic approach is to ask what a person would be like who has the answers: how she would think, feel, and act. ! A brief disclaimer. “The Stoics” as I speak of them never existed. Instead, there were individual philosophers. Stoic philosophy begins with Zeno (334/3-262/1 BCE), who spent more than twenty years in Plato’s Academy, developing his views in conversation with the then emerging Academic skepticism (Zeno was roughly 20-30 years older than 1 I am grateful to Jens Haas, Sam McVane, and Nandi Theunissen for comments. 2 On the closeness of skeptic and Stoic philosophy, cf. -
The Elements of Avicenna's Physics Greek Sources And
The Elements of Avicenna’s Physics Greek Sources and Arabic Innovations Andreas Lammer München 15. März 2016 The Elements of Avicenna’s Physics Greek Sources and Arabic Innovations Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie an der Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München vorgelegt von Andreas Lammer aus Würzburg am 15. März 2016 Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Peter Adamson Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Dag Nikolaus Hasse Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 27. Juni 2016 Contents Preface vii Introduction 1 1 The Arabic Fate of Aristotle’s Physics 9 1.1 Transmission and Translation . 10 1.2 The Commentators on the Aristotelian Text . 17 1.3 Avicenna’s Copy of the Physics ....................... 29 2 The Methodology of Teaching and Learning 35 2.1 The Method of Physics . 35 2.2 Method and Principles between Physics and Metaphysics . 72 3 The Subject-Matter of Physics 97 3.1 Body, Substance, and Corporeality . 100 3.2 Matter and Form as Common Principles . 138 3.3 Change and an Additional Principle . 183 4 Nature and Power 195 4.1 Nature, and Soul, in the Greek Philosophical Tradition . 196 4.2 Avicenna’s Commentary on Physics II.1, 192b20–23 . 207 4.3 Avicenna, and Philoponus, on Inclination . 222 4.4 Bad Readings of Aristotle . 233 4.5 Avicenna’s Account of Nature and its Relation to Soul . 260 5 Place, Space, and Void 285 5.1 A Troubled Account of Place . 287 5.2 Clarifying Aristotle’s Troubled Account of Place . 303 5.3 Eliminating Void and Space . 343 v vi Contents 6 Time and Temporality in the Physical World 397 6.1 A New Approach to an Old Definition . -
Plotinus' Epistemology and His Reading of the Theaetetus
Plotinus' epistemology and his reading of the Theaetetus Sara Magrin Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal July 2009 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Copyright Sara Magrin 2009 Abstract: Plotinus' epistemology and his reading of the Theaetetus The thesis offers a reconstruction of Plotinus’ reading of the Theaetetus, and it presents an account of his epistemology that rests on that reading. It aims to show that Plotinus reads the Theaetetus as containing two anti-sceptical arguments. The first argument is an answer to radical scepticism, namely, to the thesis that nothing is apprehensible and judgement must be suspended on all matters. The second argument is an answer to a more moderate form of scepticism, which does not endorse a universal suspension of judgement, but maintains nonetheless that scientific knowledge is unattainable. The first chapter opens with a reconstruction of Plotinus’ reading of Theaet., 151e-184a, where Socrates examines the thesis that knowledge is sensation in light of Protagoras’ epistemology. In this chapter it is argued that Plotinus makes a polemical use of the discussion of Protagoras’ epistemology. Plotinus takes Plato to show that Protagoras’ views imply radical scepticism; and he attack the Stoics’ epistemological and ontological commitments by arguing that they imply Protagoras’ views, and thus lead to radical scepticism, too. The second chapter examines Plotinus’ interpretation of the ontology of the Timaeus. In Theaet., 151e-184a Plato shows that Protagoras’ epistemology leads to radical scepticism by arguing that it implies an allegedly Heracleitean conception of the sensible world. -
Download Download
Downloaded from the Humanities Digital Library http://www.humanities-digital-library.org Open Access books made available by the School of Advanced Study, University of London ***** Publication details: Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy: Keeling Lectures 2011-18 Edited by Fiona Leigh https://humanities-digital-library.org/index.php/hdl/catalog/book/keeling-lectures DOI: 10.14296/121.9781905670932 ***** This edition published in 2021 by UNIVERSITY OF LONDON SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES Senate House, Malet Street, London WC1E 7HU, United Kingdom ISBN 978-1-905670-93-2 (PDF edition) This work is published under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. More information regarding CC licenses is available at https://creativecommons.org/licenses Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies Supplement 141 Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy KEELING LECTURES 2011–18 Edited by Fiona Leigh THEMES IN PLATO, ARISTOTLE, AND HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY: KEELING LECTURES 2011–18 BULLETIN OF THE INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SUPPLEMENT 141 DIRECTOR & EDITOR: GREG WOOLF THEMES IN PLATO, ARISTOTLE, AND HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY: KEELING LECTURES 2011–18 EDITED BY FIONA LEIGH INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON PRESS 2021 The cover image shows a painted hydria from Attica, c. 450 bc. © The Trustees of the British Museum. Reproduced with permission. ISBN 978-1-905670-90-1 (paperback) ISBN 978-1-905670-93-2 (PDF) ISBN 978-1-905670-94-9 (epub) © 2021 Institute of Classical Studies, University of London. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. -
The Avicennian Moment
The Avicennian Moment Separation and the science of being (qua being) in Aristotle and Avicenna Timothy Mark Johannessen Submitted in total fulfillment of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Arts) June 2019 Asia Institute University of Melbourne ORCID: 0000-0002-9551-0198 Abstract This thesis considers the fundamental conception of first philosophy (metaphysics) in the Metaphysics of Aristotle and its reception–reform in a major work of Abū ‘Alī al-Husayn Ibn-Sīna (Avicenna): the Metaphysics of the Healing (al-Ilāhiyyāt: al-Shifā’). Specifically, it examines some of the main theoretical features that underpin both the conception and programme of first philosophy (understood as a study both of being qua being and of immaterial being) in these works, including the notions of ‘separation’ and ‘abstraction’, which both Aristotle and Avicenna employ pervasively. In doing so, this thesis seeks to show, first of all, how each thinker solves the problem of the relationship between the ontological and theological dimensions of first philosophy, and how their solutions, and the arguments they depend on, both reflect and are reflected in their wider views on being and the nature of scientific enquiry. It is argued that while the notion of separation as independence is fundamental for Aristotle (as seen, for example, in his treatment of the aporiai of Metaphysics B), by contrast, for Avicenna, the notion of abstraction as immateriality, is central. Similar points of comparison are presented, such as the very notion of a notion or meaning which Avicenna employs constantly, as in his unique treatment of the problem of the homonymy of being; and it is argued that the conception of meaning that Avicenna uses here is not, as such, found in Aristotle, who instead relies on a notion of logoi. -
Oxforq Studies in Ancient Philosophy
OXFORQ STUDIES SOMETHING AND NOTHING: IN ANCIENT THE STOICS ON CONCEPTS PHILOSOPHY AND UNIVERSALS VICTOR CASTON EDITOR: DAVID SEDLEY VOLUME XVII . it 51 TL); it 8' au iL),' OK,dS' ovap Pindar, Pythian 8. 95 1999 I T is commonplace to find the Stoics described as nominalists. I As early as the fifth century CE they are described as holding that 'there are only particulars' and, a century later, that 'common entities are ~ Victor Caston 1999 This paper began its life long ago in Julia Annas's seminar on Hellenistic Philoso phies of Mind in the spring of 1989, and was subsequently presented at the winter meetings of the American Philosophical Association, where Wolfgang Mann com mented on it; I have profited greatly from their criticisms. I would also like to thank very warmly Jamie Dreier, Stephen Menn, and David Sedley for extensive discus sions and written comments in the interim, as well as Tad Brennan, Jaegwon Kim, Baron Reed, Ernie S088, and Jim Van Cleve for challenging criticisms. Each saved me from numerous errors; the remainder, of course, are solely my own. I e.g. E. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung [Philosophie der Greichen], 5th edn. (3 vols. in 6 parts; Leipzig, 1923; 1st edn. 1844-52), iii/I. 80-1 (cf. ii/I. 295-6); C. Prantl, Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande [Geschichte] (4 vols.; Leipzig, 1855-70), i. 420, 427-33; L. Stein, Die Erkenntnisthe orie der Stoa [Erkenntnistheorie] (Berlin, 1888),276-300; V. Brochard, 'La logique des Stoi'ciens', in his Etudes de philosophie ancienne et de philosophie moderne [Etudes] (Paris, 1926),220-38, esp.