Productive and Creative Poiesis and the Work of Art

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Productive and Creative Poiesis and the Work of Art transcultural studies 13 (2017) 99-118 brill.com/ts Productive and Creative Poiesis and the Work of Art Jason Tuckwell University of Western Sydney [email protected] Abstract There are two ancient formulations of the problem art presents to us: poiesis under- stands art as a generic ontological problem and techné treats art as a particular kind of work—a skilful, intentional practice to deviate processes of becoming. Arguably, this distinction leads to very different procedures for determining the ‘work of art’; poiesis considers artistic praxis as resolved into the artefact while techné considers it as a problem in-itself. This tension is evident in the generic designation of the ‘work of art’ which tends to conflate process with what this process produces. This confla- tion about the work of art can be illuminated via a return to Aristotle’s concept of techné. This is because techné (the kind of work art performs) remains irreducible to both poiesis (to make) and praxis (deliberative action). Where poiesis and praxis are constructive activities differentiated by their intentional ends, techné remains a more foundational power to work upon processes of material causation. What these Aristo- telian distinctions clarify is that the work of art is neither resolvable in the terms of its productions (poiesis) or the terms of its practices (praxis, deliberative actions); rather, art works by deviating these productive processes in the midst of their becoming, by bringing unprecedented differences into being. As such, the work of art apprehended by Aristotelian techné is not reducible to any poiesis; it works upon and divides poiesis into another workflow—a creative poiesis. The work of art thus appears as a creative, causal power counter-posed to all production. Keywords poiesis – techné – aesthetics – Aristotle – Benjamin © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2018 | doi 10.1163/23751606-01302001Downloaded from Brill.com09/30/2021 03:25:20AM via free access <UN> 100 Tuckwell Introduction: Poiesis and techné There are two ancient formulations of the problem art presents to us; poie- sis understands art as a generic ontological problem and techné treats art as a particular kind of work—a skilful, intentional practice to deviate processes of becoming. Although Plato considered the universality of poiesis to ulti- mately determine thinking about art, techné remained for the Greeks an irre- ducible problem. This is largely because, despite the exclusion of techné from episteme—a knowledge of universals—it was quite clear that reason had to have its own sort of techné, a skilful discernment or calculative process (logis- tikós) sufficient to produce sophia: the skill of reasoning with universals.1 As such, poiesis—with its universalising aspiration to think how ‘anything what- ever passes from non-being into being’—cannot be obviously resolved without putting techné to work.2 If this is an enduring obstacle for philosophical and ontological approaches to the problem of art, it is because their own coming to being relies upon putting techné to work. This precludes techné’s appearance as a proper object for poiesis, insofar as any element taken as axiomatic in the construction of a model, remains outside its explanatory powers.3 1 It is particularly with Aristotle, that the complexity of Greek thought about σοφίᾱ (sophia) and its complications with questions of skill (techné, broadly speaking) find a systematic ex- pression. There are the famous passages in Book vi of the Nicomeachean Ethics (specifically, EN1141a9), but the discussion of skilfulness permeates Aristotle’s divisions of knowledge, from the ubiquity of logos (evident in ‘beasts’), through aisthēsis (the ubiquity of sense- perception) up into the higher, exclusively human, rational faculties; poiesis (specific to ‘making’) and praxis (action, that is, specifically of a deliberative kind; political and ethical). 2 Plato, The Republic, 1961: 205c. 3 Aristotle can be understood to anticipate this logical limit, that was not formalised until Gödel (1931). ‘Now induction supplies a first principle or universal, deduction works from universals; therefore there are first principles from which deduction starts, which cannot be proved by deduction; therefore they are reached by induction.’ (en, vi. iii. 2–4 [EN1139b14–36]) This logical limit upon the explanatory powers of any ideal system finds a formal presen- tation in Godel; ‘Hence a consistency proof for the system S can be carried out only by means of modes of inference that are not formalized in the system S itself, and analogous results hold for other formal systems as well.’ (Gödel, On Formally Undecidable Proposi- tions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems i, pp. 596). As such, even at the limit of the rational intuition upon which episteme (knowledge of uni- versals) rests and which is thought to be beyond any form of rational deliberation, there remains the potentially difficult complications with skill. In the case of first principles, ratio- nal thought acquires its apprehension of universals via an inductive encounter or by other modes of inference—that is, via the work of techné (that is, via logistikós [calculation] and transculturalDownloaded studies from 13Brill.com09/30/2021 (2017) 99-118 03:25:20AM via free access <UN> Productive and Creative Poiesis and the Work of Art 101 To put this another way, not only does ‘the work of art’ remain inscrutable to ontological models, it is more profoundly what is put to work in order to for- mulate a poiesis. What this essay will attempt to show is that if techné cannot be reduced to poiesis, it is not only because it is the immanent mechanism that processes production, but most importantly because it divides poiesis into a counter-oriented, creative workflow. It is arguably this latter deviation into a counter-oriented creative poiesis that has always made the work of art possible in its artisanal sense, the technical skill to shape clay or stone, words or sounds, paint or pixels, and so on. Yet, if we are to reconsider techné in its Aristotelian breadth—as that distinctly rational process that links aisthēsis (sense- perception) to a power to re-shape nature (phusis) on its own terms—then techné only begins by governing the transition from embodied sense to think- ing subjects. That is first to say, techné problematises the domain of aesthetics within which the work of art is frequently restricted. Techné certainly performs this medial process that works between the hand that shapes the bowl and the eye of the craftsperson, but it does not resolve into the percept, but rather per- sisting as the skill necessary to organise rational thought. The work of art does not simply resolve between sense-perception and the ideas, rendering it indis- tinguishably from the appearance of the artefact; techné prolongs in the world of ideas, carrying out the work through which our highest conceptions are forged into being. Thus, techné is not simply to shape the form of the bowl—it is also at work in the shaping of formal ideas, what inheres in the process of cogitation that organises artefacts and aesthetic ideas into a model of poiesis. Wherever this work of art is ontologically reduced to a relation between the artefact and the aesthetic idea, this complex of skilful work-flows has been ex- changed with an ideal-object; without this preliminary reduction, the problem of art cannot be rendered comprehensible in terms of poiesis. If this is particularly problematic for the work of art, it is more importantly so because this cleaves the distinctive work-flow of Aristotelian techné into two disconnected processes. This is to separate the productivity of aisthēsis from the secondary process that announces the uniqueness of techné: the power to re-problematise causal processes, via a unique efficient cause. The problem of aisthēsis (sense-perception) to which techné is the most proximate faculty). If then, there is an unbridgeable incompossibility between the inductive or inferential functions governed by techné and any possible universal knowledge, there is no possibility of a universal deduc- tion of techné. That is to say, there is no adequate method to ontologically reduce techné to an understanding of poiesis, so that the problem of the work of art is secured within a universal ontological model of how everything comes into being. A more thorough investigation of this problem is undertaken in Tuckwell, Creation and the Function of Art, 2017. transcultural studies 13 (2017) 99-118 Downloaded from Brill.com09/30/2021 03:25:20AM via free access <UN> 102 Tuckwell art is thus not properly composed between the serial arrangements of artefacts and aesthetic ideas, but around the mechanism of intentional skill through which the contents of our higher faculties are made to affect real deviations upon what is already in being. If techné cannot be rendered in ontological terms—the apprehension of a unidirectional mode of becoming which sensi- bilises the artefact, together with how everything comes to be—it is precisely because the problem of art concerns a unique causal power, an action, that works upon this dominant flow. Techné cannot be understood in the terms of poiesis, because in setting to work upon it, techné divides poiesis, deviating the process into a recursive, counter-oriented workflow. That is to say, far from be- ing unified within poiesis, techné causes it to differentiate. The problem of art therefore concerns the work upon poiesis that causes it to deviate into distinct work-flows: there remains poiesis in its orthodox terms, a dominant, ‘natural’, unidirectional flow of becoming I will term productive poiesis; and there are secondary, recursive and supplementary work-flows, I will collectively term creative poiesis.4 My primary proposition is that the problem of art pertains solely to this latter, creative work-flow and is comprehensible only within these terms.
Recommended publications
  • Facing Nature: the Infinite in the Flesh
    Facing Nature: The Infinite in the Flesh Robert Daniel Victorin-Vangerud, B.A., M.Div. This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of. Murdoch University Perth, Western Australia 2004 I declare that this thesis is my own account of my research. ------------------------------------- Robert Daniel Victorin-Vangerud i Abstract “Facing Nature: The Infinite in the Flesh” by Robert Victorin-Vangerud This thesis explores the relation between two interpretations of chôra, drawn from a reading of Plato’s Timaeus. The first I label the elemental chôra. The second, I call the social chôra. The first chapter addresses the elements in Ionian philosophy, with an eye toward the political and social backdrop of the important cosmological notion of isonomia, law of equals. Here social and elemental are continuous. Chapter two looks at the next phase of Presocratic thought, Elea, specifically Parmenides and his influence on later thought, then turns to Heidegger’s reading of Parmenides’ through the key word of alêtheia. Finally, I offer a reading of Parmenides through a different key word— trust. The third chapter examines Plato’s cosmology in the Timaeus, focusing on the way the beginning of this dialogue inflects the dialogue in a political/social direction, putting the social chôra in tension with the elemental chôra that the body of the Timaeus’ discusses. In the fourth chapter, which examines the Phaedrus, this tension is inverted, since this dialogue on writing and justice set in what proves to be the mesmerizing and erotic elemental milieu of the world outside the walls of the polis. The second half of the dissertation turns to some modern thinkers within the phenomenological tradition or its wake who write about elementals.
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought
    THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT by MELISSA M. SHEW A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School ofthe University ofOregon in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy September 2008 11 University of Oregon Graduate School Confirmation of Approval and Acceptance of Dissertation prepared by: Melissa Shew Title: "The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought" This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree in the Department ofPhilosophy by: Peter Warnek, Chairperson, Philosophy John Lysaker, Member, Philosophy Ted Toadvine, Member, Philosophy James Crosswhite, Outside Member, English and Richard Linton, Vice President for Research and Graduate Studies/Dean ofthe Graduate School for the University of Oregon. September 6, 2008 Original approval signatures are on file with the Graduate School and the University of Oregon Libraries. 111 An Abstract of the Dissertation of Melissa M. Shew for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy to be taken September 2008 Title: THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT Approved: Dr. Peter Warnek This dissertation engages three facets of Greek philosophy: 1) the phenomenon of tyche (chance, fortune, happening, or luck) in Aristotle's Physics, Nicomachean Ethics, and Poetics; 2) how tyche infonns Socrates' own philosophical practice in the Platonic dialogues; and 3) how engaging tyche in these Greek texts challenges established interpretations of Greek thought in contemporary scholarship and discussion. I argue that the complex status of tyche in Aristotle's texts, when combined with its appearance in the Platonic dialogues and the framework of Greek myth and poetry (poiesis), underscores the seriousness with which the Greeks consider the role of chance in human life.
    [Show full text]
  • On Theodorus' Lesson in the Theaetetus 147D-E by S
    On Theodorus’ lesson in the Theaetetus 147d-e by S. Negrepontis and G. Tassopoulos In the celebrated Theaetetus 147d3-e1 passage Theodorus is giving a lesson to Theaetetus and his companion, proving certain quadratic incommensurabilities. The dominant view on this passage, expressed independently by H. Cherniss and M. Burnyeat, is that Plato has no interest to, and does not, inform the reader about Theodorus’ method of incommensurability proofs employed in his lesson, and that, therefore, there is no way to decide from the Platonic text, our sole information on the lesson, whether the method is anthyphairetic as Zeuthen, Becker, van der Waerden suggest, or not anthyphairetic as Hardy-Wright, Knorr maintain. Knorr even claims that it would be impossible for Theodorus to possess a rigorous proof of Proposition X.2 of the Elements, necessary for an anthyphairetic method, because of the reliance of the proof of this Proposition, in the Elements, on Eudoxus principle. But it is not difficult to see that Knorr’s claim is undermined by the fact that an elementary proof of Proposition X.2, in no way involving Eudoxus principle, is readily obtained either from the proof of Proposition X.3 of the Elements itself (which is contrapositive and thus logically equivalent to X.2), or from an ancient argument going back to the originator of the theory of proportion reported by Aristotle in the Topics 158a-159b passage. The main part of the paper is devoted to a discussion of the evidence for a distributive rendering of the plural ‘hai dunameis’ in the crucial statement, ’because the powers (‘hai dunameis’) were shown to be infinite in multitude’ in 147d7-8 (contrary to the Burnyeat collective, set-theoretic rendering), necessarily resulting in an anthyphairetic method for Theodorus’ proofs of incommensurability (contrary to the Cherniss-Burnyeat neutrality thesis).
    [Show full text]
  • Toward a Poiesis of Curriculum Donna Lynn Trueit Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2005 Complexifying the poetic: toward a poiesis of curriculum Donna Lynn Trueit Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Education Commons Recommended Citation Trueit, Donna Lynn, "Complexifying the poetic: toward a poiesis of curriculum" (2005). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 2988. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/2988 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. COMPLEXIFYING THE POETIC: TOWARD A POIESIS OF CURRICULUM A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Curriculum and Instruction by Donna Lynn Trueit B. S. N., University of Victoria, 1994 M. A., University of Victoria, 1996 December 2005 © Copyright 2005 Donna Lynn Trueit All rights reserved ii DEDICATION To Bill (Dr. William E. Doll, Jr.), without whom this inquiry would have been impossible: your optimism, imagination, faith, intellect and love inspire and sustain me. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This project was made possible by the incredible, intellectual atmosphere of inquiry in Curriculum and Instruction at LSU, in the Curriculum Theory Project, developed and promoted by Drs. William Pinar and William E. Doll, Jr. In this academically rich, challenging, stimulating, and welcoming environment, I took up the invitation, graciously extended, to partake.
    [Show full text]
  • Hiccups and Other Interruptions in the Symposium
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1962 Hiccups and Other Interruptions in the Symposium George Kimball Plochmann Southern Illinois University Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Plochmann, George Kimball, "Hiccups and Other Interruptions in the Symposium" (1962). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 48. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/48 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. HICCUPS AND OTHER INTERRUPTIONS IN THE SYMPOSIUM George Kimball Plochmann Plat.o's Symposium has so much charm but. contains so little open debate over concepts that were it to have been his only surviving work, literary critics would seldom have conceded that its author was a worker in the philosophical vineyard,l Readers through the ages, unconditioned as they I: would have been to expect dialectic even in the strangest Platonic frame­ work, would hardly have glanced inside the incisive characterization, the dazzling rhetoric, and the glowing mythology; and they would have accord­ ingly missed an extraordinarily subtle philosophic structure, a stately dialectical sequence that when laid bare all but overwhelms us. There is a second tendency to misinterpret: with the rest of the dialogues at hand to offer help, many philosophical critics of the Symposium are hesitant to seek for "Platonic philosophy" in any but the actual spoken discourse of Socrates, and they continue to think of the half-dozen other speakers as mere attractive foils to the hard going of the theory of ideas and the ladder of aspiration2 or love.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mechanical Arts and Poiesis in the Philosophy and Literature of the Twelfth-Century Schools
    The Mechanical Arts and Poiesis in the Philosophy and Literature of the Twelfth-Century Schools Anya Burgon Trinity Hall University of Cambridge October 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Declaration This dissertation is the result of my own work and includes nothing which is the outcome of work done in collaboration except as declared in the Preface and specified in the text. It is not substantially the same as any that I have submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for a degree or diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Preface and specified in the text. I further state that no substantial part of my dissertation has already been submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for any such degree, diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Preface and specified in the text. It does not exceed the prescribed word limit for the relevant Degree Committee. The Mechanical Arts and Poiesis in the Philosophy and Literature of the Twelfth-Century Schools Anya Burgon The ‘mechanical arts’ or artes mechanicae were first named as a part of Philosophy in Hugh of Saint-Victor’s Didascalicon (1120s). They were identified as seven arts (fabric making, armament, commerce, agriculture, hunting, medicine, and theatrics), and positioned as a parallel to the seven liberal arts. Their inclusion in the Didascalicon has been taken by previous historians to signal a new interest in science and engineering, an effort to ‘give intellectual status to technology for the first time’.
    [Show full text]
  • The Synecdoche of Poiesis Jeremiah Bowen
    The Synecdoche of Poiesis Jeremiah Bowen SubStance, Volume 49, Number 1, 2020 (Issue 151), pp. 3-24 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/751172 [ This content has been declared free to read by the pubisher during the COVID-19 pandemic. ] The Synecdoche of Poiesis Jeremiah Bowen Abstract Symposium describes a synecdoche in Greek usage, in which a particular poiesis, the making of verses set to music, stands in for the generality of poiesis, production in its entirety. This passage provides Jean-Luc Nancy with a necessary premise for what he calls “the enigma of our time”: poiesis and/or techne. But contrary to Socrates’s warning, this trope continues to distort our contemporary understanding of production. Nancy inadvertently dramatizes this distortion by mistranslating Plato’s account in a manner compatible with the Heideg- gerian contrariety, but incompatible with Nancy’s convictions regarding the labor theory of value. By tendentially foreclosing philosophical consideration of productive relations, and condensing their antagonisms into a universalized mastery, this contrariety tends to frame problems in a manner that avoids politics and elides intersecting asymmetries of power founded on class, race and sex. A word from the wise is not to be discarded, O Phaedrus, but it is to be examined. —Plato, Phaedrus (260a) The Socratic project is founded on the fallibility of those reputed to be wise, and the necessity of examining their wisdom. The importance of fallibility is clear enough in the Apology, in Socrates’s insistence that he is only wiser than others because he acknowledges his own ignorance.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium Author(S): Diskin Clay Source: Arion, New Series, Vol
    Trustees of Boston University The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium Author(s): Diskin Clay Source: Arion, New Series, Vol. 2, No. 2 (1975), pp. 238-261 Published by: Trustees of Boston University Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20163375 . Accessed: 31/01/2014 12:13 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Trustees of Boston University is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Arion. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 141.222.81.135 on Fri, 31 Jan 2014 12:13:22 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE TRAGIC AND COMIC POET OF THE SYMPOSIUM Diskin Clay For Bernard Knox 1 LATO'S SYMPOSIUM BREAKSUP only at dawn. For some, his celebration of Eros lasts longer than it should. At its end not only have Phaedrus, Eryximachus, and still others escaped into the night, but Plato's commentators have fallen asleep?like all but three or four of those still present in Agathon's banquet room. Ficino composed no Oratio octava to represent or com ment upon Socrates' conversation with Agathon and Aristophanes. As for Louis Le Roi, whose Le Sympose de Platon ( 1558) was the first French translation of the Sym posium and at the same time a sort of marriage manual for the newly married dauphin (pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1974 The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium Diskin Clay Haverford College Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Diskin Clay presented "The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium" to the meeting of the Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy with the American Philological Association in Chicago in 1974. A revised version was published in Arion NS 2 (1975) 238-261, and reprinted in J. P. Anton & A. Preus, eds. 1983. Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy vol. 2, SUNY Press, 321-339. For information about the author, see: https://classicalstudies.org/scs-news/memoriam-diskin-clay This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Śӿ ό·Dzɹąӿ êĤӿ yͱ˧ɵĀӿ Ύҝӿ ͒Ǔӿ ѾɁӿ ?$ -:A !'A 3&4B 5>ad !" oN%EOu - B % 5B \edcӿ 4 _F^u H.Ld ҮΣӿ ?5/bd m~ IJ­4̐Lӿ FPu kRD"~ %)Md ĊˏƢϜ ӷ Ѡɥ͡˿ӿ ͞ǟӿ {ν͟Іӿ 5 U`Vu ?SH,#\~ ҁ!¶%ӿ ɝщӿ e-Tw@~ i-ӿ 3.A $H!~ ISu~ =A (pu ɓÏƮϨӀЭFӿ Nsr2=)mWu Å&ĸӿ Xa067u Fb*NVu L D d 3HnS~ o.%~ '"ǹɋ҉Dӿ ҽҋӿ ˎÇҊͺ7Тӿ @46T UAIMd ȵӏƂӿ !",B Lʸ Ρӿ A5=#~ #$B =:B /ɍϛӿ )ςӿ ǣͩҸσӿ ͚ ӿ шȈ͈Ѐӿ Vc189u %(.4A ɞ˸ӿ " 3 " " '.B ċ΁˯γ΂ЩƩľӿ " J V*?d ?dm~ e:w ]"X^#f&Jp~ 2Fw B<=7W^E?8d 1E]M /(?68 ;0)A<B jǷÂ҈Ɋͷ̟ӿ @Q2YdGK+AVu uӿ &HNu ͯҹɲБӿ ŗӿ >+d pUw ѓȖŨӿӹǨʇϞ+ҏӿ d"K/~ qcLgBr4UG~ F%u r0)~ M~ 0ӿ e,u V(w -ɤˣųӿ w V ͍ιau ͎Ǐӿ ˶ϡϢʊǻӿ FIxC~ Ǜ͝λӿ ,Ȟŭӿ ̢ƟӣˍӬӿ ˪ÆϗϘ"Ĺӿ yY25N~ Z[ ~ ~ ,=fw ?50cd 19B !ӿ Ǣɪ˄ӿ .)ӿ fRBX:gu ¬$ıӿ F>?Cku ҷΧͤ̆ӿ 0Ɏƣӿ ː Фҍӿ Z!/"w ͏ǐӿ Ҍɏӿ ńʑÕ˘Άǿ3Gӿ ëүыӿ ȌŜӿ &ĺСӿ /A ӞɮѴȷӿ 6Ss7Eh~ A ˃¡Ћѧӿ <") .
    [Show full text]
  • The End of Love? Questioning Technocracy in Plato's Symposium
    AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE The End of Love? Questioning technocracy in Plato’s Symposium Philip Krinks i https://orcid.org/0000-0001-5428-6516 [email protected] i The Centre for Theology & Community – London – UK KRINKS, P. (2020). The End of Love? Questioning technocracy in Plato’s Symposium. Archai 29, e02906. Abstract: Plato’s Symposium contains two accounts of eros which explicitly aim to reach a telos. The first is the technocratic account of the doctor Eryximachus, who seeks an exhaustive account of eros, common to all things with a physical nature. For him medical techne can create an orderly erotic harmony; while religion is defined as the curing of disorderly eros. Against this Socrates recounts the priestess Diotima finding a telos, not in technical exhaustiveness, but in a https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_29_6 [1] 2 Rev. Archai (ISSN: 1984-249X), n. 29, Brasília, 2020, e02906. dialectical definition of eros in the light of the good. What is common to all human beings is the desire to be in eternal relation to the good. All technai are forms of poiesis, by which things pass from being to not being. The erotic harmony recommended by Eryximachus, no less than the Aristophanes” recommendation of eros as “of a half, or of a whole’, is subject to the question whether “it happens to be good’. A self-harmonisation produced by techne can no more evade the sovereignty of good, than can projects of self-completion with a beloved in our likeness.
    [Show full text]
  • ASHLEY GRAHAM Emory University PRAYER AFTER the DEATH OF
    ASHLEY GRAHAM Emory University PRAYER AFTER THE DEATH OF GOD Metaphysics is onto-theo-logy. Someone who has experienced theology in his own roots, both the theology of the Christian faith and that of philosophy, would today rather remain silent when speaking in the realm of thinking. – Martin Heidegger, “The Onto-theo-logical Constitution of Metaphysics”1 …if there is no certainty, neither will there be a system of certainties, that is to say a science. From which it follows that there will be no science of life either….As we examine this view closely, it looks to us more like a prayer than like the truth. – Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos2 I am trying to think while praying, to pray while thinking. – John Caputo, The Weakness of God3 I. PRAYER AS DESIDERATUM: THINKING IN THREES In The Weakness of God: A Theology of the Event, Caputo ventures a theo-logical experiment at its etymological best—using the word of ‘God’ about, to or by God (à dieu). However, he does so not without acknowledging his place in a strand of onto-theo-logical goodbyes (àdieu).4 Evoking the Name in words, he may immediately come under suspicion of Heidegger’s admonition. But what if this thinking of the Word/Name is characterized as an event more comparable to prayer than a closed onto-theo-logical construction?5 What if 1 Martin Heidegger as quoted by Peter Jonkers. “God in France: Heidegger’s Legacy,” in God in France: Eight Contemporary Thinkers on God (Leuven: Peeters, 2005), 26. 2 Quoted in Martha Nussbaum.
    [Show full text]
  • SECOND SAILING: Alternative Perspectives on Plato
    Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum 132 2015 SECOND SAILING: Alternative Perspectives on Plato Edited by Debra Nails and Harold Tarrant in Collaboration with Mika Kajava and Eero Salmenkivi Societas Scientiarum Fennica The Finnish Society of Sciences and Letters Commentationes Humanarun Litterarum is part of the publishing cooperation between the Finnish Society of Sciences and Letters and the Finnish Academy of Science and Letters ISSN 0069-6587 ISBN 978-951-653-409-4 Copyright © 2015 by Societas Scientiarum Fennica Layout by Maija Holappa Printed by Wellprint Oy, Espoo 2015 Contents Preface i Mika Kajava, Pauliina Remes and Eero Salmenkivi Introduction iii Harold Tarrant and Debra Nails Paradigmatic Method and Platonic Epistemology 1 Dimitri El Murr Pseudo-Archytas’ Protreptics? On Wisdom in its Contexts 21 Phillip Sidney Horky Plato and the Variety of Literary Production 41 Mauro Tulli The Meaning of Ἄπολλον‘ ... δαιμονίας ὑπερβολῆς’ in 53 Plato’s Republic 6,509b6–c4: A New Hypothesis A. Gabrièle Wersinger-Taylor Dangerous Sailing: [Plato] Second Alcibiades 147a1–4 59 Harold Tarrant Bad Luck to Take a Woman Aboard 73 Debra Nails Argument and Context: Adaption and Recasting of Positions in 91 Plato’s Dialogues Michael Erler Listening to Socrates in the Theaetetus: Recovering a Lost Narrator 107 Anne-Marie Schultz The Mask of Dialogue: On the Unity of Socrates’ Characterization in 125 Plato’s Dialogues Mario Regali Plato, Socrates, and the genei gennaia sophistikē of Sophist 231b 149 Christopher Rowe Erōs and Dialectic in Plato’s Phaedrus: 169 Questioning the Value of Chronology Francisco J. Gonzalez Changing Course in Plato Studies 187 Gerald A. Press Is the Idea of the Good Beyond Being? 197 Plato’s epekeina tēs ousias Revisited (Republic 6,509b8–10) Rafael Ferber and Gregor Damschen Like Being Nothing: Death and Anaesthesia in Plato Apology 40c 205 Rick Benitez Ideas of Good? 225 Lloyd P.
    [Show full text]