Book Review How a “Lawless” China Made Modern America: an Epic Told in Orientalism
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
BOOK REVIEW HOW A “LAWLESS” CHINA MADE MODERN AMERICA: AN EPIC TOLD IN ORIENTALISM LEGAL ORIENTALISM: CHINA, THE UNITED STATES AND MOD- ERN LAW. By Teemu Ruskola. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer- sity Press. 2013. Pp. 338. $39.95. Reviewed by Carol G.S. Tan∗ I. MODERN LAW’S MAP OF THE WORLD Legal Orientalism begins with a map of modern law in which the United States and China are located at opposite ends. America sees itself as being built on “particularly universal” political values in which law is given a privileged position (p. 9).1 From this perspective, China and Chinese law are cast as being “universally particular” (p. 9).2 In its particularity, the rule of law and democracy are out of its reach. While the United States has become the world’s “chief law enforcer,” China, because of its poor human rights record, is a “law breaker in chief” (pp. 1–2). Professor Teemu Ruskola’s theoretically sophisticated book traces the historical journey traveled by American law starting with the receipt of extraterritorial rights for its citizens in 1844, a mile- stone in America’s career as an imperial nation; this is not least be- cause it was at this juncture that a law of nations that was not univer- sal but particular emerged, in part to justify America’s extraterritorial rights in China. The next development was the establishment of an American court in China whose decisions were as arbitrary as those reached by the Chinese courts, the alleged arbitrariness of those courts being why, foreigners had argued, extraterritorial rights were neces- sary. There was then the taking over of a Chinese court in Shanghai, with the consequence that American judges determined the very con- tent of Chinese law. The United States passed anti-Chinese immigra- tion laws that were justified by the assertion that the “lawlessness” of China had produced Chinese immigrants who knew only despotic rule and who were therefore unsuited to a life under the rule of law in ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ∗ Professor of Law, SOAS, University of London. I would like to thank the President and editors of the Harvard Law Review for their many helpful comments. Errors remain mine. I would also like to record my thanks to the Center of Asian Legal Exchange and the Graduate School of Law, Nagoya University for hosting me when I was in the final stages of writing this Review. 1 Emphasis has been removed. 2 Emphasis has been removed. 1677 1678 HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. 128:1677 America (pp. 8, 46, 49, and 143). The U.S. Supreme Court upheld these anti-Chinese laws on the basis of the federal government’s plena- ry powers in passing immigration laws, powers that were uncon- strained by the Constitution (p. 143). The major part of Legal Orientalism is concerned with the question of how it was that Chinese law was not considered to be law and the ideational and material consequences of this exclusion. In the book’s Epilogue (Chapter Six), Ruskola argues that even with the large in- crease in the volume of laws in China since the 1980s, legal Oriental- ism cannot be simply a matter of history. Ruskola notes that in Chi- na’s accession to the World Trade Organization, it was necessary for China to adapt its legal system (pp. 205–06). Although China was voluntarily seeking admission, the situation was reminiscent of the early-twentieth century when China was told it had to modernize its legal system if it wanted to end extraterritorialism (p. 205). Ruskola concludes that colonialism’s spread of modern law has triumphed: “Today law is universal” (p. 208). Moreover, modern law, as an exten- sion of the state, has its own tendency to enact “colonialism without even colonizers” (p. 207). Even though this project is not yet complete and there are some areas of activity and life that Ruskola thinks are better considered “unlegal” (p. 220),3 the success of the modern legal project “in creating Chinese subjects who desire law and conceive of politics in juridified terms” (p. 208) is clear. Chinese citizens “are in- creasingly suing their employers, landlords, each other, and even the state” (p. 208). While Ruskola does not commit himself to modern law (though he states that “[t]he world in which we live is a fundamentally legal one” (p. 14)), he points to the rising rights consciousness in China and acknowledges that the importance of law as a “counterhegemonic” weapon is in fact increased in an authoritarian state such as China, where there is a greater risk of state encroachment on individual rights (p. 211). In closing Legal Orientalism, Ruskola observes that, despite China’s economic and political rise, “the idea of ‘Chinese law’ contin- ues to strike many as an oxymoron, haunted as it is by a long history of legal Orientalism” (p. 235). A work as rich and ambitious as Legal Orientalism is open to mul- tiple readings. This Review begins by placing Legal Orientalism in le- gal deconstruction before looking briefly at earlier works on the sub- ject of Orientalism and law. It then examines the book’s claims regarding the myth of China’s lawlessness and explores the book’s ar- gument about why America sought extraterritorial rights from China, before looking at one empirical aspect of the work — America’s prac- ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 3 Emphasis has been removed. 2015] HOW A “LAWLESS” CHINA MADE MODERN AMERICA 1679 tice of extraterritoriality in China — and considering Orientalism’s contribution to and future in the study of law. II. DECONSTRUCTION AND LEGAL ORIENTALISM As an analytical method, deconstruction is a way of interrogating the law and its apparent discourses. Where law’s technique is to de- fine an action or condition and to provide the appurtenant legal con- sequences, deconstruction encourages skepticism of the oppositional dichotomies characteristic of law. Applied to legal doctrine, for in- stance, deconstruction encourages scrutiny of the relationship between what is established as the main rule and its exceptions or subsidiary rules. Deconstruction problematizes the premise of difference and re- veals similarities so that the law’s dichotomies look untenable. Ap- plied to the theory within which legal doctrine is rooted, deconstruc- tion suggests that, if there is a dominant narrative by which we have come to understand a legal concept’s very existence, then there may be a marginalized narrative which can produce a “countervision.”4 If we identify a value that is assumed to be universal, we may ask if it is not in fact merely provincial. To be sure, deconstructive technique is employed extensively in Le- gal Orientalism. In the case study of China’s corporation law (Chapter Three) — a law characterized chiefly by its presumed absence until re- cent times — we see the binary between U.S. and Chinese law stood on its head by means of the argument that Chinese family law mir- rored the structure and performed the functions of American corpora- tion law (p. 67). The arguments focus on various aspects of Chinese family organizations and vehicles such as ancestral trusts. An im- portant element of the reading of Chinese family law as a law of cor- porations is seeing through the state ideology of Confucianism to the individual profit-making that was being pursued. In American law, the collective entity is exceptional and, as a result, has to be made a legal person through the use of a legal fiction. In Confucianism, it is quite the opposite. The starting point is the collective, and the indi- vidual’s profit-seeking activities had to be hidden behind kinship (pp. 64–65). Ruskola argues that, when looked at closely, kinship hid rela- tionships achieved through contract.5 His argument at once problema- ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 4 For a discussion of deconstruction, see J.M. Balkin, Nested Oppositions, 99 YALE L.J. 1669 (1990) (reviewing JOHN M. ELLIS, AGAINST DECONSTRUCTION (1989)). 5 Ruskola gives the example of an uxorilocal marriage where, contrary to the Confucian ideal, a son-in-law is adopted into a family with no sons and married to one of his new sisters (p. 77). Uxorilocal marriages usually involved adult men, not young boys, unlike the t’ung-yang-hsi, a marriage practice referred to in the same discussion, in which a girl child is transferred to a family to marry one of her new brothers upon maturity. See generally Arthur P. Wolf, Adopt a Daughter- in-Law, Marry a Sister: A Chinese Solution to the Problem of the Incest Taboo, 70 AM. AN- 1680 HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. 128:1677 tizes the view of China as being all about the family and not about contract. The interrogation is then reversed by the argument that many aspects of contemporary U.S. corporation law bear traces of familism. The fascinating examination consisting of a succession of points and counterpoints that draws upon sinology, kinship, anthro- pology, and legal history destabilizes the apparent difference between American and Chinese law premised on the individual/corporate iden- tity binary. Deconstruction cannot, however, supply normative direction nor can it fully explain why one value in the law was chosen over another. Thus it cannot be extended to interrogations of how we came to have a particular legal doctrine or even an entire legal system and why oth- er concepts or models were rejected. Legal Orientalism cures this limi- tation by using intuitions gained from postcolonial studies. It thus provides an understanding of the “effect that Orientalism has had on the development” of American law, Chinese law, and international law (p. 3). Observing that these categories of law, including “law” itself, are not “pregiven object[s] of knowledge” (p.