Margalit Halbertal Liberalism and the Right to Culture.Pdf
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Liberalism and the Right to Culture Authors(s): AVISHAI MARGALIT and MOSHE HALBERTAL Source: Social Research, Vol. 61, No. 3, Liberalism (FALL 1994), pp. 491-510 Published by: The New School Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40971045 Accessed: 24-03-2016 19:06 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40971045?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The New School is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Social Research http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 137.110.74.76 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 19:06:54 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms Liberalism and the Right to BY AVISHAI MARGALIT Culture /. AND MOSHE HALBERTAL Setting Up the Problem JlTuman beings have a right to culture- not just any culture, but their own. The right to culture has far-reaching implications for the liberal conception of the state. A culture essentially requires a group, and the right to culture may involve giving groups a status that contradicts the status of the individual in a liberal state. The right to culture may involve a group whose norms cannot be reconciled with the conception of the individual in a liberal society. For example, the group may recognize only arranged marriages and not those resulting from the free choice of the partners. Protecting cultures out of the human right to culture may take the form of an obligation to support cultures that flout the rights of the individual in a liberal society. And this is not the only difficulty- there is also the problem that this right may be used to protect cultures within a state which reject the "civil religion," the "ethos," the "narrative" or the "meta-narrative," or any other appellation you may choose for the shared values and symbols of the state's citizens. But these shared values and symbols are meant to serve as the focus for citizens' identification with the state, as well as the source of their willingness to defend it even at the risk of their lives. A central problem for the liberal society's protection of the right to culture- especially if the culture involved is not itself liberal- is that protecting it often requires the state to use SOCIAL RESEARCH, Vol. 61, No. 3 (Fall 1994) This content downloaded from 137.110.74.76 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 19:06:54 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 492 SOCIAL RESEARCH illiberal means. For example, granting a particular cultural group the opportunity to preserve its cultural homogeneity in a given region under certain circumstances may exact the price of preventing outsiders from living there, even if they are willing to pay the going price for homes in that area. Another problem is posed by the prevalent view among liberal thinkers that the state must be neutral with respect to its citizens' way of life. The right to culture demands that the state abandon its neutral position and actively assist needy cultures, even when these cultures preach their own view of the good life which conflicts with other views within the state. In our opinion, the right to culture in a liberal state permits the state to be neutral, if at all, only with respect to the dominant culture of the majority, on the assumption that the dominant culture can take care of itself. But a liberal state may not be neutral with respect to the cultures of minorities, especially those in danger of dwindling or even disappearing. The state is obligated to abjure its neutrality, in our view, not for the sake of the good of the majority, but in order to make it possible for members of minority groups to retain their identity. Kymlicka's discussion of the rights of minority groups in a liberal state has become well-known (Kymlicka, 1989). One of the reasons this discussion is so powerful is that it uses the concrete example of native Canadians. We, too, will use two concrete examples to illustrate our principled discussion- two minority cultural groups in Israel: Israeli Arabs and Ultra- Orthodox Jews. Both of these groups are comprised of Israeli citizens living within the borders of Israel proper. We are not discussing the case of the Palestinian Arabs who have been living under Israeli occupation since 1967 and are not Israeli citizens. This group of nearly two million people living against their will under military occupation presents a much harder problem for Israel's aspiration to being a liberal state. Some background information about the Ultra-Orthodox is in order: Ultra-Orthodox culture is essentially anti-liberal. There is no aspect of its members' lives in which it does not This content downloaded from 137.110.74.76 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 19:06:54 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RIGHT TO CULTURE 493 actively interfere, sometimes to the extent of compulsion. This includes aspects that are considered prototypically private in liberal societies, such as having a television set in one's home, which is forbidden in Ultra-Orthodox society. Similarly, there is a ban on reading any newspapers other than those published by the community itself. The community may even react with violence against individuals who violate its rules. In some Ultra-Orthodox communities there are "morality squads" that follow, report on, threaten, and sometimes act violently against members whose "morality" does not accord with the commu- nity's extreme puritanism. In short, the Ultra-Orthodox way of life is rigidly enforced by the community and its institutions. The members' economic dependency on the community is almost absolute, so that any deviance can be punished by boycott, leading to the loss of one's livelihood. This society also makes "illiberal" demands on the conduct of outsiders in their public space. People walking in certain Ultra-Orthodox neighborhoods are categorically requested to wear "modest dress," which means, for example, that women may not wear sleeveless or even short-sleeved clothing. Since driving a vehicle is forbidden on the Sabbath by Orthodox Jewish law, anyone riding in a car in an Ultra-Orthodox neighborhood on the Sabbath- or even on a public road which the Ultra- Orthodox consider part of their public space- is liable to be greeted by shouts or even a hail of stones thrown at them (Margalit, 1989). The most important value in Ultra-Orthodox society is the study of Torah (the body of law and wisdom contained in the Jewish Scriptures and its sacred commentaries), and so it is not surprising that they consider education an issue of central importance. The school curriculum is controlled exclusively by the community, and there is a clear discrimination between the education of girls and of boys. Not only are they taught different subjects, but girls generally complete their education by the age of 18-19, while the education of males continues in some sense throughout their lives. Except for some elementary This content downloaded from 137.110.74.76 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 19:06:54 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 494 SOCIAL RESEARCH arithmetic, boys are taught almost no secular subjects. Their instruction is very intensive, but it is radically limited to religious subjects. The two groups discussed here together constitute more than a quarter of the citizens of Israel (18 percent Arabs and about 7-10 percent Ultra-Orthodox). In comparison, Canada's native population constitutes only one percent of the whole. It might seem that these numerical data are not important for a principled discussion of the proper attitude of liberal societies towards cultural groups, since principles are principles regardless of the number of people to which they apply. But if we want to learn from the way states actually treat groups of their citizens, the size of the groups is liable to have an effect. Another fact that is no less important than the size of a group is its territorial concentration. This can lead groups to demand the right to determine the form of their public space. Both Ultra-Orthodox Israeli Jews and Israeli Arabs live in territorial concentrations: the Ultra-Orthodox Jews in neigh- borhoods in Jerusalem and Bnei Braq (a town near Tel Aviv), and the Arabs in the Galilee and an area known as the "Triangle" in the center of the country. The Israeli National Anthem Story One We have been at a demonstration in Tel Aviv, which was organized jointly by Peace Now, the central Israeli peace movement, and the Committee of Arab Councils, the central political group of the Israeli Arabs. The demonstration was intended in part to express outrage at the terrible mass murder at the Machpela Cave in Hebron. Peace Now demonstrations always end with the singing of "Hatikva," the Israeli national anthem, but the demonstration following the Hebron massacre ended with a minute of silence instead. The feeling of many participants was that a national anthem This content downloaded from 137.110.74.76 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 19:06:54 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RIGHT TO CULTURE 495 intended solely for Jews could not be sung at a joint demonstration of Jews and Arabs following an outrage of this sort.