PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS and LETTERS the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS and LETTERS the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS AND LETTERS The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 2 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTIILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, University of Chicago RICHARD SORABJI, University ofLondon Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Free University, Amsterdam ROGER ARIEw, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University ofWaterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, Finnish Academy PAUL HOFFMAN, University of California, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, University ofIllinois, Chicago ALAIN DE LIBERA, Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, Sorbonne JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Universita degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Cornell University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS AND LETTERS A Selection Translated and Edited, with an Introduction by LEROY E. LOEMKER SECOND EDITION KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS DORDRECHT ! BOSTON ! LONDON ISBN-13: 978-90-277-0693-5 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-1426-7 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-0 I 0-1426-7 Published by Kluwer Academic Publishers, P.O. Box 17,3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Kluwer Academic Publishers incorporates the publishing programmes of D. Reidel, Martinus Nijhoff, Dr W. Junk and MTP Press. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Nethcrlands. First edition: 1956 by Chicago University Press, Chicago Second edition: 1969 by D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht Second edition/second print: 1989 by Kluwer Academic Publishers printed Oil acidfi'ec paper All Rights Reserved © 1989 by Kluwer Academic Publishers Softcover reprint of the hardcover I st Edition 1989 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. To Priscilla PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION The selections contained in these volumes from the papers and letters of Leibniz are intended to serve the student in two ways: first, by providing a more adequate and balanced conception of the full range and penetration of Leibniz's creative intellectual powers; second, by inviting a fresher approach to his intellectual growth and a clearer perception of the internal strains in his thinking, through a chronological arrangement. Much confusion has arisen in the past through a neglect of the develop­ ment of Leibniz's ideas, and Couturat's impressive plea, in his edition of the Opuscu/es et fragments (p. xii), for such an arrangement is valid even for incomplete editions. The beginning student will do well, however, to read the maturer writings of Parts II, III, and IV first, leaving Part I, from a period too largely neglected by Leibniz criticism, for a later study of the still obscure sources and motives of his thought. The Introduction aims primarily to provide cultural orientation and an exposition of the structure and the underlying assumptions of the philosophical system rather than a critical evaluation. I hope that together with the notes and the Index, it will provide those aids to the understanding which the originality of Leibniz's scientific, ethical, and metaphysical efforts deserve. My indebtedness to all who have in some measure aided me in the preparation of the translations and interpretations is so extensive as to forbid detailed acknowledg­ ment. Professor Paul Schrecker, whose knowledge of the thought forms and relations of Leibniz, and indeed, of seventeenth century thought in general, is unsurpassed, has read and corrected a large number of the translations, particularly in Volume I, and should be credited with setting norms for accuracy and adequacy. Professor Elizabeth DeLacey has exercised extensive editorial supervision, caught many defects, and suggested changes which have consistently improved the work. Beyond the extensive work of these, there are many others who deserve my gratitude for help rendered. A fellowship of the Rosenwald Foundation in 1938 and a grant from an anonymous source in 1951 enabled me to begin a detailed study of Leibniz, to make use of the Hanover manuscripts, and to confer with European scholars. The editors of the Prussian Academy edition, and the directors of the Hanover Landes­ bibliothek, gave generous advice and opportunities for study. Professor Helmut Kuhn, now of the University of Munich, checked the translations. For detailed answers to many questions I am indebted to more friends and colleagues than I can conveniently name. Publication was subsidized in part by a grant from the Research Committee of the University Center in Georgia, generously enlarged by Emory University. More important even than this, however, has been the climate of study provided by Emory University and its administration during troubled years of war and of uncertain peace. viii PREFACE To acknowledge with gratitude the social co-operation required in such work is a pleasure which does not, however, remove the uneasy recognition that the responsi­ bility for errors and other blights on the usefulness of these translations, being the fruits of solitary decision, must be borne by the translator and editor himself. All parentheses in the text are Leibniz's own, though some of his parentheses have been removed. All editorial interpolations are in brackets. Leibniz's own underscoring has been retained except when he used it to indicate direct quotation. The keys used throughout in references to the editions of Leibniz and related works may be identified in the Bibliography. Emory University. Georgia The appearance of a corrected edition of these Leibniz translations provides an op­ portunity to thank many who have suggested improvements in the text, and in particu­ lar Professor L. J. Russell of Birmingham and Professor G. H. R. Parkinson of Reading for their numerous corrections. I must also acknowledge gratfully the help given by Mrs. Linda Cornett, Mrs. Margaret Wood, and Mr. J. Brooke Hamilton in making the textual changes involved, and that of Mr. Grant Luckhardt in revising the Index. L.E.L. Emory University, 1969 T ABLE OF CONTENTS Preface vii Introduction: Leibniz as Philosopher 1 I. The 17th Century 2 II. Leibniz's Life and Work 4 III. The Metaphysical Pattern 13 IV. Leibniz's Method 19 V. Logic and the Principles of Truth and Reality 23 VI. Mathematics and Philosophy 28 VII. Physics and the Realm of Nature 31 VIII. Biology 35 IX. Psychology 37 X. Theory of Knowledge 41 XI. Summary: Structure and Purpose 44 XII. Ethics and Social Thought 46 XIII. Theology 49 XIV. Leibniz's Consistency and Influence 54 Bibliography 63 PART I. MAINZ AND PARIS, 1666-76 71 1. Dissertation on the Art of Combinations, 1666 (Selections) 73 I. Demonstration of the Existence of God 73 II. Corollaries for Disputation 74 III. Cum Deo! 76 Definitions 77 Problems 78 2. A New Method for Learning and Teaching Jurisprudence, 1667 (Selections from Part I) 85 Part I. General and Common to All Faculties: on a Basis for Studies in General 85 3. Letter to Jacob Thomasius, 1669 93 4. Letter to Thomas Hobbes, 1670 105 5. Theological Writings Related to the Catholic Demonstrations, 1668-70 109 I. The Confession of Nature against Atheists, 1669 109 II. A Fragment on Dreams 113 III. On Transubstantiation, 1668(?) 115 Supplement: Notes on the Eucharist, 1668 118 6. Preface to an Edition of Nizolius, 1670 (Selections) 121 x T ABLE OF CONTENTS 7. Elements of Natural Law, 1670-71 131 8. Studies in Physics and the Nature of Body, 1671 139 I. The Theory of Abstract Motion: Fundamental Principles 139 II. An Example of Demonstrations about the Nature of Corporeal Things Drawn from Phenomena 142 9. Letter to Magnus Wedderkopf, 1671 146 10. Letter to Antoine Arnauld, 1671 (Selection) 148 11. Letter to Simon Foucher, with Notes on Foucher's Reply to Des Gabets, 1675 151 12. Selections from the Paris Notes, 1676 157 13. Letter to Henry Oldenburg, 1675 165 14. Two Notations for Discussion with Spinoza, 1676 167 PART II. HANOVER TO THE ITALIAN JOURNEY, 1676-87 171 15. On a Method of Arriving at a True Analysis of Bodies and the Causes of Natural Things, 1677 173 16. Letter to Arnold Eckhard, 1677 177 17. Dialogue, 1677 182 18. Letter to Herman Conring, 1678 186 19. Letter to WaIter von Tschirnhaus, 1678 192 20. On the Ethics of Benedict de Spinoza, 1678 196 Part I. On God 196 21. What is an Idea? 1678 207 22. Letters to Nicolas Malebranche, 1679 (Selections) 209 23. Two Dialogues on Religion, ca. 1678 (Selections) 213 I. Dialogue between Poliander and Theophile 213 II. Dialogue between Polidore and Theophile 216 24. On the General Characteristic, ca. 1679 221 25. On Universal Synthesis and Analysis, or the Art of Discovery and Judgment, 1679(?) 229 26. Two Studies in the Logical Calculus, 1679 235 I. Elements of Calculus 235 II. Specimen of Universal Calculus 240 27. Studies in a Geometry of Situation, 1679 248 I. Letter to Christian Huygens, 1679 248 II. Supplement 249 III. On Analysis Situs 254 28. Letter to John Frederick, Duke of Brunswick-Hanover, 1679 259 29. On Freedom, ca. 1679 263 30. "First Truths", ca. 1680-84 267 31. Selections from Leibniz's Correspondence, 1679-84 272 I. To Christian Philipp, 1679 272 II. To Philipp, 1680 273 III. To Frantyois de la Chaise, 1680 273 IV.
Recommended publications
  • A Leibnizian Approach to Mathematical Relationships: a New Look at Synthetic Judgments in Mathematics
    A Thesis entitled A Leibnizian Approach to Mathematical Relationships: A New Look at Synthetic Judgments in Mathematics by David T. Purser Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy ____________________________________ Dr. Madeline M. Muntersbjorn, Committee Chair ____________________________________ Dr. John Sarnecki, Committee Member ____________________________________ Dr. Benjamin S. Pryor, Committee Member ____________________________________ Dr. Patricia Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo December 2009 An Abstract of A Leibnizian Approach to Mathematical Relationships: A New Look at Synthetic Judgments in Mathematics by David T. Purser Submitted to the Graduate Faculty in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2010 I examine the methods of Georg Cantor and Kurt Gödel in order to understand how new symbolic innovations aided in mathematical discoveries during the early 20th Century by looking at the distinction between the lingua characterstica and the calculus ratiocinator in the work of Leibniz. I explore the dynamics of innovative symbolic systems and how arbitrary systems of signification reveal real relationships in possible worlds. Examining the historical articulation of the analytic/synthetic distinction, I argue that mathematics is synthetic in nature. I formulate a moderate version of mathematical realism called modal relationalism. iii Contents Abstract iii Contents iv Preface vi 1 Leibniz and Symbolic Language 1 1.1 Introduction……………………………………………………. 1 1.2 Universal Characteristic……………………………………….. 4 1.2.1 Simple Concepts……………………………………….. 5 1.2.2 Arbitrary Signs………………………………………… 8 1.3 Logical Calculus………………………………………………. 11 1.4 Leibniz’s Legacy……………………………………………… 16 1.5 Leibniz’s Continued Relevance……………………………….
    [Show full text]
  • Programme RE2013
    Programme ‘The Radical Enlightenment: The Big Picture and its Details’ Universitaire Stichting, Egmontstraat 11, 1000 Brussels May 16-17 2013 Thursday 16 May 2013 8.20-8.55 a.m. Welcome and registration (with coffee) 8.55 a.m.-12.15 p.m. Morning session 8.55-9.00 a.m. Opening conference: Steffen Ducheyne (Room A) 9.00-10.00 a.m. Keynote lecture I Jonathan I. Israel (Room A): Radical Enlightenment: Monism and the Rise of Modern Democratic Republicanism 10.00-11.00 a.m. Keynote lecture II Wiep van Bunge (Room A): The Waning of the Radical Enlightenment in the Dutch Republic 11.00-11.15 a.m. Coffee break 11.15 a.m.-12.15 p.m. Keynote lecture III Else Walravens (Room A): The Radicality of Johann Christian Edelmann: A Synthesis of Progressive Enlightenment, Pluralism and Spiritualism 12.15-2.00 p.m. Lunch break 2.00-6.15 p.m. Afternoon session 2.00-3.30 p.m. Parallel session I Room A: Anya Topolski : Tzedekah : The True Religion of Spinoza’s Tractatus Jetze Touber: The Temple of Jerusalem in Picture and Detail: Biblical Antiquarianism and the Construction of Radical Enlightenment in the Dutch Republic, 1670-1700 Ian Leask : John Toland’s Origines Judaicae : Speaking for Spinoza? Room B: Ultán Gillen : Radical Enlightenment and Revolution in 1790s Ireland: The Ideas of Theobald Wolfe Tone Sonja Lavaert : Radical Enlightenment, Enlightened Subversion, and the Reversal of Spinoza Julio Seoane-Pinilla : Sade, Sex and Transgression in Eighteenth- century Philosophy 3.30-5.00 p.m. Parallel session II Room A: Falk Wunderlich : Late Enlightenment Materialism in Germany: The Case of Christoph Meiners and Michael Hißmann Paola Rumore : Between Spinozism and Materialism: Buddeus’ Place in the Early German Enlightenment Arnaud Pelletier : H ow much Radicality can the Enlightenment tolerate? The Case of Gabriel Wagner ( Realis de Vienna ) Reconsidered Room B: Vasiliki Grigoropoulou : Radical Consciousness in Spinoza and the Case of C.
    [Show full text]
  • Paola Rumore
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Institutional Research Information System University of Turin Paola Rumore In Wolff’s Footsteps. The Early German Reception of La Mettrie’s L’Homme machine 1. A specter personified At the end of 1747, when L’Homme machine began to circulate, the German philosophical scene was entering into a temporary truce in its long-lasting strug- gle against materialism, at that point still considered the most harmful and the disgraceful expression of free-thinking. This situation concerned mainly that large part of Germany, which had remained almost uncontaminated by the new Francophile trend that animated the cultural enclave of Frederick’s court in Berlin. In fact, according to one of the most authoritative interpreters of 18th century German philosophy, “the French Enlightenment had surely caused some disturbance in Sanssouci, but its resonance in the surrounding German world remained limited”1. The publication of L’Homme machine, often described as a “monument of disgrace and ignominy”2, forced Germany to face once again the phantom of materialism, which now appeared in the form of a real danger in a well-delineated shape, no longer a vague, undefined, and somehow spectral threat. The degree of reality of the current menace of materialism was also in- creased by the fact that the author of the book had been warmly welcomed at the Prussian court; L’Homme machine was not one of the usual phantomatic foreign dangers pressing up against the borders of the kingdom, but a real presence on German soil.
    [Show full text]
  • Conference Programme Radical Enlightenment
    Programme ‘The Radical Enlightenment: The Big Picture and its Details’ Universitaire Stichting, Egmontstraat 11, 1000 Brussels May 16-17 2013 Thursday 16 May 2013 8.15-8.50 a.m. Welcome and registration (with coffee) 8.50 a.m.-12.15 p.m. Morning session 8.50-8.55 a.m. Welcome by a representative of the Free University of Brussels (Room A) 8.55-9.00 a.m. Opening conference: Steffen Ducheyne (Room A) 9.00-10.00 a.m. Keynote lecture I Jonathan I. Israel (Room A, Chair: Steffen Ducheyne): Radical Enlightenment: Monism and the Rise of Modern Democratic Republicanism 10.00-11.00 a.m. Keynote lecture II Wiep van Bunge (Room A, Chair: Jean Paul Van Bendegem): The Waning of the Radical Enlightenment in the Dutch Republic 11.00-11.15 a.m. Coffee break 11.15 a.m.-12.15 p.m. Keynote lecture III Else Walravens (Room A, Chair: Wiep van Bunge): The Radicality of Johann Christian Edelmann: A Synthesis of Progressive Enlightenment, Pluralism and Spiritualism 12.15-2.00 p.m. Lunch break 2.00-6.45 p.m. Afternoon session 2.00-3.30 p.m. Parallel session I Room A (Chair: Yoni Van Den Eeden): Anya Topolski: Tzedekah: The True Religion of Spinoza’s Tractatus Jetze Touber: The Temple of Jerusalem in Picture and Detail: Biblical Antiquarianism and the Construction of Radical Enlightenment in the Dutch Republic, 1670-1700 Ian Leask: John Toland’s Origines Judaicae: Speaking for Spinoza? Room B (Chair: Stéphanie Van Droogenbroeck): Ultán Gillen: Radical Enlightenment and Revolution in 1790s Ireland: The Ideas of Theobald Wolfe Tone Sonja Lavaert: Radical Enlightenment, Enlightened Subversion, and the Reversal of Spinoza Julio Seoane-Pinilla: The Transgressive Enlightenment: The Critique of the Present and the Sadeian Order 3.30-5.00 p.m.
    [Show full text]
  • Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics
    THEODICY AND REASONTHEODICY Philosophica 2 — Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, GERETTO, PERISSINOTTO CAMPOSAMPIERO, FAVARETTI and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Edizioni Ca’Foscari Theodicy and Reason Philosophica Collana diretta da Luigi Perissinotto Cecilia Rofena 2 Edizioni Ca’Foscari Philosophica Direttori Luigi Perissinotto (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Cecilia Rofena (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Comitato scientifico Silvana Borutti (Università degli studi di Pavia, Italia) Jean-Pierre Cometti (Université de Provence - Aix-Marseille I, France) Arnold Davidson (University of Chicago, USA) Roberta Dreon (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Giuseppe Goisis (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Daniele Goldoni (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Mauro Nobile (Università degli Studi di Milano-Bicocca, Italia) Gian Luigi Paltrinieri (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte (Universitat de València-Estudi General, España) Direzione e redazione Univerisità Ca’ Foscari Venezia Dipartimento di Filosofia e Beni Culturali Palazzo Malcanton Marcorà Dorsoduro 3484/D, 30123 Venezia http://edizionicafoscari.unive.it/col/dbc/10/Philosophica Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Venezia Edizioni Ca’ Foscari - Digital Publishing 2016 Theodicy and Reason:
    [Show full text]
  • No Humble Pie: the Origins and Usage of a Statistical Chart
    Journal of Educational and Behavioral Statistics Winter 2005, Vol. 30, No. 4, pp. 353–368 No Humble Pie: The Origins and Usage of a Statistical Chart Ian Spence University of Toronto William Playfair’s pie chart is more than 200 years old and yet its intellectual ori- gins remain obscure. The inspiration likely derived from the logic diagrams of Llull, Bruno, Leibniz, and Euler, which were familiar to William because of the instruction of his mathematician brother John. The pie chart is broadly popular but—despite its common appeal—most experts have not been seduced, and the academy has advised avoidance; nonetheless, the masses have chosen to ignore this advice. This commentary discusses the origins of the pie chart and the appro- priate uses of the form. Keywords: Bruno, circle chart, Euler, Leibniz, Llull, logic diagrams, pie chart, Playfair 1. Introduction The pie chart is more than two centuries old. The diagram first appeared (Playfair, 1801) as an element of two larger graphical displays (see Figure 1 for one instance) in The Statistical Breviary, whose charts portrayed the areas, populations, and rev- enues of European states. William Playfair had previously devised the bar chart and was first to advocate and popularize the use of the line graph to display time series in statistics (Playfair, 1786). The pie chart was his last major graphical invention. Playfair was an accomplished and talented adapter of the ideas of others, and although we may be confident that we know his sources of inspiration in the case of the bar chart and line graph, the intellectual motivations for the pie chart and its parent, the circle chart, remain obscure.
    [Show full text]
  • Pico Della Mirandola Descola Gardner Eco Vernant Vidal-Naquet Clément
    George Hermonymus Melchior Wolmar Janus Lascaris Guillaume Budé Peter Brook Jean Toomer Mullah Nassr Eddin Osho (Bhagwan Shree Rajneesh) Jerome of Prague John Wesley E. J. Gold Colin Wilson Henry Sinclair, 2nd Baron Pent... Olgivanna Lloyd Wright P. L. Travers Maurice Nicoll Katherine Mansfield Robert Fripp John G. Bennett James Moore Girolamo Savonarola Thomas de Hartmann Wolfgang Capito Alfred Richard Orage Damião de Góis Frank Lloyd Wright Oscar Ichazo Olga de Hartmann Alexander Hegius Keith Jarrett Jane Heap Galen mathematics Philip Melanchthon Protestant Scholasticism Jeanne de Salzmann Baptist Union in the Czech Rep... Jacob Milich Nicolaus Taurellus Babylonian astronomy Jan Standonck Philip Mairet Moravian Church Moshé Feldenkrais book Negative theologyChristian mysticism John Huss religion Basil of Caesarea Robert Grosseteste Richard Fitzralph Origen Nick Bostrom Tomáš Štítný ze Štítného Scholastics Thomas Bradwardine Thomas More Unity of the Brethren William Tyndale Moses Booker T. Washington Prakash Ambedkar P. D. Ouspensky Tukaram Niebuhr John Colet Abū Rayhān al-Bīrūnī Panjabrao Deshmukh Proclian Jan Hus George Gurdjieff Social Reform Movement in Maha... Gilpin Constitution of the United Sta... Klein Keohane Berengar of Tours Liber de causis Gregory of Nyssa Benfield Nye A H Salunkhe Peter Damian Sleigh Chiranjeevi Al-Farabi Origen of Alexandria Hildegard of Bingen Sir Thomas More Zimmerman Kabir Hesychasm Lehrer Robert G. Ingersoll Mearsheimer Ram Mohan Roy Bringsjord Jervis Maharaja Sayajirao Gaekwad III Alain de Lille Pierre Victurnien Vergniaud Honorius of Autun Fränkel Synesius of Cyrene Symonds Theon of Alexandria Religious Society of Friends Boyle Walt Maximus the Confessor Ducasse Rāja yoga Amaury of Bene Syrianus Mahatma Phule Chhatrapati Shivaji Maharaj Qur'an Cappadocian Fathers Feldman Moncure D.
    [Show full text]
  • Primeiros Escritos Boletim De Pesquisa Na Graduação Em Filosofia
    Primeiros Escritos Boletim de Pesquisa na Graduação em Filosofia Pablo Picasso, A Grande Coruja (1948) Primeiros Escritos Boletim de Pesquisa na Graduação em Filosofia N- 2, período 98/99 Universidade de São Paulo Reitor: Prof. Dr. Jacques Marcovitch Vice-Reitor: Adolfo José Melfi Faculdade de Filosofia, Letras e Ciências Humanas Diretor: Prof. Dr. Francis Henrik Aubert Vice: Prof. Dr. Renato da Silva Queiroz Departamento de Filosofia Chefe: Prof. Dr. Ricardo Ribeiro Terra Vice: Prof. Dr. Franklin Leopoldo e Silva Programa de Iniciação Científica do Depto. de Filosofia (PIBIC-USP/CNPq) Coordenador: Prof. Dr. Moacyr Novaes Programa Especial de Treinamento da Área de Filosofia (PET/CAPES) Tutor: Prof. Dr. Caetano Ernesto Plastino Endereço para Correspondência A/C Coordenador do Programa de Iniciação Científica Departamento de Filosofia USP Av. Prof. Luciano Gualberto, 315 CEP 05508-900 Cidade Universitária São Paulo - S.P. Telefone: (011) 818-3761 Fax: (011) 211-2431 e-mail: [email protected] P r i m e ir o s E s c r it o s é uma publicação do D epartamento d e F il o s o f ia d a USP/SP Editor Responsável: Moacyr Novaes Editoração Eletrônica: Oliver Tolle Apoio: Guilherme Rodrigues Neto e todo o pessoal da secretaria do departamento Agradecimentos: MAC/USP e CAF Tiragem: 400 exemplares Apresentação O boletim de pesquisa na graduação em filosofia do Departamento de Filosofia da USP/SP chega ao seu segundo número. A publicação reúne os trabalhos apresentados no II Encontro de Pesquisa na Graduação em Filosofia, realizado neste Departamento em maio de 1998, e conta com a participação de alunos pesquisadores de outras instituições de ensino de filosofia pelo Brasil afora.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
    Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Alena Šolcová FIT ČVUT v Praze November 10, 2014 Alena Šolcová, CTU in Prague 1 The Stepped Reckoner of Gottfried Leibniz • The great polymath Gottfried Leibniz was one of the first men (after Raymundus Lullus and Athanasius Kircher), who dreamed for a logical (thinking) device. • Even more—Leibniz tried to combine principles of arithmetic with the principles of logic and imagined the computer as something more of a calculator— as a logical or thinking machine. • In his treatises De progressione He discovered also that Dyadica, March1679, and computing processes can be Explication de l'Arithmetique done much easier with a binary Binaire, 1703. numberNovember coding10, 2014 . Alena Šolcová, CTU in Prague 2 Calculating machine - the binary system • In the De progressione Dyadica Leibniz even describes a calculating machine which works via the binary system: a machine without wheels or cylinders—just using balls, holes, sticks and canals for the transport of the balls: • This [binary] calculus could be implemented by a machine (without wheels)... provided with holes in such a way that they can be opened and closed. • They are to be open at those places that correspond to a 1 and remain closed at those that correspond to a 0. • Through the opened gates small cubes or marbles are to fall into tracks, through the others nothing. • It [the gate array] is to be shifted from column to column as required...! November 10, 2014 Alena Šolcová, CTU in Prague 3 Dream of the general problem-solver • Leibniz dreamed of inventing the general problem-solver, as well as a universal language: • I thought again about my early plan of a new language or writing-system of reason, which could serve as a communication tool for all different nations..
    [Show full text]
  • On Judgement: Psychological Genesis, Intentionality and Grammar
    Durham E-Theses ON JUDGEMENT: PSYCHOLOGICAL GENESIS, INTENTIONALITY AND GRAMMAR KIRKBY, DAVID,JAMES How to cite: KIRKBY, DAVID,JAMES (2013) ON JUDGEMENT: PSYCHOLOGICAL GENESIS, INTENTIONALITY AND GRAMMAR, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/9451/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 ON JUDGEMENT: PSYCHOLOGICAL GENESIS, INTENTIONALITY AND GRAMMAR A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy by David James Kirkby Department of Philosophy University of Durham 2013 2 Abstract This thesis explores conceptions of judgement which have been central to various philosophical and scientific traditions. Beginning with Hume, I situate his conception of judgement within his overarching constructivist program, his science of man. Defending Hume from criticism regarding the naturalistic credentials of this program, I argue that Hume’s science of man, along with the conception of judgement which is integral to it, is appropriately understood as a forerunner to contemporary cognitive science.
    [Show full text]
  • And the Word Became Flesh: Logic and the Ontological Argument in Leibniz, Kant and Frege
    AND THE WORD BECAME FLESH: LOGIC AND THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT IN LEIBNIZ, KANT AND FREGE by Wynne Elizabeth Lanros BA, University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of University of Pittsburgh in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts University of Pittsburgh 2009 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This thesis was presented by Wynne Elizabeth Lanros It was defended on December 2nd, 2009 and approved by Dr. Steven Anthony Edwards, Associate Professor, Department of Religious Studies Dr. Nicholas Rescher, University Professor, Department of Philosophy Dr. Paula Kane, Associate Professor, Department of Religious Studies Thesis Advisor: Dr. Steven Anthony Edwards, Associate Professor, Department of Religious Studies ii AND THE WORD BECAME FLESH: LOGIC AND THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT IN LEIBNIZ, KANT AND FREGE Wynne Elizabeth Lanros, MA University of Pittsburgh, 2009 Historically, t he philosophical literature o n t he o ntological ar gument h as pr imarily been concerned w ith t he assessment o f t he argument in t erms o f its validity or lack t hereof. R arely have the logical foundations of validity itself been investigated in their relation to the argument. My t hesis seeks t o r emedy t his o mission by investigating t he c orrelation between c hanging conceptions of logic and ontological argumentation. To do so, I discuss the conceptions of logic employed by three of the most notable modern expositors of t he o ntological argument: Leibniz, Kant and Frege. I characterize their conceptions of logic in terms of formality and modality and subsequently r elate t hese c haracterizations t o their r espective cr itiques of t he on tological argument, establishing that an important correlation exists between one’s conception of logic and one’s a ssessment of on tological a rgumentation.
    [Show full text]
  • Siegfried Wollgast Aufklärung, Pädagogik Und Akademiegedanke
    Sitzungsberichte der Leibniz-Sozietät 106(2010), 57–104 der Wissenschaften zu Berlin Siegfried Wollgast Aufklärung, Pädagogik und Akademiegedanke Im Jahre 1784 schrieb Immanuel Kant seinen kleinen Aufsatz zur Beantwor- tung der Frage „Was ist Aufklärung“. Er formulierte, das Selbstverständnis einer Bewegung erfassend, die den Menschen zur Erkenntnis der Zusammen- hänge in Natur und Gesellschaft, zu Schöpfertum, geschichtsveränderndem Bewusstsein und gesellschaftlicher Kraft führen wollte: „Aufklärung ist der Ausgang des Menschen aus seiner selbst verschuldeten Unmündigkeit. Un- mündigkeit ist das Unvermögen, sich seines Verstandes ohne Leitung eines anderen zu bedienen. Selbstverschuldet ist die Unmündigkeit, wenn die Ursa- che derselben nicht an Mangel des Verstandes, sondern der Entschließung und des Mutes liegt, sich seiner ohne Leitung eines andern zu bedienen. Sa- pere aude! Habe Mut, dich deines eigenen Verstandes zu bedienen! ist also der Wahlspruch der Aufklärung!“ (Kant 1988, S. 215).1 Aufklärung bedeutet für alle bedeutenden Denker des 18. Jh.s den ent- scheidenden Programmpunkt zur Verwirklichung eines humanistischen Zeit- alters. Für Christoph Martin Wielands Romanhelden im „Agathon“ (1766- 1767) gründete sich „wahre Aufklärung“ auf „die Hoffnung besserer Zeiten, das ist, besserer Menschen […]“ (Wieland 1986, S. 774). Johann Gottfried Herder meinte in seinen „Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Mensch- heit“ (1784-1791), „dass mit der wachsenden wahren Aufklärung der Völker die menschenfeindlichen sinnlosen Zerstörungen derselben sich glücklich vermindert“ hätten. Für ihn war zunehmende Macht der Vernunft identisch mit Zunahme „an Humanität und ihren ewigen Gesetzen“ (Herder 1965, S. 225). Aufklärung war vornehmlich praxisbezogen, von der mittelbaren Praxis der Kritik bis zur unmittelbaren Praxis der Politik. Und sie war tendenziell stets Volksaufklärung.
    [Show full text]