Benjamin Peirce and the Howland Will

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Benjamin Peirce and the Howland Will Benjamin Peirce and the Howland Will Paul Meier; Sandy Zabell Journal of the American Statistical Association, Vol. 75, No. 371. (Sep., 1980), pp. 497-506. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0162-1459%28198009%2975%3A371%3C497%3ABPATHW%3E2.0.CO%3B2-G Journal of the American Statistical Association is currently published by American Statistical Association. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/astata.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Tue Apr 1 14:55:42 2008 Beniamin Peirce and the Howland Will PAUL MElER and SANDY ZABELL* The Howland will case is possibly the earliest instance in American that the earlier will should be recognized. But this the law of the use of probabilistic and statistical evidence. Identifying 30 downstrokes in the signature of Sylvia Ann Howland, Benjamin Executor, Thomas Mandell, declined to do. Not only Peirce attempted to show that a contested signature on a will had did he claim that the later will governed, but he also been traced from another and genuine signature. He argued that contended tht txvs-of the three signatures on the earlier their agreement in all 30 downstrokes was improbable in the ex- treme under a binomial model. Peirce supported his model by will were tracings from the third, thus providing an providing a graphical test of goodness of fit. We give a critique independent ground for invalidating that mill (see of Peirce's model and discuss the use and abuse of the "product Appendix I). rule" for multiplying probabilities of independent events. Hetty Robinson retained distinguished counsel and KEY WORDS: Charles S. Peirce; 19th-century mathematical sued.' Thomas blandel retained equally distinguished statistics; Law and statistics; Handwriting analysis; Independence; counsel and defended. Between them, both sides called Product rule. as witnesses some of the most prominent academicians 1. INTRODUCTION of the day. Oliver Wendell Holmes, Sr., Parkman Pro- fessor of Anatomy and Physiology in the Medical School On July 2, 1865, Sylvia Ann Howland of Xew Bedford, of Harvard University, examined the contested signa- Massachusetts, died, leaving an estate of $2,025,000, tures under a microscope, as did Louis Agassiz, and and a single heir-her niece Hetty H. Robinson, who testified (for Robinson) that he could find no evidence had lived with her for some years. Two million dollars is of pencil marks such as might have appeared in tracing. a respectable sum, even by today's inflated standards, (The cross-examination of Professor Holmes mas both and in 1865 it was certainly a prize worth contesting. brief and painful; see Appendix 2.) Among those testify- The Howland will, dated September 1, 1863, and a ing for the Executor were Benjamin Peirce, Professor of codicil of November 18, 1864, left half the estate to a Mathematics at Harvard, and his son, Charles Sanders number of individuals and institutions. It provided Peirce, who was later to do important work in several that the residue was to be held in trust for the benefit of branches of philosophy. The Peirces mere among the Hetty Robinson and, at the time of Hetty's death, to be first to contribute to the development of mathematical distributed to the lineal descendents of Hetty's paternal statistics in the United States; a recent survey of their grandfather, Gideon Howland, Sr. Hetty's father had work in this area is given in Stigler (1978, pp. 244-251). died a month earlier, leaving her $910,000 outright and Professor Peirce undertook to demonstrate by sta- the income from a trust of $5,000,000. Although Hetty tistical means that the disputed signatures on the second Robinson was thus already a wealthy woman, she page of the will were indeed forgeries. His method was claimed a right to inherit outright the entire estate of to contrast the similarities between one of the disputed her aunt, providing as evidence for this claim an earlier signatures (referred to in the trial record as signature mill, dated January 11, 1862, mhich left the entire estate # 10) and the unquestioned original (referred to as to Hetty with instructions that no later will was to be signature # 1) with the lesser degree of similarity to be honored. found in pairing 42 other signatures penned by Sylvia Family feuds are relevant here, as is a claimed agree- Ann Howland in her later years on other documents. ment between Hetty and her aunt to leave mutual wills (See Figures A and B.) It is this analysis with mhich excluding Hetty's father. For our purposes, it is enough we shall be concerned. to observe that Hetty Robinson had an arguable claim The Peirce analysis, as we shall see, is at once ingenious and in some respects naive. It leads to a distributional * Paul Meier is Professor of Statistics, The University of Chicago, problem, discussed in Appendix 4, which is nontrivial Chicago, IL 60637, and Sandy Zabell is Associate Professor of Mathematics, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL 60201. and has some interest in its own right. The data available Support for this research was provided in part by NSF Grant SOC 76-80389. The authors are grateful to a number of friends , 1865. Testimony was taken in 1867, decision ren- and colleagues with whom they discussed aspects of this case- dered october 1868 ( ~ ~ v. b~~~d~ll,i ~20 ~ ~~cas.d ~ 1027)., P. ~iaconis,S. Fienberg, J. Langbein, P. McCullagh, J. Tuke~* A copy of the trial transcript is available in the New Bedford Public and H. Zeisel, among others. Special thanks are due to David ~ i and theb testimony~ ~in the ~text ~ ~ ~2 and 3 is~ ~ ~ d i ~ ~ ~ Wallace for extensive discussion concerning the inference problem extracted from that source, that arose, and Stephen Stigler for helpful correspondence on the historical background. The staff of the New Bedford Public Library were especially accommodating in locating and arranging for the @ Journal of the American Statistical Association copying of unique source documents and exhibits, and to them September 1980, Volume 75, Number 371 the authors express their special gratitude. Applications Section 497 498 Journal of the American Statistical Association, September 1980 A. The Unquestioned Original Signature (no. 1)and human affairs. We should not be surprised, therefore, to the Two Disputed Signatures (nos. 10 and 15) find such imputations as a matter of course in tmhepresent problem. 2. THE PROBLEM Let us start with the evidence as given, making assumptions as needed, and return later to judge which seem plausible and which not. The evidence consisted of photographic copies of 42 signatures, in addition to the original (# 1) and one of the purported copies (#10). Suppose we are given some index of agreement be- tween signatures. In the present case Professor Peirce chose the number of coincidences-in length and posi- tion-among the 30 downstrokes in each of a pair of signatures, when the two were superimposed. We might then let XI, . ,XqZ be the values of that index obtained in the record is sufficient to allow some interesting in matching each of the 42 uncontested and uninvolved analyses, but tantalizing for its failure to include details signatures with # 1, and let Y be the value of that index of major relevance for the problem at issue. However, in matching # 10 with # 1. We could then pose the prob- as we proceed, it is well to keep in mind that no organized lem as one of judging whether Y could reasonably have theory of statistical inference existed at the time, and been drawn at random from the same population that that, for example, casual imputations of independence gave rise to the sample of size 42. were made almost automatically by those seeking to bring Since, in this case, Y = 30, that is, # 1 and # 10 coin- considerations of probability to bear on problems of cide in all 30 downstrokes, and the X, are presumably B. Some of the 42 Comparison Signatures Meier and Zabell: Benjamin Peirce and the Howland Will 499 all smaller than 30, we might assign a significance prob- 1. C. S. Peirce's Table of Coincidences ability of 1/43 = 2.3% to this outcome. This is a small - enough probability to raise suspicion, but far from over- Coincidences Number of Pairs Number of Strokes ~helrning.~(If we had available the individual X, values (which we do not) we might be willing to proceed a little more parametrically. We can determine (see Table 1) that the average index in random pairings of the 42 signatures is near 6 with a standard deviation of about 2.5.
Recommended publications
  • A Century of Mathematics in America, Peter Duren Et Ai., (Eds.), Vol
    Garrett Birkhoff has had a lifelong connection with Harvard mathematics. He was an infant when his father, the famous mathematician G. D. Birkhoff, joined the Harvard faculty. He has had a long academic career at Harvard: A.B. in 1932, Society of Fellows in 1933-1936, and a faculty appointmentfrom 1936 until his retirement in 1981. His research has ranged widely through alge­ bra, lattice theory, hydrodynamics, differential equations, scientific computing, and history of mathematics. Among his many publications are books on lattice theory and hydrodynamics, and the pioneering textbook A Survey of Modern Algebra, written jointly with S. Mac Lane. He has served as president ofSIAM and is a member of the National Academy of Sciences. Mathematics at Harvard, 1836-1944 GARRETT BIRKHOFF O. OUTLINE As my contribution to the history of mathematics in America, I decided to write a connected account of mathematical activity at Harvard from 1836 (Harvard's bicentennial) to the present day. During that time, many mathe­ maticians at Harvard have tried to respond constructively to the challenges and opportunities confronting them in a rapidly changing world. This essay reviews what might be called the indigenous period, lasting through World War II, during which most members of the Harvard mathe­ matical faculty had also studied there. Indeed, as will be explained in §§ 1-3 below, mathematical activity at Harvard was dominated by Benjamin Peirce and his students in the first half of this period. Then, from 1890 until around 1920, while our country was becoming a great power economically, basic mathematical research of high quality, mostly in traditional areas of analysis and theoretical celestial mechanics, was carried on by several faculty members.
    [Show full text]
  • The Generalization of Logic According to G.Boole, A.De Morgan
    South American Journal of Logic Vol. 3, n. 2, pp. 415{481, 2017 ISSN: 2446-6719 Squaring the unknown: The generalization of logic according to G. Boole, A. De Morgan, and C. S. Peirce Cassiano Terra Rodrigues Abstract This article shows the development of symbolic mathematical logic in the works of G. Boole, A. De Morgan, and C. S. Peirce. Starting from limitations found in syllogistic, Boole devised a calculus for what he called the algebra of logic. Modifying the interpretation of categorial proposi- tions to make them agree with algebraic equations, Boole was able to show an isomorphism between the calculus of classes and of propositions, being indeed the first to mathematize logic. Having a different purport than Boole's system, De Morgan's is conceived as an improvement on syllogistic and as an instrument for the study of it. With a very unusual system of symbols of his own, De Morgan develops the study of logical relations that are defined by the very operation of signs. Although his logic is not a Boolean algebra of logic, Boole took from De Morgan at least one central notion, namely, the one of a universe of discourse. Peirce crit- ically sets out both from Boole and from De Morgan. Firstly, claiming Boole had exaggeratedly submitted logic to mathematics, Peirce strives to distinguish the nature and the purpose of each discipline. Secondly, identifying De Morgan's limitations in his rigid restraint of logic to the study of relations, Peirce develops compositions of relations with classes. From such criticisms, Peirce not only devises a multiple quantification theory, but also construes a very original and strong conception of logic as a normative science.
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce for Whitehead Handbook
    For M. Weber (ed.): Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt, 2008, vol. 2, 481-487 Charles S. Peirce (1839-1914) By Jaime Nubiola1 1. Brief Vita Charles Sanders Peirce [pronounced "purse"], was born on 10 September 1839 in Cambridge, Massachusetts, to Sarah and Benjamin Peirce. His family was already academically distinguished, his father being a professor of astronomy and mathematics at Harvard. Though Charles himself received a graduate degree in chemistry from Harvard University, he never succeeded in obtaining a tenured academic position. Peirce's academic ambitions were frustrated in part by his difficult —perhaps manic-depressive— personality, combined with the scandal surrounding his second marriage, which he contracted soon after his divorce from Harriet Melusina Fay. He undertook a career as a scientist for the United States Coast Survey (1859- 1891), working especially in geodesy and in pendulum determinations. From 1879 through 1884, he was a part-time lecturer in Logic at Johns Hopkins University. In 1887, Peirce moved with his second wife, Juliette Froissy, to Milford, Pennsylvania, where in 1914, after 26 years of prolific and intense writing, he died of cancer. He had no children. Peirce published two books, Photometric Researches (1878) and Studies in Logic (1883), and a large number of papers in journals in widely differing areas. His manuscripts, a great many of which remain unpublished, run to some 100,000 pages. In 1931-58, a selection of his writings was arranged thematically and published in eight volumes as the Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Beginning in 1982, a number of volumes have been published in the series A Chronological Edition, which will ultimately consist of thirty volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce and the Founding of American Sociology
    Journal of Classical Sociology Copyright © 2006 SAGE Publications London, Thousand Oaks and New Delhi Vol 6(1): 23–50 DOI: 10.1177/1468795X06061283 www.sagepublications.com Peirce and the Founding of American Sociology NORBERT WILEY University of Illinois, Urbana ABSTRACT This paper argues that Charles Sanders Peirce contributed signific- antly to the founding of American sociology, doing so at the level of philosophical presuppositions or meta-sociology. I emphasize two of his ideas. One is semiotics, which is virtually the same as the anthropologists’ concept of culture. This latter concept in turn was essential to clarifying the sociologists’ idea of the social or society. Peirce also created the modern theory of the dialogical self, which explained the symbolic character of human beings and proved foundational for social psychology. Politically Peirce was a right-wing conservative, but his ideas eventually contributed to the egalitarian views of culures and sub-cultures. In addition his ideas contributed, by way of unanticipated consequences, to the 20th- century human rights revolutions in the American legal system. Thus he was both a founder of sociology and a founder of American political liberalism. KEYWORDS early American sociology, inner speech, Peirce, semiotics Introduction Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) originated several ideas that contributed to social theory, particularly to its philosophical underpinnings. Some of these are in unfamiliar contexts and in need of a slight re-framing or re-conceptualization. They also need to be related to each other. But, assuming these finishing touches, Peirce hadFirst a cluster of powerful insights that tradeProof heavily on the notions of the symbolic, the semiotic, the dialogical, the cultural and the self – ideas central to social theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Victor Lenzen Papers, [Ca
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/tf0580018d No online items Guide to the Victor Lenzen Papers, [ca. 1904-1975] Processed by The Bancroft Library staff The Bancroft Library. University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, California, 94720-6000 Phone: (510) 642-6481 Fax: (510) 642-7589 Email: [email protected] URL: http://bancroft.berkeley.edu © 1997 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Note History --History, University of California --History, UC SystemHistory --History, University of California --History, UC BerkeleyGeographical (By Place) --University of California --University of California BerkeleySocial Sciences --Anthropology --ArchaeologyPhysical Sciences --PhysicsSocial Sciences --Education Guide to the Victor Lenzen BANC MSS 76/206 c 1 Papers, [ca. 1904-1975] Guide to the Victor Lenzen Papers, [ca. 1904-1975] Collection number: BANC MSS 76/206 c The Bancroft Library University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, California Contact Information: The Bancroft Library. University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, California, 94720-6000 Phone: (510) 642-6481 Fax: (510) 642-7589 Email: [email protected] URL: http://bancroft.berkeley.edu Processed by: The Bancroft Library staff Date Completed: ca. 1976 Encoded by: Xiuzhi Zhou © 1997 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Collection Summary Collection Title: Victor Lenzen papers, Date (inclusive): [ca. 1904-1975] Collection Number: BANC MSS 76/206 c Creator: Lenzen, Victor Fritz, 1890-1975 Extent: Number of containers: 5 cartons, 7 boxes and 1 oversize folder Repository: The Bancroft Library. Berkeley, California 94720-6000 Physical Location: For current information on the location of these materials, please consult the Library's online catalog. Abstract: Letters written to Lenzen and copies of letters by him; Mss.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Economics Comes to America: Charles S
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Wible, James R.; Hoover, Kevin D. Working Paper Mathematical Economics Comes to America: Charles S. Peirce's Engagement with Cournot's Recherches sur les Principes Mathematiques de la Theorie des Richesses CHOPE Working Paper, No. 2013-12 Provided in Cooperation with: Center for the History of Political Economy at Duke University Suggested Citation: Wible, James R.; Hoover, Kevin D. (2013) : Mathematical Economics Comes to America: Charles S. Peirce's Engagement with Cournot's Recherches sur les Principes Mathematiques de la Theorie des Richesses, CHOPE Working Paper, No. 2013-12, Duke University, Center for the History of Political Economy (CHOPE), Durham, NC This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/149703 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Views of Russell and Russell's Logic by His
    SOME VIEWS OF RUSSELL AND RUSSELL’S LOGIC BY HIS CONTEMPORARIES, WITH PARTICULAR REFERENCE TO PEIRCE IRVING H. ANELLIS In the years prior to World War I, it was not yet definitively certain that the new logistic developed and espoused by Frege and Russell was the “wave of the future” of mathematical logic. Ernst Schröder’s Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (1895– 1905) was still new and viewed as the cutting edge of (algebraic—as opposed to Aristote- lian) logic; Giuseppe Peano still proclaimed, in his earliest work on logic, his indebted- ness to George Boole, Charles Peirce, and Ernst Schröder, in the first footnote of his Arithmetices principia nova methodo exposita (1898), while, in a letter to Russell of 19 March 1901,1 Peano told Russell that his paper “Sur la logique des relations avec des ap- plications à la théorie des séries” on the logic of relations (1901) just “fills a gap between the work of Peirce and Schröder on the one hand and” his own “Formulaire on the other;” Alfred North Whitehead’s Treatise on Universal Algebra (1898) also still new, brought together the algebraic logic of Boole with the linear and multilinear algebras of Arthur Cayley, James Joseph Sylvester, William Rowan Hamilton, and Charles Peirce’s father Benjamin Peirce, and the calculus of extension of Hermann Grassmann. In his Treatise, Whitehead (p. x) not only named Hamilton and De Morgan as “the first to ex- press quite clearly the general possibilities of algebraic symbolism,” but continually ex- pressed his indebtedness to Boole, Grassmann, De Morgan, Schröder, and John Venn; and he described his Treatise (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Writings
    Philosophy Peirce The philosophy of mathematics plays a hilosophy of Peirce’s most vital role in the mature philosophy of Charles s. Peirce. Peirce received rigorous P importa-nt mathematical training from his father and Ma-thema-tic his philosophy carries on in decidedly philosophy Selected Writings writings on the mathematical and symbolic veins. For S Peirce, math was a philosophical tool and philosophy of many of his most productive ideas rest firmly on the foundation of mathematical cha-rles S. Peirce ma-thema-tics principles. This volume collects Peirce’s most important writings on the subject, many appearing in print for the first time. “Focuses on the major Peirce’s determination to understand writings Peirce produced matter, the cosmos, and “the grand design” of the universe remain relevant that are of greatest for contemporary students of science, significance for a correct technology, and symbolic logic. of appreciation of his larger Charles s. PeirCe (1839–1914) Ma-thema-ti was one of america’s most prolific philosophical agenda.” philosophers. he is noted for his —JosePh W. Dauben, contributions to logic, mathematics, City university oF neW york science, and semiotics. MattheW e. Moore is associate Professor of Philosophy at brooklyn College. he is editor of New Essays on Peirce’s Mathematical Philosophy. c Selections from the Writings of Cha-rles S. Peirce s PeirCe Edition ProJeCt INDIANA University Press Bloomington & Indianapolis www.iupress.indiana.edu INDIANA Edited by Ma-tthew E. Moore 1-800-842-6796 Phil of Mathematics MECH.indd 1 6/30/10 10:04 AM Beings of Reason.book Page i Wednesday, June 2, 2010 6:06 PM Philosophy of Mathematics Beings of Reason.book Page ii Wednesday, June 2, 2010 6:06 PM Beings of Reason.book Page iii Wednesday, June 2, 2010 6:06 PM Philosophy of Mathematics Selected Writings Charles S.
    [Show full text]
  • The Charles S. Peirce-Simon Newcomb Correspondence
    The Charles S. Peirce-Simon Newcomb Correspondence Carolyn Eisele Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, Vol. 101, No. 5. (Oct. 31, 1957), pp. 409-433. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0003-049X%2819571031%29101%3A5%3C409%3ATCSPNC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-L Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society is currently published by American Philosophical Society. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/amps.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Tue Mar 11 07:51:41 2008 THE CHARLES S.
    [Show full text]
  • Simon Newcomb Papers [Finding Aid]. Library of Congress. [PDF Rendered
    Simon Newcomb Papers A Finding Aid to the Collection in the Library of Congress Manuscript Division, Library of Congress Washington, D.C. 2014 Contact information: http://hdl.loc.gov/loc.mss/mss.contact Additional search options available at: http://hdl.loc.gov/loc.mss/eadmss.ms014072 LC Online Catalog record: http://lccn.loc.gov/mm79034629 Prepared by Manuscript Division Staff Collection Summary Title: Simon Newcomb Papers Span Dates: 1813-1949 Bulk Dates: (bulk 1865-1909) ID No.: MSS34629 Creator: Newcomb, Simon, 1835-1909 Extent: 46,000 items ; 145 containers plus 8 oversize ; 61.2 linear feet Language: Collection material in English Location: Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, D.C. Summary: Astronomer, mathematician, and economist. Correspondence, diaries, commonplace books, drafts of speeches, articles, reviews, and books, financial papers, genealogical papers, charts, tables, computations, photos, and printed matter reflecting Newcomb's personal and family life, his work in mathematics and astronomy, his writing of articles for encyclopedias and other publications, and his work as president of the International Congress of Arts and Sciences. Selected Search Terms The following terms have been used to index the description of this collection in the Library's online catalog. They are grouped by name of person or organization, by subject or location, and by occupation and listed alphabetically therein. People Barnard, Edward Emerson, 1857-1923--Correspondence. Bell, Alexander Graham, 1847-1922--Correspondence. Boss, Lewis, 1846-1912--Correspondence. Burnham, S. W. (Sherburne Wesley), 1838-1921--Correspondence. Campbell, William Wallace, 1862-1938--Correspondence. Cattell, James McKeen, 1860-1944--Correspondence. Davidson, George, 1825-1911--Correspondence. Gill, David, 1843-1914--Correspondence.
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Generated By
    10 Logic of Relations and Diagrammatic Reasoning: Structuralist Elements in the Work of Charles Sanders Peirce Jessica Carter 1. Introduction This chapter presents aspects of the work of Charles Sanders Peirce, illustrating how he adhered to a number of the pre- structuralist themes characterized in the introduction to this volume. I shall present aspects of his contributions to math- ematics as well as his philosophy of mathematics in order to show that relations occupied an essential role. When writing about results in mathematics he often states that they are based on his “logic of relatives,” and he refers to the reasoning of mathematics as “diagrammatic reasoning.” Besides pointing to structural themes in Peirce’s work, much of this exposition will be devoted to explaining what is meant by these two phrases. In a recent article Christopher Hookway (2010) places Peirce as an ante rem structuralist.1 In support of this claim Hookway refers to some of Peirce’s writings on numbers (also to be treated here). In addition he spends some time analyzing what Peirce means by the phrase “the form of a relation.” These con- siderations involve an in-depth knowledge of Peirce’s categories and their met- aphysical implications. In contrast I will focus on methodological aspects, in particular Peirce’s writings on reasoning in mathematics, stressing that mathe- matics consists of the activity of drawing necessary inferences. This leads to a po- sition that resembles methodological structuralism as it is characterized in Reck and Price (2000). Furthermore I find that Peirce’s position is similar in spirit to the contemporary categorical structuralist views, in particular, as formulated by Steve Awodey (2004).
    [Show full text]
  • Charles S. Peirce and the Abduction of God
    International Conference Institute for American Religious and Philosophical Thought Pamplona, 29 julio-1 agosto 2013 Charles S. Peirce and the Abduction of God Jaime Nubiola1 (University of Navarra, Spain) [email protected] [Text of Oral Presentation] "I would with all my heart join the ancient church of Rome if I could" C. S. Peirce, Letter to George Searle, August 9, 1895 (L 397) The relatively scant attention paid in scholarship throughout the years to the religious dimensions of Peirce's thought has always seemed to me to be at least surprising. Since my first readings of Peirce twenty years ago I had been deeply struck by this neglect that contrasted so much with the ubiquity of religious references in his writings, especially in his mature years. In my meetings with well-known Peirce scholars I used to ask them about God and religion in Peirce, and mostly the answer that I received was plainly that there was a lot of religious stuff in Peirce, but that they were not interested in it. On the other hand, I was pleasantly surprised by Walker Percy when in his correspondence with Kenneth Ketner he considered himself as "a thief of Peirce", intending "to use CSP as one of the pillars of a Christian apologetic" (Samway 1995, 130). It seemed to me that Percy was in some sense nearer to the real Peirce than those scholars whom I had asked about God and religion in Peirce. My reaction to these conflicting approaches was to decide that the whole matter deserved careful attention and I suggested this area of research to three of my graduate students.
    [Show full text]