Translation of Laruelle's “Badiou and Non-Philosophy: a Parallel

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Translation of Laruelle's “Badiou and Non-Philosophy: a Parallel Translation of Laruelle’s “Badiou and Non-Philosophy: a Parallel” | Speculative Heresy 3/26/13 7:30 PM Translation of Laruelle’s “Badiou and Non- Philosophy: a Parallel” Posted on March 6, 2010 by Taylor Adkins Translator’s Note: In order to avoid any sort of confusion, it should be noted that this article was included in an anthology of essays engaging various aspects of non-philosophy in contemporary philosophers. This article immediately follows Laruelle’s own essay responding to Deleuze, but was–for reasons that will become clear after reading–published under the pseudonym Tristan Aguilar. Badiou and Non-Philosophy: A Parallel Aguilar, Tristan. “Badiou et non-philosophie: un parallel” in Non-philosophie des contemporains. Ed. Le Collectif non-philosophique. Paris: Kimé, 1995. I. Everything seems to force the opposition between non-philosophy and the philosophy that takes the equation mathematics=ontology as its ontological base. This opposition can be identified on four levels: 1. The central and guiding theme: on the one hand, a philosophy of the radical Multiple (Badiou=B.); on the other hand, a non-philosophy of the radical One (Laruelle=L.). One cannot, at least at first glance, imagine thoughts more extreme or more opposed in their common research of radicality in the name of anti- contemporary radicality (the philosophies of difference: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Deleuze, Derrida). 2. The object of thought: on the one hand (B.) Being, a more-than-fundamental ontology, a veritable ontological base for philosophy, an overhaul of the concept of “being” as first: on the other (L.) a secondarization of being as an instance of a completely relative autonomy on behalf of the One as radical immanence or instance of the absolutely non-objective real; a global and resolute refusal to understand the real as Being and consequently a refusal to understand the essence of thought, if not thought itself, as ontology, be it “Presence” or not. 3. Thought itself: on the one hand (B.) the militant claim of philosophy against the ideology of its “death” or its “end” (in which B. tends to include L.) under the reserve of a certain anti-Heideggerian dissociation of ontology and philosophy itself, a division internal to philosophy but of external or scientific origin: on the other, a claim of “non-philosophy” and an external though immanent distinction of philosophy https://speculativeheresy.wordpress.com/2010/03/06/translation-of-laruelles-badiou-and-non-philosophy-a-parallel/ Page 1 of 8 Translation of Laruelle’s “Badiou and Non-Philosophy: a Parallel” | Speculative Heresy 3/26/13 7:30 PM and non-philosophy, a distinction which is itself non-philosophical or founded in the ante-philosophical and no longer philosophical (B.) real. On the one hand, a hero-philosopher who inscribes himself in the Cartesian, Nietzschean, and Mallarmean tradition of the heroic philosopher; on the other, a reduction of philosophy to the state of material or object of a thought which is that of “ordinary man.” Plato and Rousseau? Plato and Kant? Plato and Marx? 4. The conjuncture and the project: on the one hand (B.) how to supplant Heidegger by resuming the foundational Platonic gesture, how to avoid the Heideggerian extinction of ontology (under the form of the ontology of “Presence,” with its “post-modern” aftereffects); on the other (L.) how to elaborate a thought outside-philosophy but relating itself to every philosophy possible, modern and post-modern indifferently rather than to a particular philosophical decision (Platonic or contemporary, post-modern)? On the one hand, in what way does the fidelity to ontology demand a new, i.e. Platonico-modern ontology; on the other, how do we deliver thought from ontico-ontological primacy and more generally from every philosophical sufficiency by elaborating a new thought adequate to an experience of the One, an unprecedented experience foreclosed by philosophy? II. However, this antinomy, to indeed be real, must be nuanced and differentiated. Is it necessary to remember that, by definition, they do not speak of the same things when they use the same words? And that it thus cannot be a question of fabricating a simplistic opposition that would take these thoughts avant la lettre without a minimum of textual hermeneutics, as this is always necessary during the historical emergence of doctrines? 1. If they both oppose the Multiple and the One, it is no longer a question of the Multiple and the One which form circlets or co-belongings like in the metaphysics of “Presence” or in Greek ontology before Plato’s most radical decisions, or like the state of affairs after Plato and Descartes. B. liberates the Multiple (in principle it is at least supposed liberated) from any unity: Multiple-of-multiples ad infinitum; Being contains nothing but the multiple without unity. L. liberates the one from the multiple and from the unity of their mixtures; hence a One-in-One (we shall compare the formulas “multiple-of-multiples” and “One-in-One”) or a real as identity through and through or radical immanence (to) itself rather than to the “unity”-form. The radicality of the positions simultaneously rigidifies and softens the antinomy which must no longer be thought according to the schemas, at least the most traditional, of the philosophical antithetic. For example, both thinkers agree upon carrying out the “death of the Greek god of the One,” even if they do not interpret this formula in the same way, the first reducing every possible One to the One of the metaphysics of Presence and its real content, the One of counting, the second distinguishing from these adulterated or empirico- metaphysical forms a One-in-One which has remained absolutely unthought by philosophy or foreclosed by it (including by B.’s ontology). 2. Neither thinks philosophy without a de jure relation to science, even if they place themselves https://speculativeheresy.wordpress.com/2010/03/06/translation-of-laruelles-badiou-and-non-philosophy-a-parallel/ Page 2 of 8 Translation of Laruelle’s “Badiou and Non-Philosophy: a Parallel” | Speculative Heresy 3/26/13 7:30 PM between these disciplines and have two different relations to them. Epistemology under its different forms, all differentialist to various degrees (idealist, positivist, applied-rationalist, critical, etc.), is de-programmed and eliminated as a sterile or fetishizing combination of philosophy and science. They oppose to it an identity of science and philosophy rather than a difference; identity either partial, but internal on behalf of philosophy (B.) which divides the latter, or total but external or assured by a non-philosophical cause which guarantees the undivided identity of philosophy (L.). 3. Both involve a privileged relation to Marxism, a relation more (B.) or less (L.) explicit. B. engages dialectical Materialism transformed moreover in its materialist side (Being or multiple in-itself) and in its dialectical side (multiplicity of the set-theoretical type). L. instead engages historical Materialism, transformed in its materialist side (the real as One-in-One) and in its historical side (philosophy as enveloping or universal horizon of human practices). 4. The relation to philosophy no longer has the simplicity that certain slogans or appearances might suggest. B. does not completely or without distinction maintain a homogeneous relation to philosophy which L. would call “sufficiency” of the “philosophy-all” type, despite the Manifesto for Philosophy: this relation to philosophy or of philosophy to itself is internally divided or restrained by science (mathematics), philosophy identifying itself with science and in some sense depriving itself of its traditional ontological core, a function now assumed by mathematics. Ontology is then a special form of “non-philosophy” inside philosophy itself. L. does not maintain, despite certain contrary appearances, a relation of negation, but a positive relation to philosophy, and merely a relation of suspension to its so-called sufficiency for the real. The distinction passes in B. between two “parts” of philosophy that globally conserve its authority and a prohibited or truncated form of sufficiency; in L. it passes into the “philosophy-all,” i.e. between the “Principle of philosophical sufficiency” and the identity of philosophy as simple material. The first opens philosophy from the inside to mathematics; the second opens it from the outside to a thought which is nevertheless immanent (only the radical immanence of the One-in-One can be absolutely heteronomous to philosophy and yet “act” upon it). B. affirms philosophy by sacrificing its ontology to science, while L. neither affirms nor denies philosophy but sacrifices its global sufficiency or its claim to an immanent though heteronomous identity of science and philosophy. III. This first attempt at relating B. and L. sought to scramble the appearances and complicate any sort of judgment. It is possible to carry the comparison further or complete these indications. 1. The One, Being, the Multiple. a) The real is understood either (B.) as Being, i.e. radical exteriority, not in relation to something else but in-itself (multiple-of-multiples) or in a certain way, just as the immanence of pure transcendence is thus released to itself and is absolutely autonomous; or (L.) as One, i.e. radical immanence which is not the immanence of an exteriority in-itself, but immanence (to) itself rather than in-itself. The common adversary for https://speculativeheresy.wordpress.com/2010/03/06/translation-of-laruelles-badiou-and-non-philosophy-a-parallel/ Page 3 of 8 Translation of Laruelle’s “Badiou and Non-Philosophy: a Parallel” | Speculative Heresy 3/26/13 7:30 PM these thinkers is transcendent unity, synthesis in general, difference in particular, but in the name of pure Being, Being in-itself, or even the One-in-One. In reality, the refusal to various degrees bears upon metaphysical autoposition in the name of a certain identity (or non-difference) of the pure Multiple or even of Immanence.
Recommended publications
  • On First Understanding Plato's Republic
    The European Journal of International Law Vol. 22 no. 4 © EJIL 2011; all rights reserved .......................................................................................... On First Understanding Plato’s Republic Philip Allott* Downloaded from A book can change a mind, but only if that mind is ready to be changed. The mind of a particular child formed, up to the age of reason, in a time of war, is liable to be ready to ask questions of a particular kind about the human condition – still more so, when, at http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ the age of eight, that child sees, on the front-page of the newspaper, images of Belsen and Hiroshima, images that would never be forgotten. In the 1940s it was still pos- sible to believe in childish innocence. Now even small children know too much about the worst that human beings can do. Beyond the age of reason, social influences interact with the particular character of our own mind and our own personal experience to form an ever-evolving idea, an ever-denser idea, of the human condition, forcing us to live our lives in an uncomfort- able reconciling of our own private worldview and the worldview imposed on us by by Robert Sedgwick on February 1, 2012 society. Books intrude into that process of self-evolving in a unique way. The private activity of other minds reaches far into our own mind through the very private activity of reading. Philosophy is an active presence in our minds, even in the minds of those who have never read a single sentence in a single book of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Idealism and Pragmatism in the Rhetoric of John Boehner
    Idealism and Pragmatism in the Rhetoric of John Boehner: A Weaverian Analysis of Congressional Discourse Presented to the Faculty Liberty University School of Communication Studies In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Master of Arts in Communication Studies by Cody Ryan Hawley June 2014 Hawley 1 Thesis Committee William L. Mullen, Ph.D., Chair Date Faith E. Mullen, Ph.D. Date Cecil V. Kramer, D.Min. Date Hawley 2 Copyright © 2014 Cody Ryan Hawley All Rights Reserved Hawley 3 To Chuck and Kathy Hawley, My beloved parents, Responsible for All I am, And all I hope to be Hawley 4 Acknowledgements This Thesis represents the cumulative effort of countless individuals, many of whom may never know the debt to them I owe. Although I cannot name all, I wish to voice my appreciation for a few. First, Dr. William Mullen is the most any one could ever ask for in a Chair. His advice was always timely and wise, his encouragement genuine. In my life he has played countless roles–as instructor, advisor, rhetorical confidant, golf partner and friend. His influence has strengthened my resolve to attain knowledge and my commitment for a higher standard in education. There is no other one individual who has more prepared me for success in my future doctoral studies. I wish also to thank Dr. Faith Mullen and Dr. Cecil Kramer for their eagerness to serve as readers. Dr. Faith’s concern for her students is unparalleled, and I have not known a teacher more willing to go above and beyond to meet their needs.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: the Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin
    ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: The Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin Russell, Ph.D. It is widely acknowledged that W. H. Auden became a Christian in about 1940, but relatively little critical attention has been paid to Auden‟s theology, much less to the particular theological sources of Auden‟s faith. Auden read widely in theology, and one of his earliest and most important theological influences on his poetry and prose is Saint Augustine of Hippo. This dissertation explains the Augustinian origin of several crucial but often misunderstood features of Auden‟s work. They are, briefly, the nature of evil as privation of good; the affirmation of all existence, and especially the physical world and the human body, as intrinsically good; the difficult aspiration to the fusion of eros and agape in the concept of Christian charity; and the status of poetry as subject to both aesthetic and moral criteria. Auden had already been attracted to similar ideas in Lawrence, Blake, Freud, and Marx, but those thinkers‟ common insistence on the importance of physical existence took on new significance with Auden‟s acceptance of the Incarnation as an historical reality. For both Auden and Augustine, the Incarnation was proof that the physical world is redeemable. Auden recognized that if neither the physical world nor the human body are intrinsically evil, then the physical desires of the body, such as eros, the self-interested survival instinct, cannot in themselves be intrinsically evil. The conflict between eros and agape, or altruistic love, is not a Manichean struggle of darkness against light, but a struggle for appropriate placement in a hierarchy of values, and Auden derived several ideas about Christian charity from Augustine.
    [Show full text]
  • COLERIDGE, PHILOSOPHY and RELIGION Aids to Re¯Ection and the Mirror of the Spirit
    COLERIDGE, PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION Aids to Re¯ection and the Mirror of the Spirit DOUGLAS HEDLEY University of Cambridge published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB22RU, UK www.cup.cam.ac.uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011±4211, USA www.cup.org 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia Ruiz de AlarcoÂn 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain # Cambridge University Press 2000 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2000 Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeface 11/12.5pt Baskerville [CE] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library isbn 0 521 77035 1 Hardback Contents Acknowledgements page ix List of abbreviations xi Notes on the text xiii Prologue: explaining Coleridge's explanation 1 1 The true philosopher is the lover of God 18 A spiritual philosophy 21 The revival of natural theology 29 Platonism 33 The Platonic Trinity 36 German Idealism and the Platonic Tradition 40 Paley, Locke and Socinianism 45 Priestley, Unitarianism and Platonic idealism 49 Identity and difference: henology or ontology? 59 Supreme being and self-consciousness 65 `iamwhoiam'75 2 Inner word: re¯ection as meditation 88 Aphorism 89 Meditation and awakening:
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy), P.G.Govt
    Dr. Desh Raj Sirswal, Assistant Professor (Philosophy), P.G.Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com The word “Idealism” ought not to suggest ‘ideas’ as if idealism were some sort of reformist movement or exclusively ethical system.The word idealism is derived from the Greek word ‘idea’ which simply means something seen. Plato used this word in his philosophy as a technical term for ‘universals’ opposite word to particulars. Here we will study idealism with its forms. In philosophy, idealism is the group of philosophies which assert that reality, or reality as we can know it, is fundamentally mental, mentally constructed, or otherwise immaterial. Epistemologically, idealism manifests as a skepticism about the possibility of knowing any mind-independent thing In modern philosophy the word idealism is used to describe the view that reality is of the nature of ideas, that mind or self is the fundamental reality. It means that external world cannot exist independently without mind. Here is two types of idealism Objective Idealism Subjective Idealism Objective idealism asserts that the reality of experiencing combines and transcends the realities of the object experienced and of the mind of the observer. Proponents include Thomas Hill Green, Josiah Royce, Benedetto Croce and Charles Sanders Peirce. Absolute idealism is G. W. F. Hegel's account of how existence is comprehensible as an all-inclusive whole. Hegel called his philosophy "absolute" idealism in contrast to the "subjective idealism" of Berkeley and the "transcendental idealism" of Kant and Fichte, which were not based on a critique of the finite and a dialectical philosophy of history as Hegel's idealism was.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Confessiones: the Battle Between Two Conversions
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 11-12-2018 Augustine's Confessiones: The Battle between Two Conversions Robert Hunter Craig University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy of Science Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Craig, Robert Hunter, "Augustine's Confessiones: The Battle between Two Conversions" (2018). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/8109 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Augustine’s Confessiones: The Battle between Two Conversions by Robert Hunter Craig A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy with a concentration in Philosophy and Religion College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Co-Major Professor: Michael DeJonge, Ph.D. William Goodwin, Ph.D. Alexander Levine, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 2, 2018 Keywords: Autopsychographical, Theo-Ratiocination, Conversion, Consciousness, Pedagogic-Apologetic Copyright © 2018, Robert Hunter Craig DEDICATED TO: God To my wife Terry Lee Craig To my professor and pastor James F. Strange PREFACE I can recall reading the Confessiones of Augustine in 1988 for the first time when I was a sophomore at Stetson University in my Introduction to Philosophy class.
    [Show full text]
  • Contents More Information
    Cambridge University Press 0521770351 - Coleridge, Philosophy and Religion: Aids to Reflection and the Mirror of the Spirit Douglas Hedley Table of Contents More information Contents Acknowledgements page ix List of abbreviations xi Notes on the text xiii Prologue: explaining Coleridge's explanation 1 1 The true philosopher is the lover of God 18 A spiritual philosophy 21 The revival of natural theology 29 Platonism 33 The Platonic Trinity 36 German Idealism and the Platonic Tradition 40 Paley, Locke and Socinianism 45 Priestley, Unitarianism and Platonic idealism 49 Identity and difference: henology or ontology? 59 Supreme being and self-consciousness 65 `iamwhoiam'75 2 Inner word: re¯ection as meditation 88 Aphorism 89 Meditation and awakening: spiritual exercises 93 Re¯ection, recollection and restlessness 102 The soul as the mirror of the divine 109 The ascent of the mind and the inner word 116 The communication of truth and biblical symbols 127 The philosophic and the beloved apostle 136 Re¯ection and rational discrimination 145 3 The image of God: re¯ection as imitating the divine spirit 152 Prudence 154 vii © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521770351 - Coleridge, Philosophy and Religion: Aids to Reflection and the Mirror of the Spirit Douglas Hedley Table of Contents More information viii Contents Sensibility 157 The two worlds 161 `Know Thyself !' 168 Spiritual aids 180 Autonomy and the Euthyphro dilemma 188 4 God is truth: the faculty of re¯ection or human Understanding in relation to the
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of Transcendence: the Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism
    On Dubious Conceptions of Transcendence The Politics of Transcendence: The Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism Claes G. Ryn The Catholic University of America Plato and Aristotle are still approached with deference by many political thinkers who have not abandoned the notion of moral universality. Some of them treat Plato as the ultimate philosophi- cal authority and even regard substantial criticisms of him as a sign of not really having understood him. Yet Plato and Aristotle are philosophers with human flaws, and their weaknesses, too, have influenced Western political philosophy and practice. It is possible to argue, specifically, that certain dubious tendencies in Greek philosophy, especially in Plato, have deeply affected the Western way of thinking about political morality, even among philosophers who disagree with them. Those same tendencies may help explain the strong prejudice against the notion of moral universality in modern political thought. One reason for revisit- ing Plato and Aristotle is to separate persuasive from question- able elements in their legacy and to remove obstacles to a recon- sideration of the issue of moral universality. This article and the one that follows challenge widely held assumptions. It may be appropriate to remind readers that HUMANITAS is always open to publishing scholarly responses to articles in its pages. 4 • Volume XII, No. 2, 1999 Claes G. Ryn Present-day admirers of the Greeks typically assume that criti- cisms of Plato and Aristotle must stem from nihilism or relativ- ism. Most of their critics, as well as academia in general, do in- deed reject the idea of a universal good for politics.
    [Show full text]
  • A Case for Monistic Idealism
    A Case for Monistic Idealism: Connecting Idealistic Thoughts from Leibniz to Kant with support in Quantum Physics. Erik Haynes Philosophy 690: Thesis Defense Liberty University Graduate School Friday, May 6, 2016 Contents Abstract ......................................................................................................................................... iii Acknowledgments ........................................................................................................................ iv Introduction ................................................................................................................................... 1 Chapter 1. Support from Leibniz ................................................................................................ 7 Chapter 2. Support from Sense Perception: Berkeley and Kant ........................................... 19 Immanuel Kant ....................................................................................................................... 29 Critique of Kant ...................................................................................................................... 33 Chapter 3. Support from Quantum Physics and Psychology ................................................. 38 The Copenhagen Interpretation ............................................................................................ 42 The Role of the Observer in the Collapse of the Wave Function ....................................... 49 Nonlocality ..............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Provocations in Theater and Philosophy by Martin Puchner (Review)
    The Drama of Ideas: Platonic Provocations in Theater and Philosophy by Martin Puchner (review) Will Daddario TDR: The Drama Review, Volume 57, Number 3, Fall 2013 (T 219), pp. 167-168 (Article) Published by The MIT Press For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/tdr/summary/v057/57.3.daddario.html Access provided by Harvard University (23 Sep 2013 21:16 GMT) The Drama of Ideas: Platonic Provocations in Theater and Philosophy. By Martin Puchner. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010; 272 pp. $29.95 cloth. “It is time to revive Plato — not the discredited Plato of ide- alism, but a different one, the Plato of dramatic Platonism” (198). Motivated by this belief, Martin Puchner presents in The Drama of Ideas a “theatrical history of modern philosophy — a history of philosophy from the point of view of drama and the- ater” (8). The book features an eclectic cast including George Kaiser, Oscar Wilde, George Bernard Shaw, Luigi Pirandello, Bertolt Brecht, Tom Stoppard, Søren Kierkegaard, Friedrich Nietzsche, Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert Camus, Kenneth Burke, Gilles Deleuze, Iris Murdoch, Martha Nussbaum, Alain Badiou, Socrates, and, of course, Plato. Its key term, “dramatic Platonism,” carries the assertion that Platonic idealism (i.e., the theory of the world of forms) loses all potency and legitimacy when not developed in tandem with an analysis of the bodies that express those forms in the material world. According to Puchner, Plato’s philosophy is prac- tical and dramatic, and we find it at work in his dialogues. When approached as dramatic texts, the dialogues reveal Plato as a reformist playwright (chapter 1).
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Among and Against the Post-Modernists
    New Page 1 Page 1 of 7 Plato Among and Against the Post-Modernists Joseph Spencer “One day I heard someone reading, as he said, from a book of Anaxagoras, and saying that it is Mind [1] that directs and is the cause of everything.” With moments to expire before Athens would execute him, Plato’s Socrates was exploring the meaning of a few lines by another philosopher. To the last minute of Socrates’ dramatic life, Plato has him making important criticism on vital literary texts. Textual criticism is found throughout Plato’s works, making it his main philosophical methodology. His literary approach destroys the image of Plato as a logician working systematically from proven axioms or definitions toward a conclusion. In fact, Plato never makes a systematic exposition of just one philosophical issue, nor moves from a stated central topic or thesis to work out the numerous details, as Aristotle would do shortly thereafter. Plato’s selective, spontaneous, and unsystematic approach links him with a much later tradition: post-modernism. The purposes of this paper are two: to establish that Plato’s productive methodology was literary criticism; and to explore the implications of the post- modern revival of Plato’s approach. On the Elenchus: Its Negative Nature In his fundamental work on what is Socrates’ and what is Plato’s thought, Gregory Vlastos put a [2] chronological order to Plato’s writing of the dialogues. According to him, the Theory of Forms, considered the heart of Plato’s metaphysical ideas, appears seventeen dialogues into Plato’s career. But [3] the dialectic, which supposedly finds its logical grounding in the Theory of Forms, surfaces in Plato’s very first dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • On First Understanding Plato's Republic
    The European Journal of International Law Vol. 22 no. 4 © EJIL 2011; all rights reserved .......................................................................................... On First Understanding Plato’s Republic Philip Allott* A book can change a mind, but only if that mind is ready to be changed. The mind of a particular child formed, up to the age of reason, in a time of war, is liable to be ready to ask questions of a particular kind about the human condition – still more so, when, at the age of eight, that child sees, on the front-page of the newspaper, images of Belsen and Hiroshima, images that would never be forgotten. In the 1940s it was still pos- sible to believe in childish innocence. Now even small children know too much about the worst that human beings can do. Beyond the age of reason, social influences interact with the particular character of our own mind and our own personal experience to form an ever-evolving idea, an ever-denser idea, of the human condition, forcing us to live our lives in an uncomfort- able reconciling of our own private worldview and the worldview imposed on us by society. Books intrude into that process of self-evolving in a unique way. The private activity of other minds reaches far into our own mind through the very private activity of reading. Philosophy is an active presence in our minds, even in the minds of those who have never read a single sentence in a single book of philosophy. We enact philosophies in the ideas that form our consciousness, individual and social, even if we know nothing of the origin and history of those ideas.
    [Show full text]