Scheler's Metaphysics Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Scheler's Metaphysics Of Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 79/2017, p. 801-817 SCHELER’S METAPHYSICS OF WAR by Rainer Schäfer (Bonn) 1. Introduction Max Scheler’s The Genius of War and the German War contains four parts and an appendix: a) “The Genius of war”, b) “The German war”, c) “The spiritual unity of Europe and its political demands”, d) “Renun- ciation of Britain”, and the appendix “On the psychology of the British ethos and hypocrisy”. “Genius”, in this context, refers to a paradigm, an original idea, or an essence of war.1 In the first part of the Genius text Scheler develops a concept of ‘just’ war in general, arguing that it must inevitably be rooted in human life, supportive of the meaning of life. Then he tries to show how war is an expression of the worldview (Weltanschauung) of a people, which adds a socio-psychological and ethical dimension to the war phenomenon (cf. 8-115). Thereafter he argues that the just war has a metaphysical Rainer Fritz Schäfer (1971) is professor at the Department of Philosophy, University Bonn (Ger- many). His research areas are epistemology, ontology, theory of subjectivity, and classical German philosophy. Books: Hegel (München: Fink Verlag, 2011); Ich-Welten: Erkenntnis, Urteil und Identität aus der egologischen Differenz von Leibniz bis Davidson (Münster: Mentis Verlag, 2012); Was Freiheit zu Recht macht: Manuale des Politischen (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 2015). 1 Max Scheler, Der Genius des Krieges und der Deutsche Krieg (The Genius of War and the German War) (Leipzig: Verlag der Weissen Bücher, 1915; 2nd ed. 1916; 3rd ed. 1917). I quote according to the third edition. The German title is suggestive, because Scheler capitalizes ‘Deutsch’, which is gram- matically unusual, for it means that World War I is a particularly German matter. That Scheler was not simply grammatically inaccurate is evident by the title of the second part of the Genius: “Der deutsche Krieg”. There exists no translation of this writing. Other writings of Scheler concerning WW I are: Europe and the War (1915), The War as Overall-Experience (1916), and The Causes of the Hatred against Germans (1917). In addition Scheler wrote numerous articles on WW I. Therefore one can say that he really was strongly committed to the subject. doi: 10.2143/TVF.79.4.3284702 © 2017 by Tijdschrift voor Filosofie. All rights reserved. 802 Rainer SCHÄFER fundament (cf. 117-162), forming a particular reality in the moral and historical world, which culminates in the “idea” that a just and meta- physically grounded war is God’s judgment (cf. 91, 127-153). This implies criteria for distinguishing just from unjust wars (cf. 154-162). In the sec- ond part, Scheler applies those general determinations to the case of World War I (cf. 163-248). He argues that WW I is almost alone in world history in being a just war, since if war is an expression of the worldview of a people, expressing the volonté général, it is necessary that the whole nation be involved in the war. It is also necessary to fight with a chival- rous attitude, and it is imperative for the enemies to have people’s armies. Since Scheler wrote and published The Genius of War at the very begin- ning of WW I, it is clear that he could not have known the bestial slaughter, the gas attacks, the attacks on civilian populations, and the industrialized killing that were to come. This certainly does not excuse him, because he makes the fundamental mistake of judging WW I with- out fully understanding what was going on. Obviously, he was very naïve to think that a war in the 20th century could be carried out with the mediaeval and somewhat old-fashioned virtue of chivalry (Scheler also mentions: courage, willingness to take risks and danger, nobleness, hero- ism, loyalty, sacrifice, and fame, cf. 34). The third part of the Genius text (cf. 249-332) predicts what will happen after WW I. Scheler tries to forecast how a spiritual unity will be politically realised in post-war Europe. He argues that only Germany and the allied Austro-Hungarian Empire are cosmopolitan and thereby represent the true idea of Europe. The last part and the appendix of The Genius of War (cf. 333-413) argue that this unity of Europe could only be realised if Europe were completely to renounce modern British values (pragmatism, utilitarianism, capital- ism, biologism, internationalism).2 2 In Scheler research, the Genius writing is mostly ignored, although Scheler claims that it is not only war propaganda, rather a philosophy and metaphysics of war as well as an advancement of his phenomenological material value ethics. For example, Ron Perrin, Max Scheler’s Concept of the Person: An Ethics of Humanism (Basingstoke: MacMillan, 1991) and Eiichi Shimomissé, Die Phänomenologie und das Problem der Grundlegung der Ethik: An Hand des Versuchs von Max Scheler (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1971) completely ignore Scheler’s war writings; likewise Ute Kruse-Ebeling, Liebe und Ethik: Eine Ver- hältnisbestimmung ausgehend von Max Scheler und Robert Spaemann (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 2009). Heinz Leonardy, Liebe und Person: Max Schelers Versuch eines “phänomenologischen” SCHELER’S METAPHYSICS OF WAR 803 2. Forerunners, enemies and political aims of the ‘Genius’ In the Genius text Scheler tries to make German propaganda for World War I using the typical oppositions: culture vs. civilisation, com- munity vs. society, cosmopolitism vs. internationalism, hierarchy-order vs. liberal-egalitarianism, aristocratic vs. republican, morality vs. econ- omy, material values vs. utilitarianism, religious faith vs. capitalism, organic vitalism vs. contractualist mechanism, life vs. biologism. The chief enemies of Germany in Scheler’s view are Britain (cf. 73) and Rus- sia. France, regarded as the main enemy in Thomas Mann’s Reflections of a Nonpolitical Man, is not regarded as such by Scheler, who argues that France was merely seduced by Russia and Britain for their purposes and still wants revenge for the defeat of 1871 in the Franco-Prussian War and the loss of Alsace-Lorraine.3 It is interesting that Scheler and Mann use nearly the same oppositions, but argue against different enemies. Scheler’s interpretation of WW I holds that it is a conflict of different material values, which characterise the different essences of the nations. That different nations adhere to different sets of values makes conflict and war necessary, for each nation tries to promote the values it adheres Personalismus (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1976), 1 simply states that the war writings of Scheler are external to philosophy. In the center of Scheler’s war metaphysics in the Genius stands love as a uniting power between God and a nation. Therefore, it is important to consider the war philosophy if one wants a complete picture of Scheler’s material value ethics, and what it means to apply it to a concrete historical phenomenon. At least this was Scheler’s own claim until the end of WW I. Manfred Frings, Lifetime: Max Scheler’s Philosophy of Time: A First Inquiry and Presentation (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2003), 162 ff. at least mentions briefly a relation between Scheler’s material ethics and his war philosophy. Brilliant articles on the subject are Daniel Weidner, “Das Absolute des Krieges: Max Schelers Kriegsdenken und die Rhetorik des Äußersten,” in Texturen des Krieges: Körper, Schrift und der Erste Weltkrieg, ed. by Galili Shahar (Göttingen: Wallstein Verlag, 2015), 85-114 and Sebastian Luft, “Germany’s Metaphysi- cal War: Reflections on War by Two Representatives of German Philosophy; Max Scheler and Paul Natorp,” Clio: Internet Portal on History, Themenportal Erster Weltkrieg, published in 2007, accessed in 2017, http://www.erster-weltkrieg.clio-online.de. 3 Kurt Flasch, Die geistige Mobilmachung: Die deutschen Intellektuellen und der Erste Weltkrieg; Ein Versuch (Berlin: Fest, 2000), 16 ff. is amazed that most German war philosophers (Max Scheler, Georg Simmel, Paul Natorp, Friedrich Meinecke, Enst Troeltsch, Rudolf Christoph Eucken etc.) repine with the British and not with France, which is usually seen as the German ‘archenemy’. But, after the British declaration of war, after it became known that Britain had secret navy contracts with Russia, and par- ticularly after the sea blockade during the war time (at that time illegal in international law) with many civilian German hunger deaths, it was due to the concrete war situation common among the German intellectuals to direct their hatred and propaganda against Britain (cf. the review on Flasch’s book from Eberhard Demm, “Sinngebung des Sinnlosen,” in Die Welt, April 15, 2000, 27). 804 Rainer SCHÄFER to, and strives for political power in order to realise those values. War is a basic form of political competition, and this is a competition of ideas or ideal values. Scheler agrees with Heinrich von Treitschke’s famous statement that war is history and “politics κατ’ ἐξοχήν” (cf. 16, 41), for in war a state comes to its highest, truest, most basic, creative actuality. In its bellicism, this goes even further than Carl von Clause- witz, to whom war was ‘just’ an instrument of politics; according to Treitschke and Scheler, war is the very essence of politics. Germany holds the moral-religious values of true (Catholic) Christian- ity, a people as unity formed by loyalty, honesty, cosmopolitism and love, not economy. All of these values were already presented as core features of Germanness in Fichte’s Addresses to the German Nation. Cosmopolitism is an especially interesting moral value, for Scheler adopts from Fichte the somewhat contradictory idea that one nation in particular is able to per- form true cosmopolitanism, because only German intellect is able truly to understand foreign cultures. Meanwhile, Russia pursues the ideal of Pan-Slavism and the goal of establishing an empire for the Eastern Ortho- dox Church (with the final goal of reconquering Istanbul/Constantino- ple).
Recommended publications
  • Virtue and Happiness: a Philosophical Inquiry
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Wits Institutional Repository on DSPACE VIRTUE AND HAPPINESS: A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY Muhammad Assadallah Schuitema 320900 A Research Report submitted to the Faculty of Humanities, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, Applied Ethics for Professionals University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, 16th March 2015 1 Abstract The position that holds that virtue, as a good, is sufficient for happiness has had illustrious exponents in the past. We will refer to this position as the sufficiency thesis. In recent times however this position has fallen into disfavour. This is largely due to the strong intuition that certain goods other than virtue are necessary for happiness. We will refer to this as the problem of external goods. The point of this paper is to respond to the problem of external goods by articulating an understanding of virtue as involving the ability to occupy a “distanced perspective” within which the virtuous agent becomes detached from external goods insofar as he comes to view them as indifferent. My articulation of this understanding of virtue will be based upon what I take to be the core of the Stoic description of virtue. 2 Declaration I declare that this research report is my own unaided work. It is submitted for the degree of Master of Arts in the University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg. It has not been submitted before for any other degree or examination in any other university.
    [Show full text]
  • Sexual Orientation and the Law. by Richard D. Mohr. Harry V
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 1991 Book Review: Sexual Orientation and the Law. by Richard D. Mohr. Harry V. Jaffa Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Jaffa, Harry V., "Book Review: Sexual Orientation and the Law. by Richard D. Mohr." (1991). Constitutional Commentary. 395. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm/395 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Constitutional Commentary collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1991] BOOK REVIEW 313 ical context, Karst illuminates their connection to the creation of a system of caste. Having given judges the tools to work with, Karst renews the argument for the centrality of the federal judiciary, and particularly the Supreme Court, in remedying the hurt of exclusion. Judicial enforcement of the equal citizenship principle vindicates the central tenets of the American civic culture, invites outsiders into the na­ tional community, and promotes the national good by assuring that no group is a permanent loser in the political process. As we begin the 1990s, this prescription seems hauntingly sad. A court that could tell Native Americans that their religious prac­ tices (and everyone else's, for that matter) were the proper subject of political brokering7 is an unlikely candidate for spiritual leader in the quest for constitutional equality. But as Karst himself points out, the strength of the judicial commitment to equality has never been the measure of its pull on American consciousness-else how could Brown v.
    [Show full text]
  • Voegelin and Strauss on Thomas Hobbes
    A Comparison and Evaluation of Interpretation: Voegelin and Strauss on Thomas Hobbes Copyright 2002 Jeremy J. Mhire In the beginning of his essay on Thomas Hobbes in What is Political Philosophy, Leo Strauss asks the rather salient question of why we, as students of political philosophy in contemporary times, should read Hobbes?29 [1] The simplicity of this question, to say nothing of its relevance, cannot be overlooked. To study Hobbesian political philosophy is to say that it is relevant to us in some way; it speaks to us precisely because it allows us the ability to understand ourselves more fully. As our self‐ understanding is at least partially informed through the modern perspective, it makes sense to return to the thoughts of one who was influential in creating that perspective. This was certainly the standpoint of both Strauss and Eric Voegelin, two of the most influential political philosophers of the last century. By returning to Hobbes�s thought, both Strauss and Voegelin wished to revive those insights that 29 [1] Leo Strauss, What is Political Philosophy (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1959), p. 170. played a crucial role in defining how we understand ourselves today. This essay, then, is first and foremost a general attempt to understand the ways in which both Eric Voegelin and Leo Strauss used Hobbes�s political philosophy as a means through which the modern project, or modernity more simply, could be better understood. This will involve an examination of the key themes that both Voegelin and Strauss thought important to properly understand Hobbes�s political philosophy in particular, and its relationship to modernity more generally.
    [Show full text]
  • The Uniqueness of Persons in the Life and Thought of Karol Wojtyła/Pope John Paul II, with Emphasis on His Indebtedness to Max Scheler
    Chapter 3 The Uniqueness of Persons in the Life and Thought of Karol Wojtyła/Pope John Paul II, with Emphasis on His Indebtedness to Max Scheler Peter J. Colosi In a way, his [Pope John Paul II’s] undisputed contribution to Christian thought can be understood as a profound meditation on the person. He enriched and expanded the concept in his encyclicals and other writings. These texts represent a patrimony to be received, collected and assimilated with care.1 - Pope Benedict XVI INTRODUCTION Throughout the writings of Karol Wojtyła, both before and after he became Pope John Paul II, one finds expressions of gratitude and indebtedness to the philosopher Max Scheler. It is also well known that in his Habilitationsschrift,2 Wojtyła concluded that Max Scheler’s ethical system cannot cohere with Christian ethics. This state of affairs gives rise to the question: which of the ideas of Scheler did Wojtyła embrace and which did he reject? And also, what was Wojtyła’s overall attitude towards and assessment of Scheler? A look through all the works of Wojtyła reveals numerous expressions of gratitude to Scheler for philosophical insights which Wojtyła embraced and built upon, among them this explanation of his sources for The Acting Person, Granted the author’s acquaintance with traditional Aristotelian thought, it is however the work of Max Scheler that has been a major influence upon his reflection. In my overall conception of the person envisaged through the mechanisms of his operative systems and their variations, as presented here, may indeed be seen the Schelerian foundation studied in my previous work.3 I have listed many further examples in the appendix to this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Ethics
    15 BONNIE KENT Augustine’s ethics Augustine regards ethics as an enquiry into the Summum Bonum: the supreme good, which provides the happiness all human beings seek. In this respect his moral thought comes closer to the eudaimonistic virtue ethics of the classical Western tradition than to the ethics of duty and law associated with Christianity in the modern period. But even though Augustine addresses many of the same problems that pagan philosophers do, he often defends very different answers. For him, happiness consists in the enjoyment of God, a reward granted in the afterlife for virtue in this life. Virtue itself is a gift of God, and founded on love, not on the wisdom prized by philosophers. The art of living In Book 8 of De civitate Dei Augustine describes “moral philosophy” (a Latin expression), or “ethics” (the Greek equivalent), as an enquiry into the supreme good and how we can attain it. The supreme good is that which we seek for its own sake, not as a means to some other end, and which makes us happy. Augustine adds, as if this were an uncontroversial point, that happiness is the aim of philosophy in general.1 Book 19 opens with a similar discussion. In his summary of Varro’s treatise De philosophia, Augustine reports that no school of philosophy deserves to be considered a distinct school unless it differs from others on the supreme good. For the supreme good is that which makes us happy, and the only purpose of philosophizing is the attainment of happiness.2 Both of these discussions cast philosophy as a fundamentally practical discipline, so that ethics appears to overshadow logic, metaphysics, and other comparatively abstract areas as a philosopher’s chief concern.
    [Show full text]
  • Person and Man in the Philosophical Anthropology of Max Scheler
    Person and Man in the Philosophical Anthropology of Max Scheler CHEUNG Ching-yuen A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master in Philosophy in Philosophy © Chinese University of Hong Kong 23rd August 2000 The Chinese University of Hong Kong holds the copyright of this thesis. Any person(s) intending to use a part or whole of the materials in the thesis in a proposed publication must seek copyright release from the Dean of the Graduate School. /y统系馆書 yK~隨隨丫/S/ \a^LIBRARY SYSTEM乂麥// Abstract Abstract of thesis entitled: Person and Man in the Philosophical Anthropology of Max Scheler Submitted by CHEUNG Ching-yuen for the degree of Master in Philosophy in Philosophy at the Chinese University of Hong Kong in August 23'^ 2000. Max Scheler (1874-1928) is one of the most original and influential figures in modem German philosophy. He is an important figure in the phenomenological movement on one side, and he is one of the founders of philosophical anthropology on the other. Although his writing project on Philosophische Anthropologie could not be completed by the end of his life, many insights on the problem of man can be found in the other works of Scheler. The aim of this thesis is to re-construct Scheler丨s philosophical anthropology by analysing the concepts of person and man. "What is man's place in nature?" This is the main question of Scheler's philosophical anthropology. It leads us to ask another basic question, "What is man? Who is man?" This thesis is divided into four chapters.
    [Show full text]
  • Confessions, by Augustine
    1 AUGUSTINE: CONFESSIONS Newly translated and edited by ALBERT C. OUTLER, Ph.D., D.D. Updated by Ted Hildebrandt, 2010 Gordon College, Wenham, MA Professor of Theology Perkins School of Theology Southern Methodist University, Dallas, Texas First published MCMLV; Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 55-5021 Printed in the United States of America Creator(s): Augustine, Saint, Bishop of Hippo (345-430) Outler, Albert C. (Translator and Editor) Print Basis: Philadelphia: Westminster Press [1955] (Library of Christian Classics, v. 7) Rights: Public Domain vid. www.ccel.org 2 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction . 11 I. The Retractations, II, 6 (A.D. 427) . 22 Book One . 24 Chapter 1: . 24 Chapter II: . 25 Chapter III: . 25 Chapter IV: . 26 Chapter V: . 27 Chapter VI: . 28 Chapter VII: . 31 Chapter VIII: . 33 Chapter IX: . 34 Chapter X: . 36 Chapter XI: . 37 Chapter XII: . 39 Chapter XIII: . 39 Chapter XIV: . 41 Chapter XV: . 42 Chapter XVI: . 42 Chapter XVII: . 44 Chapter XVIII: . 45 Chapter XIX: . 47 Notes for Book I: . 48 Book Two . .. 50 Chapter 1: . 50 Chapter II: . 50 Chapter III: . 52 Chapter IV: . 55 Chapter V: . 56 Chapter VI: . 57 Chapter VII: . 59 Chapter VIII: . 60 Chapter IX: . .. 61 3 Chapter X: . 62 Notes for Book II: . 63 Book Three . .. 64 Chapter 1: . 64 Chapter II: . 65 Chapter III: . 67 Chapter IV: . 68 Chapter V: . 69 Chapter VI: . 70 Chapter VII: . 72 Chapter VIII: . 74 Chapter IX: . .. 76 Chapter X: . 77 Chapter XI: . 78 Chapter XII: . 80 Notes for Book III: . 81 Book Four . 83 Chapter 1: . 83 Chapter II: . 84 Chapter III: .
    [Show full text]
  • A Nietzschean Critique of Kant's Highest Good
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1988 A Nietzschean critique of Kant's highest good. Donald M. Schneier University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Schneier, Donald M., "A Nietzschean critique of Kant's highest good." (1988). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2029. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2029 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A NIETZSCHEAN CRITIQUE OF KANT’S HIGHEST GOOD A Dissertation Presented by DONALD M. SCHNEIER Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September I988 Philosophy Copywright by Donald M. Schneier I988 All Rights Reserved A NIETZSCHEAN CRITIQUE OF KANT’S HIGHEST GOOD A Disser'ta'fcion Presented by DONALD M. SCHNEIER Approved as to style and content by: Sara Lennox, Member Michael Jubien, Department Head Philosophy ACKNOV/LEDGEMENTS I would like to thank the members of my committee, es- pecially Bob Wolff, for their guidance, the AT for offering a constructive environment, my other friends for their change of pace, and Karen and my father for their steady support over this long haul. IV ABSTRACT A NIETZSCHEAN CRITIQUE OF KANT'S HIGHEST GOOD SEPTEMBER I988 DONALD M. SCHNEIER, B.A. , UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS M.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Aryeh Kosman, the Divine in Aristotle's Ethics
    THE DIVINE IN ARISTOTLE’S ETHICS Aryeh Kosman Haverford College [email protected] What role does the notion of the divine play in Aristotle’s account of a good life? This is not an obvious question; god appears relatively infrequently, for example, in the Nicomachean Ethics. But it might interest us, if only because of the perplexing appearance of the divine in Book 10 of that treatise, as that which appears to underwrite the choice of a contemplative life. The cognate question, what role does god play in Aristotle’s understanding of being, is obvious and is more understandable, given Metaphysics Lambda. That question yields a variety of answers. Some interpreters see the entire Metaphysics as directed toward the discussion of divine being in Lambda. Others see Lambda as an addendum to the central books of the Metaphysics, perhaps the residuum of a youthful view outgrown in the course of Aristotle’s maturation. In fact, Lambda’s discussion of god perfects the analysis of substance. It does so, however, not by revealing something about substance and being that the central books do not see, but by making clear that the principle articulated in those books is divine. I think that the same is true with Aristotle’s ethics: the divine is a principle that governs the discourse of the ethical treatises. Stewart put it nicely when he proposed to translate Aristotle’s doctrine “into the language of modern philosophy, and say that Aristotle makes ‘the Idea of God’ the ‘regulative principle’ in man’s life.”1 That neo-Kantian description (“the language of modern philosophy”) may now seem quaint, but it captures Aristotle’s view of god as a formal principle of our normative lives, and it does so without abandoning our commitment to read his ethics as naturalistic and human- centered.
    [Show full text]
  • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Gabriel Richardson Lear
    Happy Lives and the Highest Good This page intentionally left blank Happy Lives and the Highest Good AN ESSAY ON ARISTOTLE'S NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Gabriel Richardson Lear PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRINCETON AND OXFORD Copyright © 2004 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 3 Market Place, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1SY All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Richardson Lear, Gabriel, 1971– Happy lives and the highest good : an essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics / Gabriel Richardson Lear. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-691-11466-8 (alk. paper) 1. Aristole, Nicomachean ethics. 2. Ethics, Ancient. I. Title. B430.L43 2004 171′.3—dc21 2003042899 British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available This book has been composed in Sabon and American Gothic Printed on acid-free paper. ∞ www.pupress.princeton.edu Printed in the United States of America 10987654321 FOR MY PARENTS Dale and Leslie Richardson This page intentionally left blank Contents ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ix CHAPTER ONE Introduction 1 CHAPTER TWO The Finality Criterion 8 1. Introduction 8 2. What It Is to Be an Aristotelian Telos 11 3. Teleology in the Nicomachean Ethics 15 4. Teleology, Desire, and Middle-Level Ends 31 5. The Puzzle in NE I.7 and Two Possible Solutions 37 6. Ackrill’s Inclusivist Solution 40 CHAPTER THREE The Self-Sufficiency of Happiness 47 1. Self-Sufficiency: Three Problems for a Monistic Reading of Eudaimonia 48 2. Self-Sufficiency as a Mark of Finality 51 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant's Groundwork As Intellectual Paideia
    The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant’s Groundwork as Intellectual Paideia Author(s): Ian Hunter Source: Critical Inquiry, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Summer 2002), pp. 908-929 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/341237 . Accessed: 07/10/2015 20:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Critical Inquiry. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 23.235.32.0 on Wed, 7 Oct 2015 20:38:26 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant’s Groundwork as Intellectual Paideia Ian Hunter In fact this satisfies a longing for the transcendent, because in so far as people believe they can see the ‘limits of human understanding’, they believe of course that they can see beyond these. Work in philosophy ...isreally more work on oneself. —Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture andValue To approach philosophy as a way of working on the self means to begin not with the experience it clarifies and the subject it discovers, but with the acts of self-transformation it requires and the subjectivity it seeks tofashion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of Transcendence: the Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism
    On Dubious Conceptions of Transcendence The Politics of Transcendence: The Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism Claes G. Ryn The Catholic University of America Plato and Aristotle are still approached with deference by many political thinkers who have not abandoned the notion of moral universality. Some of them treat Plato as the ultimate philosophi- cal authority and even regard substantial criticisms of him as a sign of not really having understood him. Yet Plato and Aristotle are philosophers with human flaws, and their weaknesses, too, have influenced Western political philosophy and practice. It is possible to argue, specifically, that certain dubious tendencies in Greek philosophy, especially in Plato, have deeply affected the Western way of thinking about political morality, even among philosophers who disagree with them. Those same tendencies may help explain the strong prejudice against the notion of moral universality in modern political thought. One reason for revisit- ing Plato and Aristotle is to separate persuasive from question- able elements in their legacy and to remove obstacles to a recon- sideration of the issue of moral universality. This article and the one that follows challenge widely held assumptions. It may be appropriate to remind readers that HUMANITAS is always open to publishing scholarly responses to articles in its pages. 4 • Volume XII, No. 2, 1999 Claes G. Ryn Present-day admirers of the Greeks typically assume that criti- cisms of Plato and Aristotle must stem from nihilism or relativ- ism. Most of their critics, as well as academia in general, do in- deed reject the idea of a universal good for politics.
    [Show full text]