The English Noun Phrase

in its Sentential Asp ect

by

Steven Paul Abney

BA Indiana University

SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE

REQUIREMENTS OF THE DEGREE OF

DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN LINGUISTICS

at the

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

June

c

Steven Paul Abney

The author herebygrants to MIT p ermission to repro duce and to

distribute copies of this thesis do cument in whole or in part

Signature of Author

Department of Linguistics and Philosophy

May

Certied by

Richard Larson

Thesis Sup ervisor

Accepted by

Wayne ONeil

Chairman Departmental Committee

The English Noun Phrase

In Its Sentential Asp ect

by

Steven Paul Abney

Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and PhilosophyonMay

in partial fulllment of the requirements for the Degree of Do ctor of

Philosophy in Linguistics

ABSTRACT

This dissertation is a defense of the hyp othesis that the noun phrase is

headed byafunctional element ie nonlexical category D identied

with the determiner In this way the structure of the noun phrase parallels

that of the sentence which is headed by Inection under assumptions

now standard within the GovernmentBinding GB framework

The central empirical problem addressed is the question of the prop er

analysis of the socalled Possing gerund in English This construction

p ossesses simultaneously many prop erties of sentences and many prop erties

of noun phrases The problem of capturing this dual asp ect of the Poss

ing construction is heightened by current restrictive views of Xbar theory

which in particular rule out the obvious structure for Possing NP

NP

VP by virtue of its exo centricity

ing

Consideration of languages in which nouns even the most basic concrete

nouns show agreementAGR with their p ossessors p oints to an analysis

of the noun phrase as headed by an element similar to In which provides a

p osition for AGR I call this Inlike element D D and In b elong to the

class of nonlexical categories which I prefer to call functional categories

The analysis in which D heads the noun phrase I call the DPanalysis

Imp orting the DPanalysis into English yields an immediate solution for

the problem of the Possing gerund Possing gerunds and by extension

noun phrases generally have a more sentencelike structure than hitherto

thought namely DPs D VP In nongerundive noun phrases

DP ing

VP is replaced by a pro jection of N This pro jection of N despite b eing

a maximal Xbar pro jection corresp onds to Nbar in the standard analysis

Current trends in the treatment of minor categoriessocalled non

lexical categorieslead us to a similar conclusion Until recently minor

categories like complementizers and mo dals had b een treated as syncate

gorematic Under current assumptions however they participate fully in

the Xbar schemaInthiswaytwo simplications are achieved simulta

neously we eliminate syncategorematic elements and we acquire an endo

centric analysis of the sentence which had b een exceptional in b eing the

only exo centric ma jor categoryTo make these results fully general we are

led to treat the remaining syncategorematic elementsin particular deter

miners in noun phrases and degree words in adjective phrasesas heads

of full phrases The analogy with complementizers and mo dals indicates

that determiners and degree words should head noun phrases and adjective

phrases resp ectively In other words determiners are lexical instantiations

of D in the same way that mo dals are lexical instantiations of In

However despite the conceptual links the question of the existence of

a functional head of the noun phrase the DPanalysis and the question

of the place of the determiner are indep endent questions and I treat them

separately Chapters One through Three are concerned predominately with

the former question Chapter Four with the latter

Chapter One provides a brief intro duction In Chapter Two I present

the DPanalysis motivating it by examining languages with agreementbe

tween noun and p ossessor I also discuss issues raised by the DPanalysis

with emphasis on the parallelism b etween noun phrase and sentence hyp oth

esized under the DPanalysis In particular I treat the question of PRO

in the noun phrase and I show that the numerous dierences b etween

sentence and noun phrase do not invalidate the parallelism of structure

prop osed under the DPanalysis In Chapter Three I apply the analysis to

the three gerundive constructions Accing Possing and Ingof Finally

in Chapter Four I turn to the question of whether the determiner is the

lexical instantiation of D the functional head of the noun phrase

Thesis Sup ervisor Dr Richard K Larson Title Assistant Professor of Linguistics

Acknowledgements

Iwould liketoacknowledge rst of all mydebttomymany teachers and

mentors these last four years to my thesis advisor Rich Larson for his

guidance in matters syntactic and semantic as well as for sound advice in

the mechanics of thesiswriting To the other members of my committee

Noam Chomsky Ken Hale and Richie Kayne To Jim Higginb otham with

whom I haveworked closely since coming to MIT unfortunately for me he

is in Pisa this semester Thanks also to Jay Keyser b oth for guidance in

linguistics and encouragementinmy computational interests and to Morris

Halle for encouragement and direction and for keeping me aware of the

b eauties of phonology

Though none of mywork in parsing has found its wayinto this the

sis nonetheless a very imp ortantpartofmyintellectual developmentas

a graduate student has b een in the area of computation I am esp ecially

indebted to Sam Epstein mymentor at Bell Communications Research

for providing me with a golden opp ortunitytodevelop my ideas in parsing

and for his indisp ensable guidance and encouragement At MIT thanks to

Bob Berwick for much help and direction to Carl Hewitt for the opp or

tunitytowork with the Apiary Pro ject to Gul Agha for endless supp ort

and advice to Jennifer Cole who I had the go o d fortune to collab orate

with in the summer and fall of in work on parsing to Tom Reinhart

my Lispm guru and to Beth Levin for her guidance during the summer I

worked for the Lexicon Pro ject

Iwould like to thank the others with whom I worked at Bellcore alpha

b etically George Collier Stu Feldman Mike Lesk Maria Slowiaczek Don

Walker I would also like to thank Don Hindle Mitch Marcus and Richard

Sproat of ATT Bell Lab oratories and Bob Ingria of Bolt Beranek

Newman

In psycholinguistics sp ecial thanks to Merrill Garrett and Janet Fo dor

My studies at MIT were partially funded by a Mellon Graduate Fellow

ship in the Humanities I gratefully acknowledge their supp ort

Among fellow students present and past the eightwithwhomIhave

b een together since will always b e very sp ecial to me I consider myself

very lucky to haveworked together with these p eople I only wish it werent

over so so on They are HyonSo ok Cho e Jennifer Cole John Lumsden

Doug Saddy Ur Shlonsky Michele Sigler Carol Tenny Loren Trigo Still

amemb er of the group in spiritthough he left us for warm and sunny

Palo Alto is Steve Neale There are also two unocial memb ers of our

class who havebeenvery imp ortant to me Betsy Ritter and Kyoko Ma

sunaga Among my other colleagues I would esp ecially liketomention Di

ana Archangeli and husband Dante Mark Baker Andy Barss Ed Barton

Maggie Browning Viviane Deprez Naoki Fukui Alicja Gorecka Mohamed

Guerssel Ewa Higgins Kyle Johnson Mike Kashket Mary Laughren Juli

ette Levin Anne Lob eck Dinette Massam Katie McCreight Janis Melvold

Janet Nicol Tova Rap op ort Malka Rappap ort Marc Ryser Gab e Segal

Kelly Sloan Peggy Sp eas Tim Stowell Catherine Womack

Thanks to the sta in the Linguistics department esp ecially Maggie

Caracino and Nancy Peters

For my sanity and emotional wellb eing I owe a great debt to Carol

Tenny and her parentsas well as to Mushka and Freddy the Weasel to

Marc and Ilana AmraniCohen and b ossman Edan to my family to Betsy

Ritter and to the incomparable Capitol Theatre in Arlington My deep est

debt however is to my wife Nina for encouraging ca joling for love It is

to her that this work is dedicated

To Nina

Contents in Brief

I Intro duction

A Puzzle and Its Solution

Overview

II Noun Phrase and Sentence

General Similarities

In in the Noun Phrase

The DPAnalysis

PRO in the Noun Phrase

Dierences Between Noun Phrase and Sentence

III Gerunds

Intro duction

Noun Phrase Asp ects of Possing

Sentential Asp ects of Possing

Analyses I Finding the Seams

Analyses I I The Morphological Angle

Conclusion Syntactic Axation

IV Lexical determiners

Determiner As Head

The Adjective Phrase

The Position of Prenominal Adjectives Conclusion

Contents

Intro duction

A Puzzle and Its Solution

The Puzzle

An Apparently Unrelated Fact

The Solution

The IdentityofX

Sentence and Noun Phrase

Overview

Noun Phrase and Sentence

General Similarities

In in the Noun Phrase

Yupik

Mayan

Hungarian

Digression Comp in the Noun Phrase

Turkish

The DPAnalysis

Concepts and Terminology

Functional Selection

Two Notions of Command

Det as Head

The Position of s

App endix Selection of DP

PRO in the Noun Phrase

PRObook

theory

Control Theory

Binding theory

Arguments Against PRO in the Noun Phrase

CONTENTS

Dierences Between Noun Phrase and Sentence

Predication in the Noun Phrase

Catalog of Dierences

App endix Reducing the Dierences

The Gerund

Intro duction

The Range of Gerund Constructions

Reulands Analysis of Accing

Noun Phrase Asp ects of Possing

External evidence

Internal evidence

Sentential Asp ects of Possing

VP in Possing

PRO in the Gerund

Nbar Deletion

Analyses I Finding the Seams

Schachter

Horn

The DVP Analysis

The DIP Analysis

Analyses I I The Morphological Angle

Jackendo

PesetskyLeb eaux

Baker

Conclusion Syntactic Axation

A Final Analysis

Axes in the Syntax

Verbal and Adjectival Passive

Lexical Determiners

Determiner As Head

Arguments for the Standard Analysis

Sundry Evidence For Det As Head

The Range of Sp eciers

The Adjective Phrase

Deg as Head

Adjective Adverb and Quantier

The Sub ject of Deg

Extent Clauses

Two Sp eciers in the Adjective Phrase

Overview of Structures

CONTENTS

The Position of Prenominal Adjectives

Two Hyp otheses

Adjective as Head of NP

Two More Hyp otheses

Conclusion

CONTENTS

Chapter

Intro duction

A Puzzle and Its Solution

The Puzzle

One of the most p erplexing structures in English is the socalled Possing

gerundive construction An example is

Johns building a spaceship

What makes this construction so p erplexing is that it seems to b e neither

sh nor fowl so to sp eak On the one hand it is obviously a sentence but

on the other hand it is obviously a noun phrase

Considered with regard to its external distribution the Possing gerun

dive b ehaves exactly like a noun phrase It app ears in nounphrase p ositions

and particularly in nounphrase p ositions from which sentences are ex

cluded such as sub ject p osition under Sub jectAux Inversion emb edded

sub ject p osition or ob ject of prep osition

a did that John built a spaceship upset you

did John upset you

did Johns building a spaceship upset you

b I wondered if that John built a spaceship had upset you

Iwondered if John had upset you

Iwondered if Johns building a spaceship had upset you

c I told you ab out that John built a spaceship

I told you ab out John

I told you ab out Johns building a spaceship

CHAPTER INTRODUCTION

Likewise the sub ject of the gerundiveie Johns b ehaves like the

sub ject of a noun phrase the p ossessor not the sub ject of a sentence

This is most evident in the fact that it receives not nominative

case

John destroyed the spaceship

Johns destruction of the spaceship

Johns destroying the spaceship

It is clear that externally and with resp ect to the sub ject the gerundive

is a noun phrase Wehave this piece of structure then

NP

NP

Johns

On the other hand it is equally clear that the remainder of the gerun

dive ie building a spaceship constitutes a VP ing is a fully pro ductive

verbal ax anyverb can app ear in the gerundive construction In this

way it diers from clear cases of derived nouns which are quite sp oradic in

their pro ductivity in Englishwehave destruction for example but not

debunktion referral but not interral More imp ortantly there is quite a

long list of pro cesses and constructions which app ear in the verb phrase but

not in the noun phrase including case assignment to the ob ject raising

Exceptional Case Marking Raising to Ob ject double ob jects particles

and particle movement and numerous others All of these constructions

are to b e found in the gerundive

A PUZZLE AND ITS SOLUTION

a Johns destruction the spaceship

John destroyed the spaceship

Johns destroying the spaceship

b Johns app earance to b e dead

John app eared to b e dead

Johns app earing to b e dead

c Johns b elief Bill to b e Caesar Augustus

John b elieved Bill to b e Caesar Augustus

Johns b elieving Bill to b e Caesar Augustus

d Johns giftrental of Mary of a Fiat

John gaverented Mary a Fiat

Johns givingrenting Mary a Fiat

e Johns explanation away of the problem away

John explained away the problem away

Johns explaining away the problem away

This gives us another piece of the structure

VP

V NP

building a spaceship

The puzzle is how to t these two pieces together and without

doing violence to the principles which constrain phrase structure The ob

vious way of putting them together as in do es not satisfy this criterion

NP

NP VP

Johns V NP

building a spaceship

The structure violates widelyassumed conditions on phrase structure

in that the highest NP lacks a head VP cannot b e the missing head

CHAPTER INTRODUCTION

b ecause it do es not have the same syntactic category as NP If is not

the correct structure what is To date no fully satisfactory solution has

b een given

It is my goal in the presentwork to solve the puzzle of the Possing

gerundive construction and more generally to defend the novel analysis

of noun phrase structure up on whichmy solution dep ends the socalled

DPanalysis With agrant disregard for the principles of go o d mystery

writing then I sketch out my solution here in the intro duction The rest

of the thesis is a denouement in whichIwork out the details

An Apparently Unrelated Fact

There are a large numb er of languages in whichanovert agreement element

app ears in the noun phrase Consider for example this paradigm from

Hungarian from Szab olcsi

az en kalapom

the INOM hatsg

my hat

a te kalapo d

the youNOM hatsg

your hat

a Peter kalapja

the PeterNOM hatsg

Peters hat

Kalap is a simple noun not a verbal formit could b e replaced in this

paradigm byany noun at all Yet kalap agrees with its p ossessor marking

its p erson and numb er with an agreement marker AGR The p ossessor in

turn b ears as do es the sub ject of the sentence It is gen

erally assumed in the GovernmentBinding paradigm which I implicitly

adopt throughout that nominative case in the sentence is assigned under

governmentbyAGR hence the coo ccurence of agreement and nominative

case The minimal assumption is that nominative case in the noun phrase

in Hungarian is also assigned under governmentbyAGR As in the sen

tence the sub ject of the noun phrase ie the p ossessor and AGR are

mutually dep endent A nominative p ossessor can only app ear when AGR

is present and AGR only app ears when there is a p ossessor though that

p ossessor may at times b e nonovert

In the sentence AGR is assumed to o ccupy an Inectional p osition out

side the maximal syntactic pro jection of V The obvious hyp othesis con

cerning AGR in the noun phrase is that it o ccupies a similar Inectional

A PUZZLE AND ITS SOLUTION

p osition ie that the structure of noun phrase and sentence are parallel in

Hungarian

Sentence I Noun Phrase X

SUBJ I POSSR X

I V X N

I AGR X AGR

It is not clear what the category X is b eyond saying it is a nominal In

ectional categoryWe cannot say it is In as wewould then b e unable

to distinguish Sentence and Noun Phrase as syntactic categories but it is

more like In than anything else

A batch of questions arise immediately What is the category X Is the

pro jection of N which is sister to X maximal If so what consequences do es

that have for the relation b etween noun and p ossessor What consequences

do es the contemplated structure have for binding theory predication and

theory with resp ect to the p ossessor What consequences do es it have

for extraction from the noun phrase

Instead of facing this phalanx of questions it may seem preferable to

supp ose that AGR in the noun phrase do es not app ear in the same sort of

p osition structurallyasAGR in the sentence An alternative is that AGR

is simply adjoined to N

NP

POSSR N

N

N AGR

But there are questions that this hyp othesis raises as well Whydoes

AGR coindex only with the p ossessor and never with eg an ob ject noun

phrase WhydoAGR in the noun phrase and in the sentence o ccupy

dierent p ositions This latter question is made esp ecially p ointed by the

fact that the form of sentential AGR and nominal AGR are frequently very

similar In Central Alaskan Yupik for example they are identical

Yupik data drawn from Reed et al

CHAPTER INTRODUCTION

kiputaa he b oughtit

kiputaat they dual b oughtit

kiputaak they plural b ought it

kuiga his river

kuigat their dual river

kuigak their plural river

Also AGR in the sentence and AGR in the noun phrase frequently assign

the same case Nominative in Hungarian ergative in Yupik or Mayan

Clearly the structure given in for the noun phrase in Hungarian

and similar languages is the minimalhyp othesis and if the questions it

raises can b e satisfactorily answeredas I b elieve they canit is eminently

preferable to the alternatives

The Solution

The relevance of the structure of the Hungarian noun phrase to the puzzle

of the English gerund b ecomes clear if it is not clear already when we

examine the Turkish gerund Languages which p ossess a gerundive con

struction of the Possing typ e are very rare in fact English and Turkish

are the only twoIhave found Turkish diers from English in that it also

happ ens to b e a language with overt AGR in the noun phrase

el

thea hand

senin elin

youGEN handsg

your hand

onun eli

heGEN handsg

his hand

Similar arguments as were forwarded concerning Hungarian lead us to the

conclusion that the noun phrase in Turkish is headed by an Inectional

element which hosts AGR as in The only dierence b etween Turkish

and Hungarian is that the nominal AGR in Turkish assigns genitive case

not nominative case

The Turkish gerund is constructed by adding dIg to a verb stem



Turkish data drawn from Underhill

A PUZZLE AND ITS SOLUTION

Halilin kediye yemek vermedigi

HalilGEN catDAT fo o dACC giveNEGINGsg

Halils not giving fo o d to the cat

As in English the Turkish gerund b ehaves like a noun phrase in its distribu

tion and in showing genitive case on the sub ject On the other handagain

as in Englishkediye yemek vermedigi clearly constitutes a verb phrase

Nouns do not take accusative complements in Turkish for example any

more than in English

But if we analyze the noun phrase in Turkish as in an extraordinarily

simple account for the gerund falls into our lap under analysis the noun

phrase and sentence involve Inectional elements taking pro jections of N

and V resp ectively The exceptionality of the gerund consists therein that

the nominal Inectional element exceptionally takes VP as a complement

instead of a pro jection of N a gives the structure of a nongerundive

noun phrase in Turkish b that of a gerund

a XP b XP

GEN X GEN X

X N X VP

The source of the gerund construction under this analysis is a selectional

quirk of Xin the gerundive X exceptionally takes a verbal rather than

nominal complement

In English we need only supp ose that there is an empty nominal AGR

assigning Genitive case exactly corresp onding to the nominal AGR we see

overtly in Turkish With that we can imp ort into English the analysis we

just sketched for gerunds in Turkish giving us a remarkably simple and

principled solution for the puzzle of the gerund The pieces t together this

way

XP Noun Phrase

XP X

Johns X VP

AGR V XP

building a spaceship

CHAPTER INTRODUCTION

The IdentityofX

The most imp ortant lo ose end in my solution is the identity of the category

X One answer would b e that it is a new previously unrecognized category

it is simply the nounphrase correlate of In and the only memb er of cate

gory X is the invisible AGR which assigns genitive case One might ob ject

that it would b e imp ossible for a language learner to learn of the existence

of X if there is never anyovert word of that categoryFor this reason we

would have to assume that X as the category of the noun phrase is supplied

by Universal Grammar and not learned

If the absence of overt memb ers of category X do es not necessarily

render the hyp othesis of the existence of X untenable it would nonetheless

be much preferable if we could identify a class of lexical elements of category

X The lexical class of category In is the class of mo dals The question

is then What is the nounphrase equivalent of the mo dal And the only

real candidate as far as I can see is the determiner There is some a

priori plausibility to taking Determiner to b e our mystery categoryItis

generally assumed that every word pro jects a phrasal no de If there is a

DetP though under standard assumptions ab out the structure of the noun

phrase it never contains any material except the determiner Where are

the complements and sp eciers of the determiner If weassumethatX

Determiner we kill two birds with one stone weprovide category X

with lexical instantiations and we provide determiners with sp eciers the

p ossessor and complements a pro jection of N

DP DP DP

DP D DP D D

Johns D NP Johns D NP D NP

every N AGR N the N

moment book book

On the basis of this sp eculation I will use D to denote the mystery

category X throughout and I will call the hyp othesis that there is an In

ectional head of the noun phrase the DPanalysis

It is imp ortant to note though that there are really two questions here

that turn out to b e partially indep endent Is there an Inectional head



Ihave b een somewhat misleading in in that every is the sole determiner which

coo ccurs with a p ossessor All other determiners are illformed in this context eg

Johns the book I discuss this in some detail in Chapter Four

A PUZZLE AND ITS SOLUTION

of the noun phrase and If there is an inectional head of the noun

phrase is the determiner its lexical instantiation In the rst part of the

thesis though I use the symb ol D to denote the mystery category X I

am for the most part only concerned with the rst question In Chapter

Four I turn to the second question whether in fact Determiner D

Sentence and Noun Phrase

The solution I have prop osed is in eect to assign a more sentencelike

structure to the English noun phrase than is commonly assumed This is

attractive for conceptual reasons in addition to the empirical advantages it

provides Verb versus noun is the most fundamental opp osition in grammar

and it is app ealing to b e able to assign the phrases built on them sentence

and noun phrase resp ectivelyparallel structure

Similarities b etween noun phrase and sentence are a recurrent theme in

grammatical studySentence and noun phrase play a distinguished role in

many asp ects of grammar they were the two cyclic no des for instance in

earlier versions of transformational grammar they are also the two cate

gories whichfreelycontain sub jects

On the other hand there are very substantial dierences in nounphrase

and sentence structure which cannot b e ignored A recurring theme of the

thesis is nounphrasesentence similarities and dierences I compare noun

phrasesentence structure in a general way briey for completeness sake

Iamchiey concerned however with a single sentential asp ect of the noun

phrase the existence of an Inectional head of the noun phrase

Finally while we are on the topic of nounphrasesentence parallels it

is p erhaps relevant to note that the puzzle of howtoputthetwo pieces of

the Possing gerund together is actually the same problem as led to the IP

analysis of the sentence In earlier generative grammar the no de S sto o d

out as an exception to a restrictiveversion of Xbar theory that requires

all phrases to b e headed The solution prop osed for tting the pieces of

the sentence together was to raise the status of a minor category mo dal to

head of the sentence and to p ostulate an entirely abstract head in sentences

which lacked mo dals I have simply imp orted this solution into the noun

phrase to solve the puzzle of the gerund

CHAPTER INTRODUCTION

Overview

The organization of the thesis is as follows Chapter Two is titled Noun

Phrase and Sentence I b egin with a general discussion of parallels that

have b een seen b etween sentence and noun phrase historically and parallels

in their structure within current theory In section I fo cus on the question

of In and AGR in the noun phrase presenting a survey of languages in

which nouns show agreement with their p ossessors After considering the

evidence for an Inectional head of the noun phrase I consider how this

prop osal should b e sp elled out in section In section I discuss an

issue raised in a new form by the IninNP analysis which is of particular

relevance to nounphrasesentence parallelism the question of PRO in the

noun phrase Finally in section I treat some of the dierences b etween

noun phrase and sentence

Chapter Three is devoted to the English gerund I present in detail the

evidence whichshows that it is accurate to characterize the gerund as a

creature which is half noun phrase half verb phrase I discuss previous

attempts to solve this riddle and incorp orate asp ects of several of these

analyses esp ecially that of Jackendo into myown solution An

idea that plays a central role in my solution is that phonologically dep en

dent axes can b ehave as indep endentwords syntactically Here I rely

esp ecially on Baker b

In Chapter Four I turn to the question whether determiners are the

lexical elements that o ccupy the D p osition I argue that a ma jor motivation

for assuming so is that it provides us with enough p ositions in a TwoBar

Xbar theory to account for the quite complex range of distinctions to b e

found in the structure of the noun phrase sp ecier Again I rely heavily

on Jackendo I also discuss the adjective phrase at some length

arguing for parallel analyses of adjective phrase and noun phrase

Chapter

Noun Phrase and

Sentence

General Similarities

The similarities b etween noun phrase and sentence have received much

attention in Generative Grammar In this section I will consider a few of

those similarities in a general way

Lees the rst do ctoral dissertation to come from MIT in linguis

tics considered the similarities b etween sentences and noun phrases He

noted rst that sentences and noun phrases are similar in their external

distribution Both sentence and noun phrase o ccur as sub ject or direct

ob ject b oth sentence and noun phrase undergo Passive

a John surprised me

That John came surprised me

b Iknow John

Iknow that John came

c John was known t bymany linguists

That John came was known t by many linguists

For this reason Lees assumed that emb edded sentences were dominated

by an NP no de For him nominalization included not only derived nom

inal and gerund but all categories with sentencelikeinternal semantics

which app ear in an argument p osition This was a common view in early

generative grammar At least in some contexts emb edded sentences were

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

dominated by noun phrases sometimes including noun heads whichwere

deleted b efore surface structure

Of course b ecause two phrases share the same distribution and are

sub ject to the same transformations do es not mean that they are necessar

ily the same categoryAnobvious alternative is that the pro cesses which

treat NP and S the same are stated so as to op erate on a class of categories

of whichNPandS are memb ers This is the current view NP and S are

the arguments

NP and S are not only distinguished in b eing arguments they were also

distinguished as b eing the two cyclic no des in earlier generative grammar

That NP and S should b e so distinguished is not surprising Noun and

verb are the two most basic categories they play a centralroleinevery

language NP and S are their maximal pro jections in an intuitive sense

which I will make precise b elow This do es not explain why NP and S

have precisely the prop erties they have but it do es lead us to exp ect them

to play a sp ecial role in the grammar

Another waythatsentences b ehave rather like noun phrases is in par

ticipating in binding relations Consider the following examples

a that words are meaningless refutes itself

i i

b that words are meaningless refutes it

i i

that John is dead means that he do esnt knowit

i i

c it proves that Bill thinks that words are meaningful

i i

illustrates sentences participating in binding relations that are sub ject

to the binding conditions a b and c illustrate binding conditions

A B and C resp ectively

Lees also noted that certain noun phrasesnamely derived nominals

were similar to sentences in their internal structure and he accounted for

these similarities by deriving the noun phrases transformationally from sen

tences The internal similarities b etween sentence and noun phrase will b e

of much more concern for us than the similarities in their distribution The

most imp ortant reason for deriving noun phrases from sentences was to

account for the nearsynonymy in pairs like the following

a Neros destruction of Rome dismayed the Senate

b That Nero destroyed Rome dismayed the Senate

No accountwas given of the interpretation of either sentences or noun

phrases but it was considered that simplex sentences were the domain of

interpretation Hence to account for the synomymy of the noun phrase

GENERAL SIMILARITIES

in a and the sentential sub ject of b it was necessary to derive

them b oth from the same simplex sentence viz Nero destroyedRome

The relevant part of the interpretation of simplex sentences is represented

in the current theory by grids by assuming destroy and destruction have

the same grid we can disp ense with the transformational account of

Sentences and noun phrases are also similar with resp ect to pro cesses

likecontrol and binding The basic binding facts are the same in sentence

and noun phrase

John p ortrayed himself

i i

John s protrayal of himself

i i

himself p ortrayed John him

i i i

his own p ortrayal of John him

i i i

John recommended for himself to p ortray himself

i i

John recommended his own p ortrayal of himself

i i

John recommended for himself to p ortrayhim

i i

John recommended his own p ortrayal of him

i i

Control facts are also similar in noun phrase and sentence Adjunct

clauses can only b e controlled by the sub ject not the ob ject

a John criticized Bill after his talk

j j

b Johns criticism of Bill after his talk

j j

c John criticized Bill after PRO talking

j j

d Johns criticism of Bill after PRO talking

j j

Both c and d are ne where John controls PRO

When Chomsky intro duced a nontransformational account of the the

matic similarities b etween sentence and noun phrase Chomsky he

also considered the fact that a structural sub jectob ject distinction was

necessary in the noun phrase as well as sentence and intro duced the no de

Nand Xtheoryprecisely for this reason If we dene ccommand as fol

lows ccommands if neither dominates the other and the rst branch

ing no de dominating dominates then with the intro duction of Nbar

the noun phrase and sentence are similar enough in structure to account

for the facts of and The sub jects of b oth noun phrase and

sentence assymetrically ccommand the ob jects allowing us to capture the

assymetry in binding and control facts

A p ointonwhichsentence and noun phrase remain dissimilar under

Chomskys accountwhich has b ecome the standard account is Case

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

and assignment to the sub ject In the noun phrase the heads external

role is assigned internal to its maximal pro jection In the sentence the

verbs external role is assigned externallyTo distinguish internal and

external assignment then it seems wemust again use the relation c

command with the rstbranchingno de denition Actuallywe cannot say

rst branching no de but rst no de otherwise wewould incorrectly char

acterize the role assigned to John in Johns graduation for example as

an internal role If lack of ccommand by the head is the relation which

denes external assignment wemust characterize the relation b etween

the no de which assigns the external role and the recipient ofthatroleas

something dierent Namely VP do es not ccommand the sub ject of the

sentence The relation b etween VP and the sub ject is one of mcommand

m for maximal the term is from Chomsky a mcommands

i neither dominates the other and the rst maximal pro jection dom

inating dominates Of course the relation is actually tighter than

simply mcommand namely government Government is a sp ecial case of

mcommand

The other p oint of dissimilaritybetween sentence and noun phrase is

Caseassignment to the sub ject In recentwork Chomsky b assumes

that the Caseassigner of the sub ject of the noun phrase is the noun head

The Caseassigner of the sub ject of the sentence on the other hand is

not the verb but AGR in In In either case the relation b etween the

Caseassigner and the sub ject is again one of mcommand not ccommand

I will return to the ccommandmcommand distinction in section

I will argue that the distinction is only necessary b ecause the structural

p ositions standardly assigned to sub ject of noun phrase and sub ject of

sentence are not suciently parallel to account for the similarities in their

b ehavior in a simpler manner What is of greater interest at the moment

however is Caseassignment to the sub ject of the noun phrase There is

evidence that if taking the noun to b e the assigner of genitivecaseisnot

obviously inadequate in English it is not adequate as a universal solution

Namely there are numerous languages in which Caseassignment to the

sub ject of the noun phrase is much more similar to Caseassignmenttothe

sub ject of the sentence than it is in English This will lead us to a dierent

structure for the noun phrase in these other languages a structure which

is much more similar to the structure of the sentence The question which

then arises is whether this other structurethe DPanalysisis adequate

as a universal characterization of noun phrase structure if the standard

analysis is not I will show that it is adequatein fact highly desirable for English

INFL IN THE NOUN PHRASE

In in the Noun Phrase

There are numerous languages in which the noun phrase is much more like

the sentence than it is in English in that the noun phrase in these languages

has one or b oth or the following prop erties a p ossessed noun agrees

with its sub ject in the same way that the verb agrees with its sub ject

and the p ossessor receives the same case as the sub ject of the sentence

rather than a sp ecial genitive case Schematically

NP nomerg Nagr

NP i i

Both of these phenomena p oint to the existence of an AGR in the noun

phrase we see it overtly and we see its eects in the case assigned to the

p ossessor If there is an AGR then the minimal assumption is that there is

an Inlike p osition which it o ccupies If not wemust nd an explanation

for whyAGR o ccupies dierent p ositions in the sentence and noun phrase

The only alternative to p ostulating a nounphrase In which suggests

itself is that AGR is adjoined to N

NP

NP N

N

N AGR

Not only is this less desirable a priori b ecause it makes it more dicult

to account for the constraints on the p ositions in whichAGR app ears

but it is also empirically inadequate Namely it is reasonable to supp ose

that the conguration illustrated in with V substituted for N is

the structure of ob ject agreement markers sub ject agreement markers are

generated in In ob ject agreement markers in the verb If NP lacks an In

like p osition we predict that it will only have ob ject agreementmarkers In

fact in Yupik nouns have both sub ject and ob ject agreement markers

Thus the hyp othesis under which illustrates the only p osition for AGR

in the noun phrase is empirically inadequate and we are forced to assume

an Inlike p osition in the noun phrase

Let us b egin then by considering the facts from Yupik in more detail



The ob ject agreement is not agreement with an actual ob ject I have called it

ob ject agreement b ecause it is morphologically identical to ob ject agreement in the

sentence See immediatelybelow section

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Yupik

Yupik a Central Alaskan Eskimo language provides a textb o ok exam

ple of a language with AGR in the noun phrase Nounseven concrete

nounsagree with their p ossessors The agreement they show is the same

agreement morpheme which is found on the verb sharing even the same

suppletions Furthermore the sub ject of the noun phrase takes ergative

case the case of sub jects of transitiveverbs

angutem kiputaa

manERG buyOMSM

the man b ought it

angutet kiputaat the men pl b oughtit

angutek kiputaak the men du b oughtit

angutem kuiga

manERG riverSM

the mans river

angutet kuigat the mens pl river

angutek kuigak the mens du river

The parallelism in agreement and Caseassignment is immediately ac

counted for if we assume parallel structures

IP

DP I

angutet I VP

AGR V

t kiputaa



SM abbreviates sub ject agreementmarker OM abbreviates ob ject agreement

marker

INFL IN THE NOUN PHRASE

DP

DP D

angutet D NP

AGR N

t kuiga

The lexical head kiputaa or kuiga raises to join to AGR p ossibly at PF

On the other hand there is a dierence b etween the two structures

Namely the verb is agreeing with two arguments whereas the noun has

only one argument This might suggest that the alternative to the DP

analysis illustrated in is in fact correct Supp ose that a given head

can only agree with one argument at dstructure headraising may create

elements containing multiple agreementmarkers after dstructure

At dstructure a head can b ear at most one AGR element

We could argue that In is necessary in the sentence b ecause the verb has

two arguments and twoAGRs but it can only b ear one of the AGRs

itself hence the necessity of an In to b ear the other AGR The noun on

the other hand has only one AGR thus no nounphrase In is necessary

DP NP

DPi D NPi N

D VP N

D AGRi V DPj N AGRi

e t V AGRj pro kuiga t

kiputa a

But under this analysis it is curious that p ossessed nouns pattern mor

phologically with transitive verbs rather than intransitiveverbs Unp os

sessed nouns pattern with intransitiveverbs

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

yurartuq she dances

yurartut they pl dance

yurartuk they du dance

arnaq a woman

arnat women pl

arnak women du

Despite the fact that unp ossessed nouns have no argument they b ear an

agreement marker which enco des their own referential features sp ecif

icallynumb er Morphologically this agreement marker is identical to

that on the verb Let us assume that it is in fact the same element AGR

Tonowwehave made the implicit assumption that AGR is licensed lo osely

sp eaking by b earing an agreement relation to an argument Wenow need

to qualify that assumption

AGR is licensed either A by b earing the Agreement relation to an

argument or B by axing to the semantic head of an argument

Reconsider p ossessed nouns now Possessed nouns also showown

agreement and this agreement corresp onds to ob ject agreementintheverb

angutet kiputaat the men pl b oughtit

angutet kiputait the men pl b ought them pl

angutek kiputakt the men pl b ought them du

angutet kuigat the mens pl river

angutet kuigit the mens pl rivers pl

angutet kuigkt the mens pl rivers du

Thus the original structure given for the noun phrase in should b e

revised not to but to the following

DP

DPi D

angutet D NP

D AGRi Nj

t Nj AGRj

kuig a



kt suppletes to gket

INFL IN THE NOUN PHRASE

Mayan

A similar paradigm is found in Mayan I illustrate with data from Tzutujil

drawn from Dayley

Tzutujil lacks case marking but its agreement follows an ergativeabsolutive

pattern in that the sub ject agreement marker for intransitiveverbs is iden

tical to the ob ject agreement marker for transitiveverbs For example

xo qwari asp ect pOMsleep we slept

xixwari pOM you pl slept

xeewari pOM they slept

xixqakunaa j asp ect pOMpSMcure we cured you pl

xekunaa j sOMpSM you pl cured him

xeekikuunaa j pOMpSM they cured them

In the Mayan literature the ergative agreementmarkers whichIhave

lab elled SM are called Typ e A and the absolutive markers OM

Typ e B The full paradigm is

B absOM A ergSM

in nuu

at aa

ruu

oq qa

ix ee

ee kee

Ki is an alternantofkee

Nouns agree with their p ossessors and the agreementmarker they take

is the ergative marker SM

qatzan our nose

eetzan your pl nose

keetzan their nose

As in Yupik wecancharacterize the Typ e A AGR as AGR asso ci

ated with a functional categoryI or Dand the Typ e B AGR as AGR

asso ciated with lexical categories Tzutujil diers from Yupik only in that

Tzutujil do es not use Typ e B AGR as own AGR on the noun

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Hungarian

In Hungarian as well similar facts are to b e found Hungarian diers from

the other languages wehave examined in that it is nominativeaccusative

rather than ergativeabsolutive The relevant paradigm in Hungarian is the

following from Szab olcsi cf Szab olcsi

az en vendegem

my guest

the Inom guestp ossds

a te vendeged

your guest

the younom guestp ossds

a Mari vendege

Marys guest

the Marynom guestp ossds

Again the p ossessor shows the case of the sub ject of the sentencenominative

in this case rather than ergative and the head noun agrees with the p os

sessor This agreement is morphologically identical to the verbs sub ject

agreement On the basis of these examples in fact Szab olcsi argues that

there is an In no de in the noun phrase She argues that In is sp ecied

either for the feature Tense or for the feature Possessed the former when it

app ears in the sentence and the latter when it app ears in the noun phrase

Her In corresp onds to our In and her In corresp onds to

Tense Poss

our D

It may cause some concern that the denite article precedes the p ossessor

in If the determiner marks the p osition of nounphrase In as we

sp eculated in the intro duction then the p ossessor in app ears in the

one place it should not app ear In particular if a nominal In selects NP

and the determiner marks the p osition of In there are four p ossible word

orders as follows

DP DP

POSSR D POSSR D

D NP NP D



Horro cks Stavrou argue for the same analysis and the same two features

for mo dern Greek Szab olcsi and Horro cks Stavrou havearrived at the same analysis

apparently indep endently Nouns do not agree with their p ossessors in Mo dern Greek

Horro cks Stavrou were concerned with accounting for extraction from noun phrase in

Greek I will discuss some of their facts shortly

INFL IN THE NOUN PHRASE

DP DP

D POSSR D POSSR

D NP NP D

The two orders that are excluded are those in which the Possessor app ears

between determiner and noun exactly as in

Szab olcsi notes that az is eccentric in its p osition however All other

determiners app ear where wewould exp ect them

Peter minden kalap ja Peters every hat

Peter ezen kalap ja Peters this hat

Peter melyik kalap ja Peters which hat

Szab olcsi argues that az unlike the other determiners is not a nounphrase

In but a nounphrase Complementizer she argues that the noun phrase

in Hungarian parallels the sentence in structure not only in p ossessing an

Inectional head but also in p ossessing a nominal Complementizer pro jec

tion b eyond that

I will not consider this extension of the basic idea of nounphrasesentence

parallelism in any detail but I would like to briey examine the facts Since

there are also facts from Greek which b ear on the question I will devote a

separate section to it The question of the p osition of lexical determiners

in Hungarian I take up again in section IVc

Digression Comp in the Noun Phrase

Szab olcsi p oints out that there is a second kind of p ossessor in Hungarian

whichtakes and precedes az

Peternek a kalap ja

PeterDAT the hat

Peters hat

This p ossessor diers from the nominative p ossessor in that it can b e freely

extracted whereas the nominative p ossessor cannot b e extracted at all

Szab olcsi argues that the dierence b etween the two p ossessors is that the

nominative p ossessor is the sp ecier of a nounphrase In whereas the da

tive p ossessor is the sp ecier of a nounphrase Comp The dative p ossessor

can b e extracted and still prop erly govern its trace whereas the trace of

the nominative p ossessor is to o deep inside the noun phrase to b e prop erly

governed from outside

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Horro cks Stavrou also argue for a Comp escap e hatch in

mo dern Greek though not on the basis of a dative p ossessor Horro cks

Stavrou note that many extractions from noun phrase that are ungram

matical in English are go o d in Greek

pyon akuses t mi t oti ap elisan t

i i i i

who hears the story that dismissp

who did you hear the story that they dismissed t

to kokino mu ip es pos aghorases t to forema t

i i i

the red medat saids how b oughts the dress

the red you told me that you b oughtthet dress

He correlates this with the fact that there is a topic p osition in the noun

phrase in Greek

a to vivlio tu Chomsky

the book thegen Chomsky

Chomskys b o ok

to endhiaferon ya to arthro afto

the interest in the article this

the interest in this article

to forema to kokino

the dress the red

the red dress

b tu Chomsky to vivlio t

i i

Chomskys book

ya to arthro afto to endhiaron t

i i

the interest in this article

to kokino to forema t

i i

the red dress

He claims that this topic p osition is the sp ecier of a nounphrase Comp

K which also serves as an escap e hatch for extraction out of noun phrase

in Greek

to kokino mu ip es p os aghorases t to forema t

i KP i DP i

If Horro cks Stavrous and Szab olcsis claim that there is a noun

phrase Comp can b e veriedand the evidence at least on the cursory

INFL IN THE NOUN PHRASE

examination wehavegiven it seems to indicate soit constitutes a strong

case that the noun phrase and sentence are parallel in p ossessing functional

heads and b olsters the more mo dest prop osal which I wish to defend

namely that there is a nounphrase equivalent of In

Turkish

Turkish also shows an agreement element on p ossessed nouns even on con

crete nouns Consider the following examples from Underhill

a el

thea hand

b senin elin

youGEN hands

your hand

c onun eli

heGEN hands

his hand

In Turkish the p ossessor has genitive case not nominative or ergative

Also the agreement paradigm diers from that found on matrix verbs The

paradigms are

Verbal Nominal

s yIm s Im

s sIn s In

s DIr s sIn

p yIz p ImIz

p sInIz p InIz

p DIrlEr p lErIn

The capitalized vowels are sp ecied only H their other features are

lled in by a pro cess of The capitalized D is a dental

stop unsp ecied for voicing

If nominal AGR diers from verbal AGR in Turkish in its morphological

form and in the Case it assigns it nonetheless b ehaves like a true AGR in

that it licenses prodrop In fact though wehave not mentioned it to now

the nominal and verbal AGRs in all the languages wehave discussed to

now license prodrop This is not a necessary prop ertyofAGR but it is a

typical prop erty crosslinguistically Kornlt shows carefully that

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

the noun phrases in Turkish that can b e prodropp ed are all and only those

whose features are marked by either nominal or verbal AGR ie sub ject

of the sentence p ossessor and ob ject of certain p ostp ositions Though

other arguments can b e dropp ed they cannot b e dropp ed freely but only

under restrictive discourse conditions Kornlt argues that prodrop is not

involved in such cases

Kornlt also shows that nominal AGR assigns genitive case For exam

ple the twoaremutually dep endent a noun phrase cannot b ear genitive

case unless it agrees with a nominal AGR and if there is anyovert noun

phrase which agrees with a nominal AGR it must b ear genitive Case

a pastanIn bir parcasI

cakeGEN a pieces

a piece of cake

b pastadan bir parca

cakeABL a piece

a piece of cake

c pastanIn bir parca

d pastadan bir parcasI

Turkish also has Englishtyp e gerunds In fact all sub ordinate clauses

are gerundive There are twotyp es known in the literature as verbal

noun and nominalization The verbal noun involves the ax mE

mEk the nominalizationinvolves the ax DIg nonfuture or yEcEg

future There is a dierence in meaning which Underhill characterizes

as action verbal noun vs fact nominalization Their syntax is

virtually the same though the nominalizing morpheme is attached to the

verb stem after which nominal suxes nominal AGR case markerscan

b e attached The complements and adjuncts the nominalized verb takes are

identical to those whichittakes as a matrix verb with the exception that

the sub ject app ears in genitive case not nominative case Examples



These p ostp ositional phrases have the surface syntactic app earance of noun phrases

and p ossibly are to b e analyzed as such eg masanIn altI tableGEN unders under the table

INFL IN THE NOUN PHRASE

a i Halil her dakika isime karIsIr

Halil every minute businesssDAT interferes

Halil constantly interferes in my business

ii Halilin her dakika isime karIsmasI

HalilGEN every minute businesssDAT interfereINGs

Halils constantly interfering in my business

b Halilin geldigini biliyorum

HalilGEN comeINGsACC knowPROGs

I know that Halil is coming

c Kediye yemek vermediginiz dogru mu

catDAT fo o dACC giveNEGINGp true Q

Is it true that you did not give fo o d to the cat

In c for example the verb give assigns the same array of cases it assigns

in matrix sentences there are no underived nouns whichtake a comparable

array of arguments

Kornlt argues that AGR is the head of these emb edded sentences that

their structure is exactly parallel to that of the nonemb edded versions She

argues further that the structure extends to p ossessive noun phrases they

to o are headed by the AGR which app ears on the p ossessed noun and

assigns genitive case to the p ossessor She claims that p ossessive noun

phrases and sentences are b oth IP Under Kornlts account then non

p ossessive noun phrases dier in syntactic category from p ossessive noun

phrase the former b eing NP the latter IP This problem can b e eliminated

by assuming exactly what wehave argued to now sentence and noun phrase

are b oth headed by inectional elements In in the sentence D in the noun

phrase The dierence b etween p ossessed and nonp ossessed noun phrases

is the presence or absence of AGR not a dierence of syntactic category

The Turkish facts are esp ecially interesting for two reasons they show

that at least in some languages there is an AGR in the noun phrase which

assigns Genitive case p ointing the waytoward an analysis in which there

is a similar but abstract AGR in English noun phrases and secondly the

Possing typ e of gerund app ears to b e rare crosslinguistically but Turkish

shows that it is not simply a quirk of English I will have a great deal more

to say ab out the Possing gerund in the Chapter I I I in I I Ib and b

I return briey to Turkish gerunds

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

The DPAnalysis

Concepts and Terminology

Ihave presented the essence of the p osition which I will defend in the rest

of this thesis that the noun phrase is headed by an Inlike category in

many languages including English and probably universallyIwould like

to sp ell out myhyp othesis carefully here and dene my terminology

a Inectional Elements

First I havespoken of an Inlike no de or an Inectional element in

the noun phrase without dening precisely what I mean I consider the

no de In to b e typical of a class of elements that I have elsewhere called

functional elementsincontrast with thematic elements They are typically

called nonlexical categories I resist this designation b ecause I assume

that complementizers and mo dals etc have lexical entries likeany other

word The twouncontroversial functional elements are Complementizer

and Inection

The primary prop erty of functional elements is this they select a unique

complement which is not plausibly either an argument or an adjunct of

the functional element C selects IP and I selects VPCandIdonot

taketypical arguments noun phrases prep ositional phrases sub ordinate

clauses not even as an option C and I do not takemultiple arguments

but only one IPoroneVP resp ectively And semantically at least on

an intuitivelevel C and I contrast with N V A etc in that they do

not describ e a distinct ob ject from that describ ed by their complement

In That John hit the bal l for instance the VP hit the bal l intuitively

describ es an act of hitting the IP John hit the bal l describ es an act of

hitting and the CP that John hit the bal l also describ es an act of hitting

This intuition is a ma jor motivation for the continuing debate over whether

V is not actually the head of the sentence In the passing on of the

descriptivecontent of their complements functional heads contrast with

thematic heads The noun phrase the bal l describ es a ball when that noun

phrase is the complementofaverb as in hit the bal l the VP emphatically

do es not describ e a ball but an action in this case an act of hitting

We see then that the relation b etween a functional element and its

complement and the relation b etween a thematic element and its comple

ment contrast starkly I assume that there are syntactic relations b etween

all heads and their complements or adjuncts by which those complements

and adjuncts are licensed a minimal condition on a wellformed syntactic

 Abney

THE DPANALYSIS

structure is that every no de b e licensed by some such relation These rela

tions divide into two classes thematic relations on the one hand including

at least assignment and the relation by which adjuncts are licensed there

is no concensus ab out what precisely that relation is and functional se

lection or fselection on the other hand The syntactic relation b etween

a functional element and its complement is fselection Fselection corre

sp onds semantically to the passing on of the descriptive content of the

complement The relation b etween a nonfunctional element and its com

plement is a thematic relation for this reason I call nonfunctional elements

thematic elements I distinguish functional elements from thematic ele

ments by means of the syntactic category feature F Functional elements

are F thematic elements are F

There are a large numb er of prop erties that typify the functional ele

ments in contrast with the thematic elements and justify our treatment

of them as a natural class I will discuss these prop erties in the next sec

tion I would liketopoint out here that these additional prop erties do

not dene the class of functional elements functional elements are dened

as those elements which p ossess the feature F There are atypical func

tional elements just as there are atypical elements within virtually every

grammatical category This do es not call into question the existence of the

classes it only means that in some cases it is dicult to decide howto

classify a particular item

b CProjection and SProjection

The distinction b etween fselection and thematic relations allows us to cap

ture the intuition that the verb is the head of the sentence without sup

p osing literally that S VP Let us distinguish two notions of pro jection

whichwemay call cpro jection category pro jection ie syntactic pro

jection and spro jection semantic pro jection These designations are

of course mo delled on Pesetskys cselection and sselection A

no des cpro jection is its syntactic pro jection in the usual sense the maxi

mal cpro jection of V is VPIIP and C CP A no des spro jection path is

the path of no des along which its descriptive content is passed along The

maximal spro jection of V is CP via IP likewise the maximal spro jection

ofIisCP and the maximal spro jection of C is CPFormally

is an spro jection of i

a or

b is a cpro jection of an spro jection of or

c fselects an spro jection of

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

To illustrate graphically the cpro jection set of the lower V is circled in

a and its spro jection set is circled in b

c D vs Det

Returning to the noun phrase what it means to prop ose an Inlike no de

as head is that there is a functional element a F category which heads

the noun phrase I have designated this category D and will continue to

do so but I must stress that the existence of a functional head of the noun

phrase and the question whether the determiner is the head of the noun

phrase are two separate questions Except in a handful of passages I will

b e concerned only with the former question whether there is a functional

head of the noun phrasein this chapter and the next In Chapter Four I

turn to the second question whether or not determiners are lexical items

of category D the way mo dals are items of category I

It is easy to conate the two issues The In no de is the site of b oth lex

ical Insie mo dalsand of AGR This corresp ondence is not neces

saryhowever An account in which there were no indep endent morphemes

of syntactic category In would not b e incoherent As it happ ens there

is some evidence that mo dals are of category In they are in contrastive

distribution with overt AGR ie only when a mo dal is present do nite

verbs fail to mark agreement with the sub ject they are in contrastive dis

tribution with innitival to which is itself in contrastive distribution with

AGR overt or nonovert It is an op en question whether similar evidence

can b e pro duced to supp ort the claim that lexical determiners o ccupy the

THE DPANALYSIS

same p osition as AGR in the noun phrase assuming there is an AGR in

the noun phrase

For the purp oses of the next twochapters then the designation D

is entirely arbitrary it is a hyp othetical syntactic category whichisF

but distinguished from In and Comp in that it b elongs to the nominal

system not the verbal system ie D is NF whereas In and Comp

are NF D is the site of AGR in the noun phrase By Determiner on

the other hand I mean the lexical determiners leaving op en the question

whether in fact D Determiner Det is synonymous with Determiner

A few more notes on terminology under the DPanalysis the noun

phrase is DP not NP DP is sub ject to the Case Filter and Criterion DP

undergo es Passive and WhMovement leaving b ehind DPtraces When I

write NP I mean the maximal cpro jection of N NP under the DP

analysis corresp onds to N in the standard analysis I never use NP simply

as an abbreviation for noun phrase in a pretheoretic sense When I wish

to refer to the noun phrase without presupp osing an analysis I always

write out noun phrase this refers to DP under the DPanalysis and

NP under the standard analysis

d Syntactic Features

Iwould like to conclude this section by sp elling out my assumptions ab out

the feature comp osition of syntactic categories in a little more detail

Anticipating conclusions of later chapters let us take the nounverb

distinction to b e the most fundamental categorial distinction adjectives

clearly group with nouns in English though not in all languages prep osi

tions less clearly group with verbs but probably so Adhering to standard

notation the feature that captures the nounverb dichotomyisthus N

I am not p ersuaded that adjectives and verbs have something in common

that nouns and prep ositions lack however in the way that they are group ed

by the feature V Certainly the adjectiveverb vs nounprep osition di

chotomyisinnoway on a par with the noun vs verb or functional vs

thematic dichotomies There are two ma jor motivations for having the fea

ture V to predict that there are four ma jor syntactic categories

when taken in conjunction with N and to p ermit a treatmentof

passive participles as unsp ecied for V

As concerns the second p oint in section I I I I argue for a very dif

ferent view of passive participles which replaces any need for considering

passive participles to b e verbadjectivehybrids unsp ecied for V

As concerns the rst p oint there are in fact clearly many more syntactic

categories than N V A and P in English We can also add at least Q Adv Det In Comp Conj And A and P are not so ma jor that they

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

app ear in all languages Some languages lack Englishtyp e adjectives or

nearly so Swahili is a famous example Other languages app ear to lack

a separate class of adp ositions using nouns instead the Mayan languages

for instance

Further there are two distinct categories with very dierentsyntactic

prop erties which meet notional criteria of adjectiveho o d ie they typi

cally denote physical attributes emotional states etc In some languages

adjectives in the notional sense are syntactically very similar toeven

a sub category ofverbs in other languages they b ehavesyntactically like

nouns Many languages have b oth syntactic typ es with a prep onderance

of one or the other It app ears then that there are at least twosyntactic

categories that are notionally adjectives one essentially nominal N

as in English and one essentially verbal N If so and if b oth syntac

tic typ es of adjective constitute ma jor categories then wehave ve ma jor

categories not four

These are my reasons for b eing skeptical of the standard NV cate

gory tetrachotomy I do not claim that I haveproven in this brief discussion

that there is no feature V nonetheless I do not adopt it I do assume

nouns are distinguished from adjectives and prep ositions are distinguished

from verbs but I do not assume that these two distinctions necessarily have

anything in common

I assume two ma jor features F N which dene four ma jor classes

of syntactic categories I also assume that there are minor features that

distinguish sub classes of syntactic categories but I will not argue here for

a particular set of minor features Unless a given minor feature cuts across

ma jor syntacticcategory classes the question of the identity of the minor

features is not very interesting A candidate for a minor feature which

cuts across ma jor syntacticcategory classes is that which distinguishes

nouns and adjectives In section IV I examine the p ossibility that this

feature also distinguishes b etween main verbs and auxiliaries ie that

NAVAux

The four ma jor classes of syntactic categories are as follows

See Dixon for a detailed notional characterization of adjective and a survey

of language typ es with regard to the syntactic expression of adjective notions

I do not assume that categories are necessarily dened by their feature comp ositions

I assume that features dene classes of categories but I leave op en the question whether

it is p ossible for two categories to have all feature sp ecications in common yet remain distinct categories

THE DPANALYSIS

F F

N V Aux P I C

N N A Q Adv D

These classes app ear not to b e exhaustive For example conjunctions like

and or app ear to b e F but unsp ecied for N they app ear equally

freely in b oth nominal and verbal systems Likewise P seems to straddle

the line b etween functional and thematic elements one might wish to treat

it as unsp ecied for F

Functional Selection

In this section I would like to consider the prop erties of functional cate

gories in more detail

The distinction b etween thematic and functional categories is a very

venerable one Aristotle in his Poetics makes a ma jor category cut b etween

complementizers conjunctions etc on the one hand and nouns verbs

and adjectives on the other The traditional Japanese grammarian Akira

Suzuki in his Gengyo YonsyuRon On Four Parts of Sp eech

distinguishes four syntactic categories noun verb adjective and particles

case markers auxiliary verbs etc The rst three are si the last zi

The distinction b etween functional and thematic elements is also im

p ortantinpsychology Children acquire functional elements later than the

matic elements Also in certain aphasias the ability to pro cess functional

elements is lost while the ability to use and understand thematic elements

survives

There are a numb er of prop erties that characterize functional elements

in contradistinction to thematic elements Like all ma jor grammatical dis

tinctions there is a substantial grayareabetween thematic and functional

elements there are thematic elements with some prop erties of functional

elements and vice versa and some items that are very dicult to cate

gorize at all Thisdoesnotnullify the distinction however And even

though none of the following prop erties are criterial for classication as a

functional element that do es not mean that it is false or naive to ascrib e

these prop erties to the class of functional elements The prop erties which

characterize functional elements then are

Functional elements constitute closed lexical classes

 My source on Suzuki is Makino

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Functional elements are generally phonologically and morphologically

dep endent They are generally stressless often clitics or axes and

sometimes even phonologically null

Functional elements p ermit only one complement which is in general

not an argument The arguments are CPPP and I claim DP

Functional elements select IPVPNP

Functional elements are usually inseparable from their complement

Functional elements lack what I will call descriptive content Their

semantic contribution is secondorder regulating or contributing to

the interpretation of their complement They mark grammatical or

relational features rather than picking out a class of ob jects

The nal characteristic concerning the semantics of functional ele

ments is in some sense the crucial characteristic It is the prop erty con

sistently chosen by traditional grammarians to characterize functional el

ements Aristotle denes functional elements simply as words without

meaning in contrast to thematic elements words with meaning For

Suzuki the rst prop ertyofasi thematic element is that it denotes

something the rst prop ertyofazi is that it denotes nothing it only

attaches voice of heart to si quoted in Makino

Descriptive contentwhat functional elements lackis a phrases link

to the world If someone utters the word ball and there is a ball in view

the default assumption is that that ball is b eing describ ed by the utterance

This is the sense in which the noun bal l has descriptivecontent Verbs also

have descriptivecontent in this sense For instance if John hits Bill and

the word hit is uttered it is clear what action is b eing describ ed On

the other hand with the utterance of a functional elementsay the mo dal

wil l or the complementizer ifit is not p ossible to pick out some bit of the

world in the same wayWords with immediacy and concreteness are those

with descriptive content they are the words that survive when language is

reduced to bare b ones as when one is attempting to communicate with a

nonsp eaker of ones language

More formally thematic elements are roughly those which denote a

predicate of typ e he ti ie functions from entities to truth values rst

order predicates This is uncontroversial with regard to common nouns

Verbs however are not usually considered to b e exclusively singleplace

predicates Under most accounts there are at least transitiveverbs of typ e

he he tii in addition to intransitives My characterization of thematic

elements as those with he ti denotations can b e maintained though if we



On the other hand predicates of typ e he he tii and he he he tiii etc are rst

THE DPANALYSIS

adopt a somewhat extreme form of Davidsons event semantics Let us

assume that as in my informal discussion verbs are singleplace predi

cates over events Hit for example do es not denote x y x hit y nor

even e x y e iswas an eventofx hitting y as Higginb otham b

assumes but rather ee iswas an event of hitting For thematic ele

ments then this view involves a complete divorcing of semantic arguments

and syntactic arguments No syntactic argumentofaverb is a semantic

argument of it Syntactic arguments eg agent patient are related to the

verb via roles functions from events to ob jects For example the VP

hitaboy would have the denotation ee iswas an event of hitting x

b oyx Patiente x I take assignment to b e a place syntactic

relation holding among a assigner a receiver and a role In general

the denotation of any phrasemarker of the form b c where Thetabc

a

is ebe ec

In contrast to thematic elements functional elements take predicates

as arguments they are functors Following Higginb otham wemay

assume that In is an existential quantier over predicates of events The

denotation of an Ibar I VP is true i eVPe In similar fashion de

terminers taketwo predicates as arguments the characterization of deter

miners sp ecicallyquanticational determiners as relations b etween sets

is from Barwise and Co op er cf Higginb otham May The



denotation of the noun phrase the boy for instance is X X yb oy y

 

yb oy y if jyb oy y j undened otherwise

Two Notions of Command

Before I turn to a preliminary consideration of the second half of the

DP hyp othesisie that determiners o ccupy the p osition of DI would

like to discuss one advantage that accrues to the DP hyp othesis simpliciter

The DPanalysis allows us to reunify the notion of ccommand For most

purp oses the denition of ccommand which is required is one in which

the cdomain of a no de is the rst maximal category which dominates that

no de But with resp ect to binding in the noun phrase a simplied ver

sion of Reinharts original branching no de denition is necessary

order predicates in contrast with eg determiners which are of typ e hhe ti hhe titii

ie which take predicates as arguments If one nds ob jectionable the extension of

Davidsons ideas I present immediately b elow in the text thematic and functional ele

ments can still b e distinguished as rstorder vs secondorder predicates



In a very broad sense of event which means something closer to situation than

event in the usual sense In particular I assume that stativeverbs and the like denote

events in the intended sense of event



There are a numb er of matters I am glossing over I give a formal and much more

detailed account in Abney in preparation

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Consider the noun phrases of

a picture of himself

b The citys destruction t

c His picture of himself

d Its destruction t

e Himself s picture of himself

f Himself s destruction t

If we assume the maximal category denition of ccommand and as

sume that is not maximal the sub ject and ob ject p ositions mutually

ccommand So wewould exp ect that a Johns picture of himselfwould

violate Condition C of the binding theory as the rexpression John is c

commanded and b ound by himself Similarly his picture of himself should

violate Condition B and e and f should arguably b e go o d with each

anaphor binding the other For this reason Chomsky a adopts two

command relations ccommand with the branching no de denition and

mcommand with the maximal category denition We can avoid this

duplication of relations by supp osing as in the DPanalysis that is in

fact maximal Then a nouns complementwould fail to mcommand its

sub ject as desired

It is conceptually disagreeable to have one general notion of command

mcommandand another sp ecial notion of command for binding theory

solely to b e able to account for binding in the noun phrase But matters

are in fact worse than this Consider again these adjunct control examples

from section

a John criticized Bill after his talk

j j

Johns criticism of Bill after his talk

j j

b John criticized Bill after PRO talking

j j

Johns criticism of Bill after PRO talking

j j

We can account for this paradigm if we assume that the after adjunct is

attached high enough that the coindexed elements Bil l and hisorBil l and

PRO do not ccommand each other This do es not prevent the pronoun

from taking Bil l as antecedent but it do es blo ckcontrol of PROby Bil l

b Control of PRO is p ossible only when the antecedent ccommands

PRO

Under the standard analysis this entails that ccommand not mcommand

is the requisite notion of command inasmuchaswe can attach the after

adjunct no higher than daughter of NPinwhich case the only no de inter

vening b etween Bil l and PRO is Nbar

THE DPANALYSIS

This is problematic b ecause it would predict that it would b e imp ossible

for a direct ob ject of a verbtocontrol an adjunct within VP In the structure

NP do es not ccommand IP hence control should b e blo cked

VP

V IP

V NP

But there is reason to b elieve that control is in fact not blo cked in this

conguration Consider the following examples

a I gave the gun to Mugsy PRO to get rid of it

i j i

b I gave the gun to Mugsy PRO to get rid of it

i j j

c I gave the gun to Mugsy PRO to get rid of

i j i

d I gave the gun to Mugsy PRO to get rid of

i j j

We can account for this paradigm by assuming there must b e mutual c

command b etween the controller and the adjunct When there is no op era

tor the adjunct can attach either under IP a or under VP b with

corresp onding dierences in the identity of the controller When the ob ject

p osition is b ound by an empty op erator on the other hand there must b e

mutual ccommand b etween the adjunct and the antecedent of the empty

op erator viz the gun Hence only the VP attachmentisavailable and

c is ungrammatical

If the adjunct is under VPhowever it is still an adjunct and for that

V Thus we are brought to the conclusion that reason cannot b e under

b and d have the structure shown in with control b etween

the ob ject and the adjunct This conclusion runs directly counter to the

hyp othesis that the sub jectob ject assymetry in control in the noun phrase

is to b e accounted for by attaching the adjunct outside N It is p erfectly

compatible with the DPanalysis however where the uniform denition of

N but not V is a command is in terms of maximal pro jections and

maximal pro jection

Det as Head

In this section I would like to consider in a preliminary way the hyp othesis

that the determiner is the lexical instantiation of D

The primary motivation for putting determiners in the p osition of D is

to allowustomaintain a general restrictiveversion of Xbar theory First

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

it is widely assumed in GB circles that phrase structure rules should b e

entirely eliminated If we eliminate the phrase structure rule



NP

NP N

Det

wemust explain what constrains the determiner to app ear in the p osition

it o ccupies ie under the standard analysis

NP

DET N

POSSR

N COMPL

In current GBtheory an account for the distribution of some element

generally takes the following form app ears only where it is licensed

It is licensed minimallyby some semanticallyinterpreted relation it b ears

to some other element assignment is the quintessential such licensing

relation Additional relations may imp ose additional restrictions

There is apparently a selectional relation b etween the determiner and

noun that provides a likely candidate for the licensing relation that de

termines the distribution of determiners Determiners only o ccur in noun

phrases and nouns often require a determiner eg singular count nouns

The question is then the nature of the relation b etween determiner and

noun We might assume that N selects Det alternatively DetP

The only real mo dels wehave for such a relation are the relation b etween

I and its sub ject or that b etween C and its sub ject following Fassi Fehri

Chomsky a in assuming that fronted whelements o ccupy

Sp ec of C However N clearly do es not assign DetP nor is there any

likely source for a movement which lands DetP in Sp ec of N If determiners

were sub jects of N wewould exp ect eg that paw to b e interpreted as if

it were thats paw But determiners are neither arguments nor adjuncts

Another p ossibility is that DetP mo dies N and selection is imp osed

via this mo dication relation ie DetP is only capable of mo difying Ns



With some exceptions That for instance also o ccurs in APs that bigButit

is sucient here that there exist determiners suchasthe every which only app ear in noun phrases

THE DPANALYSIS

This would put DetP on a par with adjective phrases Determiners dier

from adjectives in imp ortantways however Adjectives even in prenominal

p osition clearly head full phrases as is evident from the fact that they take

their own sp eciers

a nearly as devastating attack

AP

DetP never contains any material except Det Corresp onding to this APs

app ear in p ositions other than the prenominal p osition p ostnominallyas

complementof be seem etc as heads of small clauses Some Dets never

app ear outside of the noun phraseeg the aand others when they

stand alone b ehave exactly like noun phrases

that was a nice idea

DetP

Iwould like some

DetP

John thoughtabout those

DetP

This last fact suggests that DetP in fact is the noun phrase This leads

us to a third hyp othesis that Det selects a pro jection of N not vice versa

In this case there is a ready mo del for the relation b etween Det and NP

namely fselection Det has all the prop erties of a functional element It

constitutes a closed lexical class it is often phonologically weak and in

separable from its complement eg the and a and it lacks descriptive

content If Det b elongs to the same class of elements as Comp and Inas

it certainly app ears tothe minimal assumption is that it is licensed by the

same relation viz fselection The analysis allows us to accountfor



I am b eing a little sloppyhereinmy use of the word license TechnicallyDetis

not licensed by NP under the analysis rather NP is licensed by Det Det is licensed

by b eing the head of DetPwhichisnow the noun phrase and licensed in the ways that

wehave always assumed noun phrases are licensed Det is licensed by fselection only

in the sense that the analysis provides a place for Det in the network of licensing relations

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

the licensing of Det without inventing a new kind of relation the licensing

of Det generalizes with that of In and Comp

There are further Xbar theoretic considerations that make the Det

ashead analysis attractive First D is no longer defective with resp ect

to Xtheory but pro jects a phrasal no de and takes a complement like

other categories This is in keeping with the analysis of I and C which has

emerged in recentyears see Chomsky Stowell Chomsky a

in whichIandCaretaken to participate fully in the X system In fact the

Detashead analysis is almost forced if we wish to supp ose generally that

nonlexical categories are not defective with resp ect to Xbar theory

Another Xbar theoretic advantage of the Detashead analysis is that

determiner and p ossessor no longer app ear in the same p osition There

is a tendency in current views of Xbar theory toward the p osition that

max

there are X p ositions on the one hand and X p ositions on the other

Xschema and the two are completely disjoint In the formulation of the

given in Stowell the Sp ec p osition like complement p ositions can

only b e lled with maximal pro jections not X s An X cannot ll an

max max

X p osition and vice versa This separation of X and X p ositions

max

is preserved and strengthened in Chomskys recentwork an X can

max max

substitute only into an X p osition and an X can adjoin only to

max

an X mutatis mutandis for X The Detashead analysis allows us to

Xschema without confronting us with the adopt this strong version of the

embarassing question of whyDetPnever contains any material except Det

With regard to complements and sp eciers wenowhaveavery sym

metric system Only functional categories ie C I D freely haveovert

sub jects John was Bill seen Johns Bill s

IP VP DP NP

pictureif we assume that only functional categories can host AGR this

fact is immediately accounted for All and only sub ject p ositions are land

ing sites for movement where substitution is involved who Bill saw

CP IP

t Bill was seen t the citys destruction t

IP VP DP NP

Another factor whichmakes a parallel syntactic treatment of Det and

In attractive is their semantic similiarity The function of the determiner

is to sp ecify the reference of a noun phrase The noun provides a predicate

and the determiner picks out a particular memb er of that predicates ex

tension The same function is p erformed in the verbal system by tense or

Inection The VP provides a predicate that is a class of events and tense

lo cates a particular event in time In Higginb othams terms In binds the

VPs event place in the same way that the Determiner binds the op en place

in NP



The qualication freely is meant to exclude cases where ECM into saySpecofAP

or Sp ec of PP under Stowells account of small clauses p ermits sub jects

to exceptionally app ear in these categories

THE DPANALYSIS

Though the idea that the Determiner is the head of the noun phrase

seems rather o dd at rst the conceptual considerations I havejustsketched

make it seem a very natural even necessary development of current views

of phrase structure I will discuss the Detashead analysis in more detail

in Chapter Four I haveintro duced it here b ecause I will o ccasionally make

reference to it in the remainder of this chapter and in the next

As a bibliographic note I would also liketopoint out that the Det

ashead analysis and the analysis in which there is an Inectional ie

functional head of the noun phrase are also not so o dd that others have

not thought of it b efore me When I rst b egan exploring the p ossibility

I thought it quite novel but I have since discovered comparable prop osals

in Brame Hale Hellan Horro cks Stavrou

Hudson Kornlt Kuro da Reuland Szab olcsi

For the most part these authors app ear to b e unaware of each others

work

The determiner as head of the noun phrase is also of course a very well

established tenet in the Montagovian semantic tradition Montague

and receives particular attention in the Generalized Quantier prop osal of

Barwise Co op er cf Higginb otham May

The Position of s

In this section I would like to consider how Case is assigned to the p ossessor

under the DPanalysis It is generally assumed that the s is involved in

Caseassignment to the p ossessor But what precisely is the p osition of s

and what is its relation to the p ossessor

a Morphological Case Ax

One p ossibility that can b e immediately eliminated is that s is a morpho

logical casemarking As is wellknown s cliticizes to the entire sub ject

noun phrase it do es not app ear simply as an ax on the head

a a cousin of mines house

b the man in the stores sudden disapp earance



If words like mine your are suppletive from Is or mes yous then cliticization

of s feeds morphological pro cesses This is not problematic



The text examples are not p erfectly wellformed Later in a dierent context I mark

them as marginal I think they are suciently go o d though to illustrate the claim that

s is not simply a case ax which attaches to the head of the noun phrase

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

b Determiner

Another p ossibility suggested to me byRichard Larson is that s in fact

o ccupies the determiner p osition ie that the structure is the following

DP

DP D

John D NP

s book

s app ears only prenominally in noun phrases DPs b ecause it is in fact

a D The noncoo ccurence of p ossessors and determiners is not problem

atic b ecause p ossessors do coo ccur with a determiner namely s Case

assignment to the p ossessor is parallel to Caseassignment in the sentence

s corresp onds to AGR in assigning Case to its sub ject Possessors fail to

coo ccur with other determiners b ecause other determiners are unable to

assign Case

c Postp osition N CaseAssigns

A third p ossibility is that s is a p ostp ositional Casemarker Let us assume

Chomskys b characterization of Caseassignment in the noun phrase

He assumes the standard analysis of the noun phrase in which the noun is

head s is not present at dstructure It is also not the assigner of Case

to the p ossessor Rather the noun assigns genitive case to the p ossessor

Genitive case in contrast to nominative and is an inherent

case and is assigned at dstructure However even though it is assigned

at dstructure it must b e realized at sstructure this is the purp ose of

sinsertion s is the realization of genitive case

This analysis is not readily transplantable into the DPanalysis struc

ture It is crucial for Chomsky that the noun govern the p osition in which

s app ears this is a consequence of his Uniformity Condition on inherent

Caseassignment by whichheintends to account for the lack of raising in



To account for genitive case assignmentinthePossing gerund Chomsky assumes

VP can assign genitive case when it heads a noun phrase This is highly problematic

Wehave already discussed how making VP the head of the Possing gerund violates

Xbar theory strictly interpreted Further unanswered questions are why VP is the only

Caseassigner which is a maximal pro jection and why VP do esnt assign genitive case

in other places such as to the sub ject of innitives The DPanalysis p ermits a much

less ad ho c account of gerunds as wehave seen and as will b e sp elled out in detail in

the next chapter

THE DPANALYSIS

the noun phrase among other things In the DPanalysis though the

noun do es not govern the p osition of the p ossessor This problem might

b e gotten around byintro ducing a notion of sgovernment which diers

from government only in that the elements whichanode can sgovern

b elong to the domain of its s maximal sprojection rather than that of

its maximal cpro jection Unless it can b e shown that sgovernment plays

some indep endent role in the grammar however an analysis which did not

require it would b e preferable

Quite apart from the DPanalysis an ob jection to Chomskys analysis

is that it do es not explain why s only app ears with p ossessors If s is the

realization of genitive Case it is explicable why it can only app ear in the

context of genitive case assignment but this would still p ermit s app earing

p ostnominally destruction the citys or in APs

On the other hand if s can only b e inserted under governmentbyNit

is dicult to explain why it can app ear in gerunds Johns baking the cake

As mentioned in fo otnote Chomsky assumes that VP exceptionally

assigns genitive case here this move seems to me to b e entirely ad ho c

d Postp osition AGR CaseAssigns

Alternativelywe could take s to b e a p ostp osition marking genitiveCase

assigned byAGR not N

DP

PP D

DP P D NP

s AGR N

An apparent problem for the p ostp ositional analysis is that the deter

miner never actually app ears but is always empty when there is a p ossessor

This would seem to make the p ostp ositional analysis and the DPanalysis

incompatible One p ossibility is that the disapp earance of the determiner

is actually an instance of a more general pro cess of determiner elision If

this is the case it turns this apparent liabilityinto an advantage Under an

analysis in which determiner and p ossessor o ccupy the same p osition there

is no determiner at all not even a deleted one making it dicult to ex

plain why p ossessed noun phrases have a denite interpretation Under the

elision analysis we can assume that the determiner that has b een deleted is denite

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Evidence for other cases of determiner elision is not hard to nd In

English consider the noun phrases

a a hundred nights

hundred nights

b those a hundred nights

those hundred nights

A is required b efore hundred unless a determiner pro ceeds when it is elided

A similar pro cess is found in Papago

a g aal

the children

b g hajee

the pmother

their mother

c g g aal hajee

the the children pmother

c am g miisa weco

the the table underneath

d g t hajee g aal

the pmother the children

the childrens mother

d am t weco g miisa

the underneath the table

under the table

e g aal hajee

the children pmother

the childrens mother

e am miisa weco

the table underneath

Two consecutive determiners as in cc are ungrammatical Either the

p ossessor can b e extrap osed as in dd other material in the sentence

can intervene b etween the noun phrase and the extrap osed p ossessor or

the inner p ossessors determiner can b e elided Evidence that the bracket

ting in e is as shown and not am miisa weco is that am is a sp ecial

 Data from K Hale pc Cf Hale et al

THE DPANALYSIS

lo cative determiner that only o ccurs with p ostp ositions like weco am

miisa is illformed

One piece of evidence weighing against the elision analysis is that rel

ative clauses are licensed by the but are prohibited with p ossessors the

book that I read Johns book that I read If there is an elided the with the

p ossessor ie if the structure is actually Johns the book that I read prior

to PFthis is unexp ected

An alternative to the elision analysis is that there is a coo ccurence re

striction in English whichprevents nominal AGR from o ccupyingaDnode

which is already o ccupied by a lexical determiner Then overt p ossessors

cannot coo ccur with determiners b ecause the p ossessors would not receive

Case

A nal question is whether the genitive marker s is presentatd

structure or inserted after dstructure If it is present at dstructure we

must tread lightly visavis passive in the noun phrase Ob ject of p ostp o

sition is generally assumed not to b e a valid landing site for movement

if we take s to b e a p ostp osition this would apparently b e incompati

ble with nounphrase passive We can avoid this problem by taking s to

b e equivalent to a casemarker in languages that overtly mark case For

concreteness let us assume casemarkers dier from true adp ositions in

that the phrase headed by the casemarker is like a noun phrase with re

sp ect to assignment Casemarkers are functional elements that inherit

the descriptivecontentand the referential indexof their complement

whereas true adp ositions are thematic elements that and Caseassign

their complements I will denote casemarkers as K in contrast with

true adp ositions ie P Further let us supp ose that an argument

must b e a maximal spro jection This means that a DP is an argument

when it is not the complement of a K but DP is not an argumentwhenit

is the complementofKThus assigning a role to KP but not to the DP

buried inside it do es not violate the criterion Finally casemarkers

b ear the case features of the argument they head these case features must

by licensed by and coincide with the Case actually assigned to the argu

ment If DP s isaKPwe can generate it as complement of a noun

receiving the internal role assigned by that noun and raise it to Sp ec of

D to receive genitive Case from AGR in other words the characterization

ofKIhave just given p ermits us to treat s as a p ostp ositional K without

forcing us to abandon the idea of passive in the noun phrase

It seems then that coherent accounts can given whether we take s to

b e present at dstructure or inserted in the course of the derivation For

conceptual reasons I prefer a theory in which dstructure can b e read o

of sstructure hence a theory which eschews insertion op erations For this

reason I prefer the analysis in which s is present at dstructure though

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

it will not b e crucial for anything I havetosay in what follows

There is also little evidence clearly favoring the sascasemarker analyis

over the sasdeterminer analysis of section b or vice versa I prefer

the sascasemarker analysis for two reasons historically s was a case

morpheme synchronically analyzing it as a case marker is more intuitive

than analyzing it as a determiner and the sasdeterminer analysis do es

not generalize to languages like Hungarian where p ossessors and lexical

determiners ie AGR and lexical determiners do coo ccur the sascase

marker analysis do es generalize to these languages

App endix Selection of DP

An obvious ob jection to the DPanalysis is that unlike C and I D do es not

app ear to b e selected by a matrix head but as is wellknown selectional

restrictions are imp osed on N This would argue against D as the head of

the noun phrase But note rst that the kinds of selectional restrictions

imp osed on nouns are purely semantic and not structural in the way the

restrictions imp osed on C and I have b een argued to b e Namely the kinds

of selectional restriction imp osed on ob ject noun phrases are also imp osed

on sub ject noun phrases Restriction to animate nouns is one such example

as illustrated in the classic sentences

a i Sincerityfrightens John

ii John frightens sincerity

b i Sincerity fears John

ii John fears sincerity

The sub ject however is not governed by the verb which imp oses the re

striction Thus though it is unexplained whyverbs do not select for deter

miners this is actually a general problem verbs do not select for any part

of the noun phrase in the way they select for C and I

In regard to the selection of determiners there is a very interesting

paradigm from Navaho that merits consideration There is a small class of

Navaho verbs which select for semantic categories typically assigned to the

determiner as illustrated in Perfective stem given All Navaho

examples drawn from Young Morgan

a hi to kill one thing

tseed to kill two or more things

b gho d to run of one b eing

chaa to run of two b eings

jee to run of three or more b eings

THE DPANALYSIS

c han to throw one thing

tliid to throwtwo or more things

a aad to lose toss a at exible ob ject

deel to lose toss a slender exible ob ject

ne to lose toss a round or bulky ob ject

b tso oz to handle a at exible ob ject

la to handle a slender exible ob ject

a to handle a round or bulky ob ject

tlee to handle mushy matter

ta to handle a slender sti ob ject

c keez to fall of a slender sti ob ject

heezh to fall ow of mushy matter

tsid to fall of a hard ob ject

tlizh to fall of an animate ob ject

The distinctions made in are distinctions often enco ded in determiners

ie in class markers such as are found in many East African languages

What is most striking is that unlike the semantic selectional restrictions

found in English these restrictions are imp osed only on the object There

are no transitiveverbs in Navaho which select for the numb er of their

sub ject in this fashion

There are two facts that make this paradigm only a curiosityhowever

First though the selected argumentisalways a sole argument it is prob

ably not always an underlying ob ject run for instance is not a typical

unaccusative meaning Secondly and more imp ortantlyNavaho do es not

actually mark any of these distinctionsob ject class or numb erin its de

terminer Despite this though I think that the Navaho paradigm do es

show that selection of determiner is not a p ossibility excluded byUniversal Grammar

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

PRO in the Noun Phrase

A question on which the DPanalysis b ears is whether there can b e a PRO

sub ject of the noun phrase The DPanalysis involves making the noun

phrase sentencelike in suchawayastomake ro om for a PRO sub ject

Certain curiosities ab out noun phrase b ehavior which indicate it is as if

there was a PRO in the noun phrase have long b een noted In this section

I review and expand on these facts

Under the standard analysis PRO in the noun phrase is not a p ossi

bility without signicantly altering certain assumptions ab out PRO if the

noun phrase is the maximal pro jection of N its sub ject p osition is always

governed by N hence PROisalways excluded

On the other hand the DPanalysis p ermits PRO in the sub ject p osition

of the noun phrase In particular since D is not a lexical categorywe

exp ect it not to b e a governor hence its sub ject p osition may b e ungoverned

dep ending on whether there is an external governor and whether DP is

abarriertogovernment In principle then there maybea PRO in the

sub ject p osition of DP

PRO b o ok

The standard analysis app ears to make the right predictions for examples

like the PRObook as observed by Aoun Sp ortiche Iwanted

the book cannot mean either I wanted my b o ok or I wanted someones

b o ok This indicates that there is neither a controlled nor arbitrary PRO

p ossessor present

However there is an explanation for the nono ccurence of PRO inde

p endent of the nongovernabilityofPRO It is very likely that the p osses

sor role is not assigned by the noun Possession is p ossible with every

concrete noun not varying from item to item as roles do It has b een

claimed by some that s is the assigner of the p ossessor role I would like

to state it slightly dierently the p ossessor role is assigned by D but

only when s is present This comes to the same thing if s isaDwe claim

that s is the only determiner that assigns the p ossessor role If s is a

casemarker we can supp ose that there is a unique empty D whichAGR is

able to o ccupy this empty D is the assigner of the p ossessor role

If this story is correct PRObook violates the Criterion there is no

role for PRO as there is no s On the other hand if s do es app ear



Under the accountinwhich s is a casemarkerwe are forced to take the somewhat

curious p osition that the empty D that assigns the p ossessor role call it D cannot

e

app ear without AGR If D satises count nouns need for a determiner and if it could

e

app ear without AGR wewould exp ect it to b e able to assign the p ossessor role to PRO

PRO IN THE NOUN PHRASE

there is either an AGR with it or it is itself equivalenttoAGR on the

sasdeterminer story in b eing a Caseassigner Thus PROs book is also

illformed in this case b ecause PROisgoverned byAGR

An apparentweakness in this account is a problem with one of my

assumptions namely that D is the assigner of the p ossessive role

AGR

There are apparent recipients of the p ossessive role which app ear as com

plements of N as in the social security number of your spouse cf your

spouses social security number If the p ossessive role is assigned byD

how can it show up inside NP I would like to suggest that the of involved

in these examples is a true prep osition which assigns the p ossessive role

In other words D assigns the p ossessive role but it is not the only

AGR

word which do es so D and of are unable to coo ccur for the same rea

AGR

son that twoverbal adjuncts which assign the same role cannot coo ccur

your spouses social security number of the big lout is equivalenttothe

ship was destroyedbyanExocet missle with that endish weapon Of your

spouse in the social security number of your spouse is thus distinct from

of your spouse in the deception of your spouse The former is a PP the

latter a KP The former is a assigner the latter not The distinction is

underlined in the fact that the assigner imp oses sp ecial restrictions on its

ob jects which are not imp osed by the case marker Consider

a the battlecry of the Visigoths

the battlecry of John

b the elimination of the Visigoths

the elimination of John

theory

a Derived Nominals

The rst argument that there is in some cases a PRO sub ject of DP comes

from theoryThe Criterion in its simplest form predicts a recipient

for the external role in action nominalizations like the destruction of the

in PROD b o ok Note that it is not sucient simply to saythatD is a governor

e e

indep endently of whether it has an AGR or not If D can app ear without AGR we

e

would predict that D b o ok without a PRO is wellformed the countnounbook has

e

an acceptable determinerIfwe claimed that D b o ok is bad b ecause D obligatorily

e e

assigns a role but there is nothing available in D b o ok to assign it to then we

e

run into problems with examples of nounphrase passive like the citys De destruction

where wewould liketosay that D Caseassigns but crucially do es not assign the

e

city



Whatever this restriction is it is not phonological ie no monosyllablesasit

might seem at rst OK the battlecry of fools

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

city and in fact an agent is understo o d Ceteris paribuswewould exp ect

the agenttobesyntactically realized

DP PRO the NP destruction of the city

th

We can assume that NP assigns the external role of destruction to PRO

via predication For cases suchasCaesars AGR destruction of

D NP

the city I wish to make a similar claim Caesar is Caseassigned byD

AGR

but it is assigned byNP The empty D in the p ossessive construction

assigns the p ossessor role optionally I assume If the p ossessor receives a

role from N either externallyasin Caesars destruction of Carthageor

via an internal trace as in the citys destruction t D do es not assign

AGR

the p ossessor role and the sub ject receives only one role as desired

b Rationale Clauses

Ro ep er presents evidence that implicit agents b ehave as if they are

syntactically present which supp orts the claim that implicit agents are

indeed presentasPRO Consider

a the PRO destruction of the city PROtoproveapoint

b the citys destruction PROtoprove a p oint

a the PRO review of the b o ok PROtoproveapoint

b the b o oks review PROtoproveapoint

Ro ep er exx

Ro ep er argues that the rationale clause is licensed only if the Agent role

is syntactically realized In the a sentences the rst PRO receives the

Agent role licensing the rationale clause In the b sentences on the other

hand the passivized ob ject lls the sub ject p osition excluding PRO Hence

the Agent is not realized and the rationale clause is not licensed

We cannot say simply that there must b e an Agent in the matrix clause

and it must control the sub ject of the rationale clause First there are

rationale clauses even where no control is involved

Jesus died that we mightlive

John cleaned o the table for Mary to haveroomtowork



Counter Williams I assume that predication is p ossible in the noun phrase

precisely b ecause I assume counter Williams that there is a maximalcategory predicate

NP within the noun phrase More on predication b elow section

PRO IN THE NOUN PHRASE

Let us assume that rationale clauses are licensed by a relation R b etween

the matrix and sub ordinate situations where the interpretation of R

is the purp ose of is Where the sub ject of the rationale clause is

PRO though R is sub ject to a condition on control Where the matrix

situation is an action as opp osed to a state there must b e an agent and

it must control the lower PRO Where the matrix situation is stative on

the other hand this is not the case

Roses are thornyPRO to protect them from gardeners

i i

Not only is there no agent but the sole argument roses also do es not

control PRO if we claimed that roses controlled PRO then wewould have

a Principle B violation b etween PRO and them

In these cases as observed by Lasnik it do es not app ear that

PRO has an arbitrary interpretation Rather the controller app ears to b e

the matrix situation Thus means that the fact of roses b eing thorny

protects them from gardeners

It is not necessary that the situation b e the controller in statives how

ever Consider

Sharks are streamlined PRO to cut through the water b etter

Here sharks is the controller situations in particular that of sharks b eing

streamlined cannot cut through water

The prop er generalization app ears to b e this with a matrix action

a stative situation there must b e an agent and it must control

the rationale clause With a matrix state a stative situation any

argument including the situation itself may b e the controller

This predicts contrary to Ro ep er that rationale clauses should in fact

b e p ossible with middles if middles can b e made stative This can b e

accomplished by making the matrix sentence generic

Continents sink PRO to replenish the earths supply of magma

The distinction b etween this example and Ro ep ers ungrammatical the

boat sank to prove a point Ro ep er exa is that the matrix sentence

in Ro ep ers example describ es an individual event hence is stative and

thus an agent is required

Finally Ro ep er notes that in contrast to passive in nominals and mid

dles passive in the sentence do es not nullify rationaleclause licensing

The b oat was sunk to collect the insurance

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Ro ep er argues that the Agent role is in fact syntactically realized on the

passive morphologyBaker Johnson and Rob erts prop ose that the

passive morpheme en behaves like a sub ject clitic Alternativelywe can

analyze this implicit argumentasa PROaswell if we adopt a biclausal

analysis of passive roughly

the boat was PROi en VP sink t PROi to collect the

Ag insurance

The matrix PRO or the en under the Baker Johnson Rob erts

prop osal b ears the agent role and licenses the rationale clause In nom

inals and middles the morphology is absent hence the emb edded passive

clause with its PRO is absent the Agent role cannot b e assigned and

the rationale clause is not licensed

the boat s D NP destruction t to collect the insurance

The long and short of this discussion is that when restricted to stative

cases Ro ep ers original observation still holds rationale clauses require

a syntactical lyrealized controlling agent argument to b e licensed PRO

provides such a controller in the nominal though not in the passive

nominal where PRO is displaced by the fronted ob ject

Control Theory

A second argument that has b een forwarded in favor of a PRO in sub ject

of the noun phrase is provided by control theory Consider

Any attempt PROtoleave

The desire PRO to succeed

In the rst example the attempter is necessarily the same as the leaver

and mutatis mutandis for the second example This is explained if we

assume that a conguration of obligatory control is involved and that there

is a PRO sub ject of attempt desire

A problem is that similar facts arise even where control cannot b e in

volved For example in an attemptedescape the attempter is necessarily

the escap er but wewould not wish to say there is a control relation b e

tween twoPRO sub jects Apparently there is a purely semantic control

phenomenon following from the meaning of attempt

PRO IN THE NOUN PHRASE

Binding theory

Binding theory also provides arguments for the existence of PRO in the

noun phrase The simplest examples are the following

a pictures of themselves b other the men

b criticism of oneself is necessary in mo deration

The anaphors themselves oneself lackovert antecedents Principle A in

sists that a lo cal antecedent exist therefore it must b e nonovert A PRO

sub ject of noun phrase is by far the most likely candidate

There is an alternative explanation one might suggest for a Con

sider

a pictures of each other were given t to the men

d Igave pictures of each other to the men

Supp ose that the men ccommands each other in b Principle A is sat

ised in the normal wayeven without a PROinpictures of each otherIf

we assume that binding theory is applied to a conguration in which noun

phrases are at least optionally reconstructed into their dstructure p osi

tions a is grammatical b ecause it is identical to b at the relevant

level of representation In like manner we might explain the grammatical

ity of a by assuming that the dstructure is in fact

e b other the men pictures of each other

This explanation do es not extend to b however thus b remains as

evidence for a nounphrase PRO

Parallel to b are examples like

PRO criticism of them

i i

where the criticisers cannot b e them This can b e accounted for as a

Principle B violation if there is a PRO sub ject of criticism

Further examples are due to Ross

a PRO the realization that he has broken the law

i i

b PRO the realization that John has broken the law

i

ji

In a the realizer can b e he In b on the other hand the realizer

cannot b e Johnbutmust b e someone else This is explicable as a Principle

C violation assuming there is a PRO present

It is also p ossible to construct violations of Strong Crossover though

the judgments are rather subtle Consider the following two discourses

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

John won in small claims court

The judge b elieved PRO the assertion that Bill cheated him

i i

I cant remember who it was who won in small claims court

Who did the judge b elievePRO the assertion that Bill cheated

i

ji

t

In it is p ossible that John is sp eaking for himself that he is the

asserter In it do es not seem that the sp eaker can b e assuming that

the asserter and the cheated were the same p erson whose identity is under

question There is a mild CNPC violation in making it less than fully

grammatical but that is irrelevant to the p oint under discussion

Again consider these examples from Chomsky b

a They heard stories ab out each other

i i

b They heard PRO stories ab out them

i i

c They told stories ab out each other

i i

d They told PRO stories ab out them

i i

Assuming Chomskys binding theory the judgements are as would b e ex

p ected except for the b sentence They told stories about them Since

the whole sentence is the governing category for themwewould exp ect a

violation of Condition B just as in d On the other hand if PRO option

ally app ears in the noun phrase the noun phrase b ecomes the governing

categoryThus sentence b b ecomes acceptable where PRO is not coin

dexed with them And in fact the only interpretation available is one in

which they heard someone elses stories ab out them In sentence d on

the other hand the PROmust b e coindexed with the sub ject hence with

them b ecause of the meaning of tel lThus d cannot b e saved byallowing

the optional PRO to app ear

This argument is actually not consistent with an earlier argument at

least on the face of it It is crucial to the argument from paradigm

that PRObeoptionalIfPRO is optional however then we lose our earlier

explanation of why they cannot b e the criticisers in criticism of them I will

not pursue the issue here b eyond suggesting that it mayberelevant that

criticism is a derived nominal while story is not Perhaps PRO is required

with criticism to receive the external role but not with story b ecause

story is not deverbal hence lacks a grid Story can acquire an external

role by a kind of backformation pro cess treating it as if it were deverbal This pro cess is presumably optional and somewhat marginal

PRO IN THE NOUN PHRASE

Arguments Against PRO in the Noun Phrase

a Yesterdays Destruction

Williams presents several arguments against having PRO in the noun

phrase One argument is that in the noun phrase temp oral adjuncts can ll

the sub ject p osition under certain circumstances When they do so they

presumably displace PRO yet rationale clauses are still licensed indicating

that the licensing of rationale clauses is not evidence for the presence of

PRO after all

yesterdays D destruction of the ship to collect the insurance

AGR

Iwould like to claim that PRO is in fact present in that the

structure is

DP

DP KP D

PRO yesterdays D NP

AGR destruction of the ship

Poss

Ag

Let us supp ose that PRO only counts as governed when it participates

in some relation with a governor In D Caseassigns and assigns

AGR

yesterday but it has no relation to PRO hence do es not govern PRO In

this crucially diers from



I assume that yesterday receives the p ossessor role from D is interpreted

AGR

as the destruction b elonging to yesterday the destruction of yesterday This highly

abstract sense of p ossession app ears to b e well within the range of asso ciations that

qualify as p ossession the range of relations qualifying as p ossession is notoriously broad

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

DP

PRO D

D NP

AGR book

Poss

In PROis assigned byD hence governed In PRO has no

AGR

relationtoD PROis assigned byNP receiving the external role

AGR

of destruction and of course PRO requires no Case NP do es not qualify

as a governor b eing a maximal pro jection else PROwould b e governed

by VP in innitives as well

b Obligatoriness of Control

The ma jor argument against having a PRO in the noun phrase is that the

PRO in the noun phrase diers from sentential PRO in its prop erties as

acontrollee PROinthesentence must usually b e controlled otherwise it

must b e arbPRO in the noun phrase on the other hand may b e b oth non

controlled and nonarbitrary ie nongeneric Consider these examples

from Williams l

a The leaves should not b e b othered while PRO dessicating

i i

b The leaves should not b e b othered during PRO dessication

i i

a You should not b other the leaves while PRO dessicating

i i

b You should not b other the leaves during PRO dessication

i i

The PRO of the gerund must b e coreferential with the surfacestructure

sub ject This provides strong evidence that it in fact exists The PRO

of the noun phrase on the other hand is not sub ject to this restriction It

do es not require an antecedentatall

You should not enter the chamb er during PRO detoxication of

i j

the samples

vs You should not enter the chamb er while PRO detoxifying the

i j samples

PRO IN THE NOUN PHRASE

If there were actually a PRO in the noun phrase one would exp ect it to

b ehave likePRO in the sentence Since PRO in the sentence cannot takea

discourse antecedent this suggests that PRO in the noun phrase either

do es not exist or is not PRO

Wasow and Ro ep er also note the obligatoriness of control into

sentences but not into noun phrases They compare dierent kinds of

gerunds Consider

a I detest PRO loud singing

i j N

b I detest PRO singing loudly

i j V

a John enjoyed PRO a reading of The Bald Soprano

i j N

b John enjoyed PRO reading The Bald Soprano

i j V

a PRO sightings of UFOs makeMary nervous

j N i

b PRO sighting UFOs makes Mary nervous

j V i

a PRO the killing of his dog upset John

j N i

b PRO killing his dog upset John

j V i

All the verbal gerunds are go o d with coreference The nouns vary a is

bad the others are relatively acceptable

One p ossible explanation for these facts is the following It is prop osed

in Williams that control is not a direct relation b etween an antecedent

and PRO but is actually a relation b etween an antecedent and the clause

of whichPRO is sub ject and only indirectly a relation b etween antecedent

and PRO This would p ermit us to make a distinction b etween PROinthe

noun phrase and PRO in sentences if we supp ose that sentences are sub ject

to control but noun phrases are not The apparent dierence b etween

PRO in sentences and PRO in noun phrases with regard to obligatoriness

of control is actually a dierence in the ability of the phrase containing

PROtobecontrolled

A distinction in control prop erties dep ending on the nature of the phrase

of whichPRO is sub ject seems to me very reasonable Wemust b e careful

in howwe sp ell it out though Anticipating results of Chapter Three I

assume that PROing and Ingof gerunds are not distinct in syntactic

category b oth are noun phrases But they are distinct in their control

prop erties as wesawabove PROing patterning with innitives and Ing

of patterning with noun phrases This is a ticklish problem to whichI

return in section I I I For now it must remain outstanding

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

In conclusion the DPanalysis provides ro om for a PRO in the noun

phrase and there is evidence that suchaPRO exists At present the evi

dence is somewhat mixed b ecause of the dierences in control prop erties of

nounphrase PRO and sentence PRO but if the prop osal proves defensible

that these dierences trace to dierences in the phrase containing PRO

rather than to PRO itself the ma jor disadvantage of p ostulating a PROin

the noun phrase will have b een removed

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Dierences Between Noun Phrase and Sentence

The theme of this chapter has b een the similarities b etween noun phrase

and sentence particularly those nounphrasesentence similarities which

provide evidence for the parallelism of nounphrase and sentence structure

p ostulated under the DPanalysis However there are also substantial dif

ferences b etween noun phrase and sentence This leads to understandable

skepticism of the DPanalysis which could well app ear susceptible to the

charge that it is motivated by a handful of similarities only at the exp ense

of ignoring a much larger b o dy of dierences In this section I defend the

DPanalysis against this accusation I present a long list of sentencenoun

phrase dissimilarities to show that none of them seriously challenge the

DPanalysis The ma jority clearly are concerned only with the relation

between the noun and its complements the remainder arguably so

Before I catalog these dierences though I consider one alleged dier

ence that clearly do es concern the structure of the noun phrase sp ecier

not its complements namely the alleged lack of predication in the noun

phrase

Predication in the Noun Phrase

It has b een claimed that there is no predication in the noun phrase Williams

N do es not predicate of an external and Rothstein claim that

argument as it is a nonmaximal category and only maximal categories

are syntactic predicates Consider the following examples

a I consider John a go o d lawyer

b Isaw Johns lawyer

a involves a small clause in which agood lawyer is the predicate and John

is the sub ject This small clause corresp onds in meaning to the full clause

John is a good lawyer in which agood lawyer is likewise predicated of John

Now consider b If there were predication b etween the N lawyer and the

sub ject Johnwewould exp ect the sense John is a lawyer But b

do es not presupp ose that John is a lawyer rather that there is someone

who is a lawyer with whom John is asso ciated probably as client That

b do es not have a reading in which John is the lawyer is attributed to

alack of predication b etween Nbar and p ossessor

These facts app ear in quite a dierent light however if we take seri

ously the idea that verbs denote situations If verbs denote situations the

predication involved in a is clearly dierent from predication b etween

a VP and its sub ject as in John leftInJohn left the VP denotes an event

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

of leaving and its sub ject is identied with some role dened bythatevent

in this case the leaver In Iconsider John a good lawyer on the other

hand the predicational noun phrase denotes a lawyer and the sub ject is

identied with the lawyer not with some role dened relativetoalawyer

To bring home the p oint let us consider the examples

Caesar destroyed the city

Caesars destruction of the city

Mo difying assumptions of Higginb otham let us take the denotation

of the VP destroy the city to b e the oneplace predicate

exy cityy destroy eR x e R y e

where DESTROY is a oneplace predicate true of exactly the acts of de

struction R is an Agent relation and R is a Patient relation The relation

between this predicate and the denotation of the sub ject Caesar is not one

of semantic predication rather Caesar lls one of the roles asso ciated with

DESTROY namely R of More precisely xx Caesar is added

as a restriction on one of the existential quantiers assuming that In

serves to existentially bind the lamb daabstracted variable e of the

denotation of the IP Caesar destroyed the city is the following

ex x Caesary cityy destroy eR x eR y e

Iwould like to argue that the semantics for destruction is exactly par

allel Recall that the syntactic structure I assume for Caesars destruction

of the city is



Or some platonic ideal of a lawyer an abstract essential lawyer For the sake

of concreteness let us assume with Montague that individuals are sets of prop erties

or functions from prop erties to p ossible worlds if wetakeintensionalityinto account

Then the predicational noun phrase a lawyer can b e taken to denote the set containing

only the prop erty of b eing a lawyer an archiindividual The predicate is identied

with of the next phrase in the text should then b e understo o d as includes



Or to b e consistent with the previous fo otnote we could take it to denote the

singleton set containing the prop erty corresp onding to this predicate

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

DP

KP D

Caesars D NP

N PP

destruction of the city

The NP destruction of the city I claim is semantically identical to the

verb phrase destroy the city Its translation is In DP the variable e

is b ound by D in the same way that In binds the ep osition in VP and

there is a syntactic relation of Predication b etween the maximal pro jection

NP and its sub ject Caesar whichisinterpreted just like the syntactic

relation of Predication b etween VP and its sub ject namely not as semantic

predication but as the lling of an argumentslot by restricting a variable

ex x Caesary cityy destroy eR x e R y e

If this account is correct then there is in fact predication within the

noun phrase and the relation b etween John and a lawyer in Iconsider

John a lawyer is not predication at all but identication If predication

were involved in small clauses headed by noun phrases wewould exp ect

eg Iconsider John an expression of grief to b e synonymous with

SC DP

Iconsider John to have expressed grief but of course it is not

IP VP

I should add though that I do not wish to imply that NP always

predicates of the sub ject of DPI have already stated explicitly that I take

the p ossessive role to b e assigned by D not to b e an external role

of NP assigned via predication Thus Johns expression of grief and Johns

puzzled expression dier in the way John acquires a role there is syntactic

predication by NP in the former but not in the latter

Two more arguments Rothstein gives against predication in the

noun phrase are the optionality of the sub ject in the noun phrase and

the lack of pleonastics in the noun phrase The paradigm is

illustrative



More precisely the denotation of John is taken to include b e a sup erset of the

denotation of a lawyer where the denotation of John is the set of Johns prop erties

and the denotation of a lawyer is the set containing the sole prop ertylawyerho o d Cf fo otnote

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

a destroyed the city

the destruction of the city

b it is likely that John will leave

its likeliho o d that John will leave

The generalization is not quite noun phrase vs sentence however at

least not if Possing gerunds are noun phrases as is widely accepted and

as I argue in the next chapter Pleonastics are p ermitted in b oth Accing

and Possing gerunds

a I approve of there b eing a literacy exam for p olitical candi

dates

Iwas worried ab out it b eing to o obvious that Charlie was lying

b Iwas worried ab out its b eing to o obvious that Charlie was

lying

The sub ject of gerunds is also obligatory If it is not overt there must

be a PRO present as illustrated bythecontrast from Williams

cited earlier

a The leaves should not b e disturb ed while PRO dessicating

b The leaves should not b e disturb ed during dessication

Whether there is a PRO in b is immaterial here What is imp ortant

is that the obligatorily agentcontrolled reading of the adjunct in a

indicatesthataPRO is indeed present

In short in some noun phrases namely gerunds the sub ject is oblig

atory and pleonastics are allowed These are precisely the noun phrases

in which a VP app ears in place of an NP under the analysis of gerunds I

sketched in the intro duction

Under the DPanalysis then the generalization is that VP requires a

sub ject to predicate of whereas NP is capable of predicating of a sub ject



Possing with there is illformed but it is generally agreed that this is due to ex

traneous factors This is esp ecially likely in light of the wellformedness of the there

example in a p erhaps it has to do with the fact that there b ears an inherent case

in its adverbial function which clashes with genitive case cf

i a yesterdays party

b thens party

nows party

heres party

theres party

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

but do es not require a sub ject PRO is obligatory only where predication is

obligatory and pleonastics are p ermitted only where predication is oblig

atory This commits us to a weaker p osition than Rothsteins namely

that syntactic predicates do not always require sub jects only verbal syn

tactic predicates do This revision of Rothsteins claim seems reasonable

esp ecially in light of the fact that with regard to other forms of argument

takingeg internal assignmentverbs demand their arguments to b e

syntactically presentinaway that nouns do not The only nouns whose

arguments are not freely deletable are derived nominals and if Leb eaux

claims are correct derived nominals are not nouns at LF but verbs

They are certainly atypical nouns on anyones account Wemay claim

then that syntactic arguments of verbs b oth arguments and predication

arguments are obligatory while those of nouns are in general optional

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Catalog of Dierences

In this section I give a fairly exhaustive list of the constructions found in

the sentence which are not found in the noun phrase Many of these facts

are old observations some as far as I know have not b een noted previously

in the literature The purp ose of presenting this catalog of dierences is

to show that they do not call into question the parallelism b etween noun

phrase and sentence structure p ostulated under the DPanalysis The DP

analysis p ostulates similar sp ecier structures for noun phrase and sentence

most of the dierences listed here have clearly to do with noun complement

structure as it contrasts with verb complement structure I do not attempt

to give detailed analyses of all these constructions however doing so would

b e a thesis in itself I only wish to show that the fact of these dierences is

not problematic for the DPanalysis

a A Preliminary Pro cess vs Result

In examining the dierences b etween sentence and noun phrase we will have

frequent cause to compare derived nominals with the verbs from which they

derive In doing so it is crucial to make a distinction which is to o frequently

not made in the literature on derived nominals namelybetween pro cess

nominals and result nominals Pro cess nominals denote actionsevents

and result nominals denote ob jects Consistentlythe grid of the verb

is preserved only in pro cess nominals not result nominals Result nominals

mayhave PP complements that app ear to corresp ond to arguments of the

verb but they are never obligatory and frequently show other indications

of b eing mo diers not arguments This is most clearly seen with derived

nominals that have b oth result and pro cess readings suchasexamination

a examination of the students will take several hours

examination will takeseveral hours

b the examination of the students was printed on pink pap er

the examination was printed on pink pap er

Examination in a denotes an action whereas examination in b

denotes a concrete ob ject Though the ob ject is illformed with the result

nominal here this is not always the case

a a reconstruction of the events will take a long time

a reconstruction will take a long time



Result nominal is something of a misnomer in that result nominals do not always

denote the result of the action of the verbthough that is a often the case Following

Grimshaw I use the term in a extended sense to cover all nominals that denote

ob jects concrete or abstract instead of events

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

b Johns reconstruction of a thcentury French village was de

stroyed in the re adapted from Anderson

Johns reconstruction was destroyed in the re

It is not always a trivial task to determine whether one is dealing with

a pro cess nominal or a result nominal in a given example There are a

numb er of diagnostics that are helpful if not fo olpro of These are collected

in Grimshaw

Process nominals do not pluralize Thus the clipping of the grass is

a pro cess nominal but in the plural the clippings it can only b e a

result nominal

Process nominals do not occur with demonstrative determiners Thus

that examination of the students occuredaweek ago is distinctly o dd

whereas that examination is twenty pages long is ne

Result nominals often require a determiner Consider examination

p

was ten pages long but examination of the students took ten hours

Process nominals do not occur with of NPs The adjunct of NPs only

has a concretep ossess ion reading which is incompatible with events

the discovery of the vaccines occuredatanopportune momentcf

the vaccines discovery occured at an opportune moment

The distinction b etween pro cess and result nominals is made clearly in

Anderson and Grimshaw but it is much more often completely ignored

with the result that many of the arguments in the literature concerning

derived nominals are compromised Two examples o ccur esp ecially fre

quently Johns belief to be intel ligent is rep eatedly cited as an illustration

that there is no raising in the noun phrase and Johns gift of Mary of a

b o ok is cited to show that there is no dative shift in the noun phrase Nei

ther of these examples quite illustrate the intended p oint however Both

belief and gift are result nominals not pro cess nominals Belief do es not

preserve the argument structure of the verb

John b elieved the story

Johns b elief of the story

And gift obviously denotes the ob ject given it cannot denote the act of

giving

Johns gift of a Rembrandt to the Fogg to ok place yesterday

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

What confuses matters somewhat is that belief and gift do take argu

ments that app ear to corresp ond to verbal arguments

a the b elief that John was intelligent

b the gift of a b o ok to Mary

These arguments in fact fall under a nominal paradigm however Result

nominals fail to preserve the grid of the verb from whichtheywere de

rived but they may take mo diers like those of similar concrete nouns

this is one factor whichcontributes to diculty at times in distinguishing

pro cess and result nominals Belief patterns with nonderived nouns like

theory

the b elief that John was intelligent

the theory that John was intelligent

Gifts arguments pattern with two dierent sets of nonderived nouns The

gift of a book has the argumentstructure of nouns like tribute honorarium

agiftofabook

an honorarium of a goldinlaid plaque

ayearly tribute of a horse

AgifttoMaryhas the argumentstructure of nonderived nouns like present

letter

a gift to Mary

a presenttoMary

a letter to Mary

In short one must b e careful to distinguish b etween arguments that pattern

with nominal paradigms and those inherited from ro ot verbs Only pro cess

nominalsnominals that denote eventspreservethe grid of the ro ot

verb

Two closing notes rst Belief and gift are typical of a large class of

derived nouns whichhave only result readings namely zeroderived nouns

Often zeroderived nouns do not take mo diers whicheven app ear to cor

resp ond to verbal direct ob jects

a hit of the ball

Johns kickofthedog

the slap of the little brat

Marys frightofBill

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Even when zeroderived nouns take ofcomplements they consistently meet

diagnostics for b eing result not pro cess nominals

a Johns fear of water

Johns fear

Johns fears of failure

b a smear of paint

asmear

several smears of paint

It is also usually clear that the nominal do es not denote an action but

an ob jectthough esp ecially with nouns of mental state it is all but im

p ossible to distinguish b etween the action denoted by the verb and the

mental state denoted by the result nominal For example it is dicult to

distinguish b etween the action of fearing something and the mental state

of fear

Second derived nominals in ing often b ehave dierently from other

derived nominals The two most salient dierences are that nominals in

ing never allow passive and they do allow particles

a the b ombing of the city

the destruction of the city

the citys b ombing

the citys destruction

b the explaining away of the problem

the explanation away of the problem

Because of these facts zeroderived nominals and nominals in ing are

b est avoided in making generalizations ab out the relation b etween derived

nominals and the verbs they derive from The b est nominals to study are

axally derivedusually latinateand clearly denote actions not ob jects

With this in mind I turn to an examination of the dierences b etween

noun phrase and sentence



As p ointed out to me byRKayne there is at least one apparently zeroderived

nominal which denotes an action and otherwise app ears to b e a pro cess nominal namely

capture I submit however that capture is analyzed as a cranb erry word derived

axally from the stem capt from which are also derived captor captive Capture thus

actually patterns with failure seizure not with zeroderived nominals which are almost

always AngloSaxon

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

b Obligatoriness of Subject

The sub ject is obligatory in the sentence but not in the noun phrase

destroyed the city

destruction of the city

c Pleonastics

When there is no genuine sub ject in the sentence a pleonastic sub ject is

inserted This option is not available in the noun phrase

a there arrivedaman

theres arrival of a man

b it was proven that the earth is round

its pro of that the earth is round

These two facts do clearly concern the sp ecier of the noun phrase not

the complement But it app ears that a reasonable account can b e given

under the DPanalysis as sketched at the end of the previous section I

have nothing to add to my discussion there

d Case

Nouns do not Caseassign their ob jects hence they may not app ear with

barenounphrase complements unlike their verbal counterparts

a Caesar destroyed the city

b Caesars destruction the city

It is usually claimed that b is a wellformed dstructure and that it is

saved by a rule of ofinsertion which applies to yield the wellformed

sstructure Caesars destruction of the city Alternativelywemaytake of

to b e a Casemarker K rather as we argued for s Probably we should

distinguish the Case marked by s and the Case marked by of I will call

the former genitive and the latter though with the caveat

that what I mean by partitive is precisely the Case marked by of

genitive and genitive would p erhaps b e b etter in b eing more neutral

but they would b e harder to keep straight The noun assigns partitive Case

D assigns genitive Case A KP generated in the ob ject p osition of a

AGR

noun can b e headed by either a partitive or genitive casemarker the Case

it is actually assigned must agree with the Case marked however which

requires it to raise to a p osition of genitive Case assignmentifitshows

genitive marking

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

e Restrictions on Passive

There is a nounphrase equivalent of passive as wehave noted There

are additional restrictions on this movement however b eyond those found

in the sentence Consider the following examples adapted from examples

noted by Mona Anderson

a Iknow algebra

Algebra is known by many p eople

Icontemplated the days events

The days events should b e contemplated b efore sleeping

b knowledge of algebra

algebras knowledge

contemplation of recentevents

recentevents contemplation

The accountgiven by Andersonthe only accountgiven to dateis that

what is involved is an Aectedness Constraint on sub categorization frames

whereby only nouns denoting actions which aect the denotata of the

nouns ob jects can b e sub categorized for a barenounphrase ob ject Non

aective nouns can b e sub categorized only for genuine ie dstructure

ofPPs Since only bare noun phrases and not PPs can undergo passive

passive can only o ccur with aective nouns If this account is correct it

lo cates the dierence in the complement structure of nouns

It is not entirely clear that the Aectedness Constraint really constitutes

a dierence b etween noun phrase and sentence There are after all verbs

which do not p ermit passive resemble weigh cost Itisinteresting that

none of the nominalizations of these verbs take ob jects

a John weighed p ounds

p ounds were weighed byJohn

Johns weighingweight of p ounds

b John resembles his father

his father is resembled byJohn

Johns resemblingresemblance of his father



It is not entirely clear that know ledge is a pro cess nominal Because of its Anglo

Saxon origins and its similarity to clear result nominals like fear it is arguable that

algebras know ledge is out b ecause know ledge is a result nominal This would make of

algebra a PPmo dier not a direct ob ject of know ledge A similar argument cannot b e

brought against contemplationhowever so the paradigm stands

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

c That b o ok costs

are cost bythatbook

That b o oks costingcost of

Iwould like to suggest that the ob jects of weigh etc are not direct ob jects

but measure adjuncts whichhave to some extent b een made into arguments

at least in that they are obligatoryWe can either supp ose that they dier

from true arguments thematically or Casetheoretically let us call them

simply oblique arguments without deciding whether oblique is to b e

dened as b earer of oblique role or b earer of oblique Case The

generalization then is that oblique arguments cannot b e passivized and

ob jects of nominals cannot corresp ond to oblique arguments of verbs

f Psych Nouns

A class of derived nominals which consistently fail to take ob jects are the

psych nouns

a Mary frightened John

Mary amused John

Mary angered John

Mary b ored John

Mary liked John

Mary hated John

b Marys fright of John

Marys amusementofJohn

Marys anger of John

Marys b oredom of John

Marys like of John

Marys hate of John

The reason however is obviously that all the examples in b are result

nominals All but two are zeroderived and the axal examples amuse

ment and boredom clearly refer to mental states not acts amusement

cannot refer to the act of amusing someone and boredom cannot refer to

the act of b oring someone The question is then why no pro cess psych nom

inals exist If any class of nouns is to fail to have pro cess nominalizations

wewould exp ect it to b e nouns of mental state inasmuch as their thematic

structure is so very unlike the canonical AgentPatient structure In fact if

we consider ing nominals the examples of divide into a hierarchyof

wellformedness when an of ob ject is present roughly the verbs with the

greatest element of causation are most grammatical

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

c Marys frightening of John

Marys angering of John

Marys amusing of John

Marys b oring of John

Marys liking of John

Marys hating of John

And if we consider examples like tempt or realize that havetwo readings

one one stativewe nd only the causative reading in the pro

cess nominal

a I can tell that cake is tempting John

the devil tempted Jesus

b the cakes temptation of John

the devils temptation of Jesus

a John realized his mistake

John realized his fondest dreams

b Johns realization of his mistake

Johns realization of his fondest dreams

In short it app ears that pro cess nominals can only b e built on verb

meanings that include an element of agentivity not on purely stativeverb

meanings Purely stativeverb meanings yield stative nominals which are

uniformly result nominals

Possibly this generalization subsumes the Aectedness Constraint Con

sider an example like fear of cats Fear is obviously a result nominal so

wemust take of cats to b e a PP mo dier that expresses as it were the

content or sub ject matter of the mental state of fear This presents

the p ossibility of analyzing know ledge of language in the same way know l

edge is a result nominal and of language is a PP mo dier sp ecifying the

content or sub ject matter of the mental state of knowing Thus lan

guages know ledge is out b ecause language is not an argumentbutamod

ifer of know ledge hence cannot passivize mutatis mutandis for the pro

posals contemplation The ob ject of know ledge or contemplation is freely

deletable which is consistent with their b eing result nominals



However know ledge and contemplation do seem to dier when they are denite

i a the knowledge of his imp ending do om frightened him

the knowledge frightened him

b the contemplation of his imp ending do om frightened him

the contemplation frightened him

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

a knowledge of language makes man man

knowledge makes man man

b hes busy with contemplation of the prop osal

hes busy with contemplation

Atany rate it seems clear that the question hinges on dierences in the

thematic structures of nouns and verbs and is not relevant to the question

of the structure of the noun phrase sp ecier

g Raising

Raising ie Raising to Sub ject is p ossible in the sentence but not in the

noun phrase

a John app eared to haveleft

John was b elieved to b e intelligent

John was likely to win

b Johns app earance to have left

Johns b elief to b e intelligent

Johns likeliho o d to win

I will discuss these facts together with those in the next two paragraphs

h Exceptional Case Marking

Exceptional Case Marking Raising to Ob ject is found in the sentence but

not in the noun phrase

a I b elieved John to b e intelligent

I exp ected John to win

b My b elief John to b e intelligent

My exp ectationexp ectancy John to win

An alternativeway to Casemark ob jects of nouns is via ofinsertion

but this course is also unavailable for the noun phrases of b

My b elief of John to b e intelligent

My exp ectation of John to win

There is also a contrast with the passivization facts if we use pronouns instead of

full noun phrases as p ointed out to me byRKayne its contemplation ie of his

imp ending do om its know ledge A more systematic investigation is called for

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

It should b e p ointed out that my belief of John and my expectation of

p p

John are also illformed contra Ibelieve John I expected JohnLikewise

Johns belief t etc corresp onding to Johns belief to be intel ligent though

p

John was believed This suggests that whatever is wrong with eg Johns

belief to be intel ligent is the same thing as is wrong with the simpler Johns

belief t and has nothing to do with raising A ready suggestion is that the

illformedness of Johns belief t has the same source as the illformedness

of algebras know ledge tWe could claim that John in Ibelieve John is

not an argument but an oblique adjunct Actuallywemust group belief

with weightnotknow ledge Bil ls weight of the package Bil ls belief

p

of John Bil ls know ledge of algebra However this would not explain

why Johns belief to be intel ligent is illformed whatever prevents oblique

noun phrases from passivizing Case clash p erhaps should not prevent

the argument John in John to be intel ligent from moving to Sp ec of D and

receiving genitive Case

The prop er generalization I b elieve is that nouns cannot take reduced

clause complements but only full CP complements If nouns are incapable

of licensing bareIP complements then the noun would b e incapable of

governing the sub ject of the lower clause hence incapable of Caseassigning

it accounting for the lack of ECM Likewise a raised sub ject would b e

incapable of governing its trace whichwould thus violate the ECP

I will p ostp one discussion of why nouns should b e incapable of tak

ing reducedclause complements until I have presented the numerous other

nounphrasesentence dierences that fall under the same generalization

Note though that if the dierence is in the sub categorizationselectional

prop erties of nouns and verbs as I claim then we do not need to assume

dierences in the landing sites of Amovementie the structure of the

sp ecierof noun phrases and sentences

i Small Clauses

Another reduced clause which nouns do not take are small clausesthough

the unavailability of raising and Exceptional Case Marking are sucientin

themselves to preclude anywellformed small clause structure in the noun

phrase

a I b elieveJohnafool

I exp ect John in my oce

b my b elief John a fo ol

my exp ectation John in my oce

c my b elief of John a fo ol

my exp ectation of John in my oce

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

a John was b elieved a fo ol

John was exp ected in my oce

b Johns b elief a fo ol

Johns exp ectation in my oce

j Ditransitivity

There are no ditransitive nouns Dative Shift

a Igave Bill a b o ok

Irented Bill a car

I fed the cat dinner

b the rental of Bill of a car

c the giving of Bill of a b o ok

the renting of Bill of a car

the feeding of the cat of dinner

Gift is a result nominal thus the illformedness of the frequentlycited the

gift of Bil l of a car is out for entirely extraneous reasons Rental do es

not app ear to suer from this shortcoming cf my rental of the car took

place a ful l year ago

This fact ts in with b oth generalizations I have put forward to now

the inability of nouns to assign partitive Case ie of to arguments

that receive oblique Case in the VP and the inability of nouns to take

reduced clause complements The lack of ditransitives falls under the latter

generalization if we adopt an analysis in which doubleob ject verbs take

a small clause complement Several such analyses have b een prop osed

including those of Kayne a Larson The lack of ditransitives

falls under the prohibition against oblique arguments if we assume one of

the two arguments is oblique If we consider the contrast the feeding of the

p

cat dinner the feeding of the cat it seems to indicate that the Theme is

the oblique argument it also app ears to indicate that oblique should b e

dened in terms of Caseassignment not assignment inasmuch as there

are many examples with nonoblique Theme arguments eg the sel ling of

the car On the other hand the following alternation indicates that it is

the Goal argumentwhich is oblique

a i I presented the award to John

ii I presented John with the award

b i my presentation of the award to John

ii my presentation of John with the award

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

The Theme is emb edded in a PP in bii hence could not b e the

oending argument

One p ossibility is to assume that feed has two distinct grids in feed

the cat the cat receives the Patient role and in feedthecat dinner the

cat receives the Goal role Then taking oblique to mean Goal would

give the right results Another p ossibility is to followKayne a in

extending the smallclause analysis of ditransitives to present John with

the award

Another example which p ossibly b elongs here is the contrast

a I b elieve the story

I b elieve John

b my b elief of the story

my b elief of John

my belief of the story is not very go o d but it is clearly b etter than when

the sentence with the goal argument is nominalized

k Object Control

Ob ject control constructions do not app ear in the noun phrase

a I p ersuaded John to leave

I instructed John to leave

b my p ersuasion of John to leave

my instruction of John to leave

Other commonlycited examples like my command of John to leave my

order of John to leave are trivially ungrammatical by virtue of involving

zeroderived result nominals

One p ossibility is that these examples fall under the prohibition against

oblique arguments assuming that John is oblique It is true that exam

ples like my persuasion of John are grammatical but wemight argue that

persuasion like feedisambiguous b etween two frames one which is a sim

ple action verb taking a direct ob ject Patient and no ob ject control and

the second which takes an oblique Goal argument and ob ject control

a I p ersuaded John

Pt

I p ersuaded John to leave

Goal

p



One is tempted to cite my instruction to John to leave here but that example is

actually irrelevant b eing clearly a result nominal patterning with my command to John

to leave etc Cf I instructed to John to leave

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

I co erced John

Pt

I co erced John to leave

Goal

b my p ersuasion of John

Pt

my p ersuasion of John to leave

Goal

my co ercion of John

Pt

my co ercion of John to leave

Goal

It is rather dicult to detect much dierence in the meanings of these

pairs however visavis the role of John An alternativeistoappealtothe

prohibition against small clauses and analyze the examples of b as

my p ersuasion of John

my p ersuasion of John PROtoleave

SC CP

my co ercion of John

mycoercion of John PROtoleave

SC CP

l Tough Constructions

Tough constructions are not available in the noun phrase

a John is tough to please

Bill is easy to oend

Mary is pleasanttolookat

b Johns toughness to please

Bills easiness to oend

Marys pleasantness to lo ok at

It is p ossible to assimilate these examples either to the examples involv

ing oblique arguments or to the examples involving semiclauses Let us

consider the former alternativerst

It has b een argued that there is a nonovert b enefactive argumentin

tough constructions whichcontrols the innitival clause corresp onding to

an overt forcontroller as in John is tough for Bil l PRO to please it

i i

is tough for Bil l PRO to please John If this is correct wehavethe

i i

following structure where e is the nonovert controller of PRO

John is tough e OP PRO to please t

j i j i j

If e is syntactically present it is reasonable to consider it an oblique argu

ment as it is a for adjunct when it app ears overtly ie a b enefactive or

ethical dative adjunct

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

A second p ossibility is that tough constructions are actually unaccusative

in particular that John is not assigned by tough but is the sub ject of a

small clause complementof tough

e is tough John OP PROtopleaset

SC i i i

There is some direct evidence in favor of this structure First there is

the fact that wedohavesentences like it is tough to please John that seem

to indicate that the sub ject p osition of tough is not a p osition Further

recall the sentences

a I gave the gun to Mugsy PRO to get rid of it

i j ij

b I gave the gun to Mugsy OP PRO to get rid of t

i j

ij

On the basis of these sentences we argued that a clause must b e in a relation

of mutual ccommand with the antecedents of b oth an empty op erator in

its sp ecier and PRO if its sub ject is PRO The PRO reading is ruled out

i

in b b ecause if the adjunct clause attaches to IP the antecedentof

OP do es not ccommand OP and if the adjunct clause attaches to VP the

adjunct clause do es not ccommand the antecedentofPRO On the PRO

j

reading if the adjunct clause attaches to VP b oth the antecedentofOP

and the antecedentofPRO ccommand the adjunct clause and the adjunct

clause ccommands b oth of them thus the structure is wellformed

If this analysis is correct and if the innitival clause is a complementof

tough in John is tough to please as indicated by the fact that it is selected

by tough cf eg John is necessary to please to see that the innitival

clause indeed sub categorizes the predicate then the innitival clause is

attached under VPandJohn must also originate under VP

If we adopt Belleti Rizzis prop osal that psychverbs are actu

ally doubleob ject unaccusativesie that John feared Mary derives from

efeared Mary Johnwe not only have a precedent for the analysis of

tough movement prop osed here but it also seems p ossible to defend a very

strong thematic restriction on the p osition of arguments at dstructure

namely that arguments are external at dstructure i they b ear an actor

or agent rolecrucially not an exp eriencer role Agent alone

app ears to b e to o strong for cases of simple intransitives like sneeze where

the sub ject is an actor but arguably not an agent

There is actually a third p ossibility that tough nominalizations are

excluded on b oth counts oblique arguments and small clauses Supp ose

that there is an emptycontroller of PRO and that John originates as

sub ject of a small clause

John is tough e t OP PRO to please t

j i SC j j i j

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

The one y in the ointment for all these alternatives is the example Mary

is pretty to look at Unlike Mary is pleasant to look at there is no imp ersonal

version it is pretty to look at Mary and pretty takes no forphrase Mary

is pretty for John to look at My only suggestion is that Mary is pretty to

look at is formed on analogy with sentences built on synonyms of pretty all

of which otherwise t at least halfwayinto the toughconstruction paradigm

the lackoffor adjuncts requires explanation though

a the sun streaming in is b eautiful to lo ok at

the sun streaming in is lovelytolookat

the sun streaming in is gorgeous to b ehold

the sun streaming in is breathtaking to b ehold

the sun streaming in is pleasanttolookat

the sun streaming in is nice to lo ok at

b it is b eautiful to see the sun streaming in

it is lovely to see the sun streaming in

it is gorgeous to see the sun streaming in

it is breathtaking to see the sun streaming in

it is pleasant to see the sun streaming in

it is nice to see the sun streaming in

m Johns breaking his leg

One curious dierence b etween sentence and noun phrase is the p ossibilities

of interpretation in the following pair

a Johns breaking his leg

b Johns breaking of his leg

a can describ e a situation in whichJohnunintentionally breaks his leg the

Exp eriencer reading in b on the other hand the strongly preferred

reading is that in which John intentionally breaks his leg the Agent

reading This is not precisely a dierence b etween sentence and noun

phrase but rather one b etween VP and NPat least under my assumptions

ab out the structure of gerunds

It is p ossible to ascrib e the semantic ambiguityofatoasyntactic

ambiguity Break can b e either an action verb or an exp eriencer verb Under

the agentive reading let us supp ose that break is a simple transitive but

under the exp eriencer reading let us supp ose that break is a doubleob ject

unaccusative Under the latter reading John is nonagentive b ecause it

is underlyingly not a sub ject but an ob ject The contrasting dstructures are

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

a John broke his leg agentive

b e brokeJohnhisleg exp eriencer

b is parallel to the ditransitive structure of give As with give the second

ob ject the displaced direct ob ject cannot b e easily passivized The

book was given Johnlikewise his leg was broken only has the agentive

reading where someone intentionally broke Johns leg

We can then subsume the unavailability of the exp eriencer reading in

the nominal under either the prohibition against obliques or the prohibition

against small clauses as with ditransitives It would fall under the prohi

bition against small clauses if we extended Kaynes or Larsons smallclause

analysis of ditransitives to the structure of b

Striking conrmation for this account comes from West Flemish In

many Germanic languages there is an ethical dative that can b e used

with verbs of acquisition and deprivation In English it is found only with

verbs of acquisition as in Im going to get myself a new TV In German it

is also found with verbs of deprivation

dem Kind ist sein Fahrrad geklaut worden

the childDAT is his bikeNOM stolen b ecome

the childs bikewas stolen

As in English the direct ob ject b ecomes the sub ject In West Flemish how

ever the ethical dative can b ecome the sub ject as discussed by Liliane

Haegeman

Jan is zenen velo gepakt

JanNOM is his bike stolen

Jans bikewas stolen

Haegeman applies a battery of tests which show unambiguously that Jan

is the sub ject not a topic in it agrees with the verb it can b e

replaced with a sub ject clitic etc This example diers from John broke

his arm under the analysis I am prop osing only in that it is passive and

not ergative Haegeman also gives transitive ergative examples

a Jan is zenen oarm gebroken

Jan is his arm broken

Jan brokehisarm

b Jan is zenen inkel verstukt

Jan is his ankle sprained Jan sprained his ankle

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

c Jan is zenen b o ek vergeten

Jan is his b o ok forgotten

Jan forgot his b o ok

Haegeman argues that these are unaccusatives not intransitives b ecause

the auxiliary is to be not to have As such they exactly matchthe

structure I prop ose for John broke his arm and provide striking cross

linguistic evidence supp orting that analysis

n PseudoPassive

Pseudopassive is not available in the noun phrase

a The dispute was settled

A sum was settled on

b The disputes settlement

A sums settlementon

Under usual assumptions the availability of pseudopassive dep ends on the

p ossibility of reanalysis b etween verb and prep osition This is then a third

dierence b etween nouns and verbs nouns do not take oblique ob jects do

not take reduced clause complements and do not reanalyze with prep osi

tions We can make this third prohibition more general if we followBaker

b in taking the reanalysis of pseudopassive to b e in fact prep osition

incorp oration In general it is not p ossible to incorp orate into nouns but

only into verbs Pseudopassive is only a sp ecial case

Whichever analysis wecho ose it seems clear that what is at stake is the

relation b etween the noun and prep osition hence our analysis of sp ecier

structure is not aected

o Particles Particle Movement

Neither particles nor particle movement are p ermitted in noun phrases

a he explaineddened away the problem

he explaineddened the problem away



A question which Haegeman do es not address is the fact that these ergatives are

apparently identical to the structures she called passives earlier The passives dier

from German and Dutch passives in that the past participle of the passive auxiliary to

becomeisabsent I assume that this has brought ab out an accidental similaritybetween

passive and ergative structures Atany rate it is clear that the examples of are

ergativesesp ecially b ecause of example c there is no p ossible source for it as a

passive The only candidate would b e the nonsensical Someone forgot John his book

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

he separated out the impurities

he separated the impurities out

b his explanationdenition away of the problem

his explanationdenition of the problem away

p

cf his explanationdenition of the problem

his separation out of the impurities

his separation of the impurities out

p

cf his separation of the comp onent media

If we followKayne b and Gueron in analyzing particle con

structions as small clauses this fact to o falls under the prohibition against

reduced clause complements of nouns

p Resultative Secondary Predicates

Resultative secondary predicates are not p ermitted in the noun phrase

a Wepainted the house red

We hammered the metal at

We shot him dead

b Our painting the house red

Our hammering the metal at

Our sho oting him dead

c Our painting of the house red

Our hammering of the metal at

Our sho oting of him dead

If we adopt a smallclause analysis of ditransitives it would b e natural

to distinguish resultative from depictive secondary predicates by treating

resultatives as small clause complements and depictives as simple adjuncts



Ihave had to illustrate with gerundive forms b ecause I have b een unable to nd any

verbs which take resultative clauses and yield nominals that take arguments Almost

no latinate verbs take resultative predicates and almost no AngloSaxon verbs which

are also for the most part zeroderived yield nominals that take arguments

i a We injected him dead

We contused him senseless

We extruded the metal round

b Our paint of the house

Our hammer of the metal Our shot of the escap ee

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

wepainted the house red

SC

Mary painted John nude

AP

This would account for the contrasts b etween resultative and depictive sec

ondary predicates resultatives predicate only of ob jects never sub jects

and resultatives apparently sub categorize the matrix verb only a restricted

class of verbs take resultative secondary predicates Depictives on the other

hand can predicate of sub jects as well as ob jects and app ear much more

freely with nearly anyverb would b e no more dicult to inter

pret than ditransitives under a small clause analysis It would dier from

ditransitives in fact only in having an understo o d come to b e instead

of come to have in the small clause We gave John a book would b e

interpreted roughly as wewere the agents of an act of giving whose cau

sandum was that John should come to have a b o ok and we painted the

house red would b e roughly wewere the agents of an act of painting

whose causandum was that the house should come to b e red

q Object Pleonastics

Pleonastics do not app ear exclusively in sub ject p osition There are some

ob ject pleonastics in English and they are plentiful in other languages

such as German They do not app ear in the noun phrase however

a I hate it when it snows on myFrench toast

I lose it whenever she lo oks at me that way

I cant b elieve it that youvenever listened to Twisted Sister

b my hatred of it when it snows on myFrench toast

my loss of it whenever she lo oks at me that way

my disb elief of it that that youvenever listened to Twisted

Sister

r Concealed Questions

Concealed questions are not available in the noun phrase

a I considered your oer

I considered sab otage



Consider for instance the contrast i

i John drank himself silly

i i

John drank whisky silly

i i

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

I knew the facts

I knew the time

b my consideration of your oer

my consideration of sab otage

myknowledge of the facts

my knowledge of the time

s Indirect Questions

Over a broad range indirect questions are unavailable in the noun phrase

a Iknow who came

I recollect who came

I determined who came

I rememb er who came

b myknowledge who came

my recollection who came

my determination who came

my remembrance who came

These are all go o d when of is inserted

my knowledge of who came

my recollection of who came

my determination of who came

my remembrance of who came

t Complementizer Deletion

The complementizers that and for can b e deleted in the sentence after

bridge verbs but not in the noun phrase

a Iknow Bill came

I b elieve Bill came

I rememb er Bill came

Id prefer Bill to do it

b myknowledge Bill came

my b elief Bill came

my remembrance Bill came

my preference Bill to do it

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

c myknowledge that Bill came

my b elief that Bill came

myremembrance that Bill came

my preference for Bill to do it

These last four sets of facts ob ject pleonastics concealed questions indi

rect questions thatdeletion I have no analysis of I only note that the

phenomena clearly concern only the complement of the noun not its sp ec

ier

In conclusion I have shownin rather more detail than was probably

necessarythat the many dierences b etween sentences and noun phrases

are dierences in the complements p ermitted by nouns and verbs Three

ma jor generalizations are these verbs but not nouns allow oblique argu

ments verbs but not nouns take reduced clause complements and verbs

but not nouns can b e incorp orated into These dierences do not weigh

against the DPanalysis in that the parallelism b etween noun phrase and

sentence structure envisioned under the DPanalysis centers on the struc

ture of their sp eciers not their complements also b ecause these dierences are for the most part selectional not structural

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

App endix Reducing the Dierences

In this section I would like to indulge in some frankly sp eculative theoriz

ing the aim of which is to reduce the three ma jor dierences b etween noun

and verb identied in the previous section to one overarching dierence

These are the cases we wish to account for

a Johns app earance to have left

b the app earance of John to have left

c my exp ectation of John in my oce

d myrental of Bill a car

myrental of the car

my feeding of the cat dinner

my feeding of the cat

e the presentation of the award to John

the presentation of John with the award

f my p ersuasion of John to leave

my p ersuasion of John

g Johns toughness to please

h Johns breaking of his leg under Exp eriencer reading

i a sums settlementon

j the explanation away of the problem

the explanation of the problem away

k the sho oting of John dead

l myamusement of the children

Let us set aside i for the moment and consider the remaining cases

which fall under the prohibition against direct oblique arguments and the

prohibition against reduced clauses It seems that the cases p otentially ex

plicable under the prohibition against oblique arguments is a prop er subset

of the cases explicable under the prohibition against reduced clauses All

cases receive at least a p otential account under the prohibition against re

duced clauses but several do not app ear to involve oblique arguments ie



There are six other cases wehave examined but which do not app ear to fall under

our three generalizations hence which are ignored in namely obligatoriness of

sub ject sub ject pleonastics ob ject pleonastics concealed questions emb edded ques

tions and thatdeletion

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

a b c j k and l To substantiate this claim wemust verify

that there are no cases of single oblique arguments ie not in a ditransi

tive construction or a construction otherwise analyzable as a small clause

which are prohibited in the noun phrase The examples that readily spring

to mind are also bad in the sentence hence are irrelevant

the rental of Bill

Goal

but I rented Bill

Goal

the presentation of Bill

Goal

but we presented Bill

Goal

In fact there are cases that wehave already noticed where what is appar

ently a Goal argument is go o d precisely when it o ccurs alone

the feeding of the cat dinner

the feeding of the cat

my p ersuasion of Bill to leave

my p ersuasion of Bill

my instruction of Bill to clean up

my instruction of Bill in the ner p oints of hygiene

A few problematic cases do exist First wehave already noted the con

trast it weighs lbs its weighing of lbs In this case though it

app ears that we are dealing with a constraintabove and b eyond the prohi

bition against oblique arguments Namely lbs cannot passivize in the

sentence whereas the oblique arguments wehave b een concerned with oth

erwise do passivize lbs was weighed by the book John was renteda

p

car A second problematic case is my promising of John cf Ipromised

John John was promised This do es seem to b e a genuine counterexam

ple But since it is the only one I have found I will assume there is some

complicating factor I have not discovered Atworst we could app eal to the

prohibition against oblique arguments for this individual case even if we

reduce it to the prohibition against small clauses in all other cases

Let us b egin with ditransitives It is the Goal argument which receives

the verbs accusative case it is the Goal argument for instance whichmust

app ear adjacent to the verb and it is the Goal argumentwhich passivizes

IgaveJohnabook

I gave a b o ok John

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

John was given a b o ok

a book was given John in American English

Something sp ecial must b e said ab out the way the second argument the

Theme receives Case Baker b suggests that it do es not receive Case

but is identied hence passes the Case lter by incorp orating into the verb

at LF I would like to suggest a mo dication of this account Let us adopt

a smallclause analysis of the doubleob ject construction Further let us

supp ose that there is an abstract X head of the small clause as required

by a strict interpretation of Xbar theory

IP

John VP

V XP

gave DP X

Bill X DP

e a book

Let us supp ose that there is a sp ecial constraint on suchanempty head

namely that it must b e identied by incorp orating into the verb So it is

not the second ob ject which incorp orates into the verb but the empty head

taking the second ob ject as its complement

It is not clear what syntactic category to assign X to I assume that the

second ob ject is licensed by b eing assigned and Caseassigned by X this

makes X app ear to b e a prep osition and the construction in question to b e

an applicative if Baker b is right in analyzing applicatives as cases

of prep ositionincorp oration On the other hand the small clause parallel

suggests treating X as an In Another p ossibilitywould b e that it is a

verb We might treat X as a protoverb that corresp onds to the have

part of the meaning of give and assigns the two roles asso ciated with that

part of the meaning of give namely the Goal Possessor and Theme roles

The verb give is actually the combination VX and do es not corresp ond to

a unique syntactic no de until after incorp oration has o ccured at LF This

explains the obligatoriness of incorp oration X alone is not a word and if

it did not incorp orate it could not b e assigned its lexical prop erties which

it p ossesses only by virtue of b eing a part of the word give

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

This third alternative is indistinguishable for practical purp oses from

the account presented in Larson a Larson assumes verbraising

rather than protoverb incorp oration but otherwise his structure is iden

tical to that of with V substituted for X

IP

John VP

V VP

gave DP V

Bill V DP

t a book

Larson defends this analysis in part by app ealing to a large range of tests

summed up in Barss Lasnik that show that the inner indirect

ob ject is actually higher in the structure than the outer direct ob ject

The smallclause structure is one of the few conceivable analyses for the

doubleob ject construction that has the prop erty that the inner ob ject as

symetrically commands the outer ob ject

Larson prefers a verbraising analysis over an incorp oration analysis in

order to avoid the pitfalls of lexical decomp osition he do es not wish to

rep eat the mistakes of the generativesemanticists in decomp osing give into

cause to come to haveHowever the protoverb approach I am prop os

ing is subtly but fundamentally dierent from lexical decomp osition The

basic problem with the lexicaldecomp osition approachisthatitcannot

account for the idiosyncratic prop erties of give that are not contributed

byany of its comp onents cause cometoorhave My view is that verb

meanings are arranged in an inheritance lattice such that individual verbs

indeed p ossess idiosyncratic prop erties but the prop erties they share with

all other verbs of their class need not b e stated individually for eachverb

but once for the classob ject that represents the entire verb class Agen

tiveverbs for instance all inherit from a classob ject that p ossesses two



Larson also assumes NPs instead of DPs I am glossing over that dierence for

consistencys sake Another wrinkle to Larsons analysis which is not imp ortant for my

purp oses is that he assumes the underlying structure is actually John e a book gave

V

to Bil l and passive applies in the lower VP as wellasverbraising out of the lower

VP to yield the surface order



Inheritance lattices have b een extremely well studied in the articial intelligence

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

or three roles Agent Instrument and Patient Motion verbs inherit

from a classob ject that p ossesses the roles Theme Source Goal It is

these classob jects which I mean when I say protoverb The agentive

verb classob ject is the protoverb with roughly the content of cause the

motionverb classob ject is the protoverb with roughly the content of go

It is imp ortant to understand that these protoverbs or archiverbs are

not the actual verbs cause and go Rather it is convenient to designate

them as cause and go b ecause the agentiveverb classob ject and the

motionverb classob ject are present in purest form in the verbs cause

and go resp ectively cause and go app ear to inherit from the single classes

CAUSE agentive class and GO motion class resp ectivelyTheverbs

cause and go are distinct from the classes CAUSE and GO however and

do have some idiosyncratic prop erties they do not inherit from those classes

Averb may instantiate more than one class Dierentverbs instantiat

ing the same classes may map the roles provided by those classes dierently

For example one verb inheriting from b oth the Agentive class and the Mo

tion class may map the Agent and Theme roles onto the same p osition y

for instance while another may map Patient and Theme roles onto the

same p osition throw for instance Further an individual verb can have

idiosyncratic prop erties which it do es not inherit from any class An in

dividual verb may also override prop erties provided by a class ob ject Fly

for instance inherits from CAUSE arguably but it overrides the Patient

role in the grid it inherits from CAUSE keeping only Agent and Instru

ment roles he ew with a hangglider In short viewing protoverbs as

verb classob jects avoids the problems of lexical decomp osition as usually

conceived We can view give as containing the parts inheriting from the

classes CAUSE COMETO GO without implying that give has only the

prop erties provided by these parts This disarms Larsons ma jor motiva

tion for adopting a verbraising analysis in preference to an incorp oration

analysis like that of

The analysis is also reminiscent of Chomskys analysis of

small clauses Chomsky suggested that the matrix verb and the small

clause predicate form a complex predicate and the smallclause predicate

is subsequently extrap osed to yield the surface word order

a I considerintelligent John

b I consider John intelligent

In the current framework this would probably b e revised so that b is

literature they are as basic to knowledge representation as constituent structure is to

syntax Reasonable starting p oints for the interested reader are Winston Chapter

Fahlman ba

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

sstructure and a is not dstructure but LF ie intel ligent incorp orates

into consider The analysis diers from this hyp othetical revision of

Chomskys analysis only in that it is not intel ligent but an abstract element

selecting intel ligentwhich incorp orates into consider

I V consider X e XP John X X t intelligent

There is actually something of an inaccuracy in in that under the

analysis I have prop osed the verb consider is actually the V complex which

includes X X is part of the lexical entry of consider In other words it is

only at LF that there is a unique no de corresp onding to the word consider

Thus verbs which take small clause complements select those complements

in the strongest p ossible sense the head of the complement is actually a

part of the verbs lexical entry

Notice that whatever the category of X adopting the analysis

in eect generalizes the unavailability of the doubleob ject construction in

noun phrases with the imp ossibility of incorp orating into nouns whichwe

had used to account for the lack of pseudopassive i of The

account also generalizes to c e f g h k and l of

under the analyses illustrated in

c exp ectation of John X in my oce

XP e PP

e presentation of John X with the award

XP e PP

f p ersuasion of John X PROtoleave

XP e CP

g Johns toughness t X OP PRO to please t

i XP i e CP j j

h Johns breaking t X of his leg

i XP i e PP

k sho oting of John X dead

XP e AP

l my amusement t X of the children

i XP i e PP

A note ab out h and l these dier from the others in that I have

placed the of on the second ob ject not the rst ob ject This is b ecause

these two cases derive from doubleob ject unaccusativeverbs under the

analysis I am assuming Leaving the rst ob ject in its dstructure p osition

or leaving the of o the second argument do es not improve matters

the breaking of John his leg

the breaking his leg put John in an awful x

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

the amusement of John the children

Johns amusement the children

Johns breaking his leg is grammatical but deceptive it is clearly a Poss

ing gerund not an Ingof gerund Only the Ingof gerund is relevant to the

question at hand

The remaining cases are a b and j of raising innitival

ECM and particles a and b dier from the examples of in that

they involve Sbar deletion innitives not small clauses I would liketo

claim that these complements are not IPs but CPs They generalize with

the examples of in that the empty complementizer is incorp orated

into the matrix head in order to b e identied The structure is thus

V consider C e CP C t IP John to VP

I assume that it is the empty complementizer which assigns accusativecase

to the lower sub ject Johnmuch in the way that X assigns Case to the

second ob ject in doubleob ject constructions

Raising and innitival ECM are ungrammatical in the noun phrase

under this account b ecause theytooinvolve incorp oration into the matrix

head which is illegal when that head is a noun

It is tempting to assume that the failure of complementizer deletion in

noun phrases is also due to the requirement that the empty complementizer

b e identied by incorp orating into the matrix verb This is not obviously

p ossible however If we to ok that course wewould b e unable to distinguish

ECM and control constructions

Id preferC t John to do it

i CP C i IP

I exp ectedC t John to do it

i CP C i IP

Possibly there is a way of resolving this quandary and bringing the lackof

complementizer deletion in the noun phrase under the prohibition against

incorp oration as well but I leave it as an op en question

The nal case is j the lack of particles in the noun phrase Kayne

b argues that particle constructions are also to b e analyzed as small

clausal where the particle is a little verb

Ilooked the information up

PP P

It would b e natural to assume that the version Ilooked up the informa

tion is derived by incorp orating upKayne givesanumb er of arguments

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

against this hyp othesis however For instance pronouns are p ermitted in

the particlemoved construction but not when the particle is adjacentto

the verb

Ilooked it up

I lo okedup it

This is unexp ected if look up is a complex verb as verbs can certainly take

pronominal ob jects I sought it

Another argument is that particles allow mo diers whereas parts of

comp ound verbs do not

Ilooked it rightup

I rightupended the chair

Another argument is that sentential sub jects can app ear with pre

p osed particles but not p ostp osed particles

a I p ointed out that John had left

b I p ointed that John had left out

Kayne generalizes the illformedness of b with the illformedness of

sentential sub jects of emb edded clauses He analyzes a as involving

extrap osition of the sentential sub ject If wemoved the particle leftward to

derive a on the other hand that John had left would still b e an em

b edded sentential sub ject the sub ject of the trace of outThus wewould

incorrectly predict a to b e illformed Kayne argues that the exam

ples with prep osed particles are uniformly derived by extrap osing the

sub ject of the particle obligatorily with sentential sub jects optionally

with nounphrase sub jects

I will followKayne in assuming that prep osed particle constructions

are derived by extrap osition of the sub ject of the particle I assume though

that the particle does incorp orate at LF accounting for the unavailability

of particle constructions in noun phrases

An unsolved problem for this analysis is why particles are go o d with

ing nominals but not with other derived nominals

a i the explaining away of the problem

ii the explanation away of the problem

b i all the gyrating away they do makes tops susceptible to

idiosyncratic typ es of structural damage

ii all the gyration away

DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

b shows that it is not Case or assignment to the ob ject that makes

aii bad the same contrast is to b e found where an intransitiveverb

is involved

One p ossible solution is that ing nominals exceptionally p ermit incor

p oration This is clearly wrong though b ecause ing nominals do not

p ermit incorp oration in any of the other cases wehave discussed

the exp ecting of John to leave

the giving of John a b o ok

the b eing tough to please

etc

Another p ossibilityisthat ing nominals with particles are in fact Vparticle

comp ound verbs in contrast to verbs app earing with particles in the sen

tence This would explain why the base form of these nominals is bad

the looking of the information up Most of Kaynes tests ruling out a

Vparticle complex verb in the sentence are not helpful in the noun phrase

b ecause they involve other small clauses in addition to the particle these

would b e indep endently ruled out by the prohibition on small clauses in

the noun phrase The two tests that can b e applied to ing nominals give

conicting results a is illformed indicating that looking up is not a

complex noun but b is also illformed indicating that up is not an

indep endentword

a the lo oking up of it

b the lo oking right up of the information

I leave this as an op en question

To sum up the results of this section given the analyses illustrated in

and a signicant range of the constructions which are prohib

ited in the noun phrase can b e unied under a single generalization namely

a prohibition against incorp oration into nouns



As Kayne p oints out this example can also b e ruled out by a prohibition against

PPs in sub ject p osition He cites contrasts such as i to illustrate that this prohibition

can force rightward movement of the sub ject when it is a PP

i John teamed up with Bill

John teamed with Bill up

They sto cked up on fo o dstus

They sto cked on fo o dstus up

CHAPTER NOUN PHRASE AND SENTENCE

Chapter

The Gerund

Intro duction

In English the construction in which the noun phrase lo oks most likea

sentence is the gerund where by gerund we mean the class of structures

headed byverbing The gerund particularly the socalled Possing

constructionhas long b een a puzzle Unlike the sentencelike noun phrases

wehave examined in other languages the English Possing construction is

not simply a noun phrase with sentential prop erties but has a decidedly

grionlike structure Its forequarters ie its external distribution and

its sub ject are that of a noun phrase while its hindquarters its com

plement structure are that of a verb phrase

The gerund is of great interest in evaluating the DPanalysis inasmuch

as if the DPanalysis is correct it provides a simple and general structure

for the gerund which app ears otherwise so exceptional Under the DP

analysis we can takethePossing construction to involve D taking a VP

complement instead of an NP complement In this waywe account for the

prop erties of the Possing construction while maintaining a strict version

of Xbar theory

There is a resp ectable transformational literature on the gerund includ

ing Lees Rosenbaum Ross Emonds Wasow

and Ro ep er Sto ckwell Schachter and Partee Thompson

Horn Williams Schachter Reuland Baker c

In the earlier work it was assumed that all gerunds were sentence trans



In traditional usage the term gerund usually refers to the noun in ing not to

the construction headed bysuch a noun see eg Poutsma Current usage is

frequently more lax applying the term gerund b oth to the noun in ing andtothenoun

phrase headed in a pretheoretic sense byN I follow the more lib eral usage here

ing

CHAPTER THE GERUND

forms The lexicalist hyp othesis of Chomsky paved the way for a

nonsentential treatmentofPossing and he argued explicitly for a non

sentential treatment of gerunds like the cal ling of the rol l Emonds

claimed that Possing gerunds were never dominated byS atany level

of derivation this p osition was apparently not widely adopted until the

midseventies however Horn and Schachter b oth argue for

this p osition Schachters analysis app ears to have b ecome standard it is

adopted for example in Chomsky

The paradigmatic sentencetensed S with that complementizerand

the paradigmatic noun phrasea simple concrete noun phrase like the

rockhavevery distinct prop erties b oth internally and externally ie with

regard b oth to their structure and distribution As Ross p oints out

though there is a range of structures p ossessing b oth sentence and noun

phrase prop erties Ross argued that these constructions form a continuum

of which tensed S and concrete noun phrase are the endp oints in order

of increasing nouniness tensed S indirect question innitive Accing

Possing action nominal Ingof derived nominal concrete noun Un

der more common assumptions there is a cut b etween sentence and noun

phrase and exceptional prop erties of atypical constructions must b e ac

counted for in some other way The generally accepted cut at least since

Reuland is b etween Accing the most nounphraselikesentence and

Possing the most sentencelike noun phrase

The Range of Gerund Constructions

There are a numb er of distinct structures in which the gerund app ears In

this section I would liketosurvey them In coming sections I will fo cus

more narrowly on the Possing construction

Discriminating at a fairly ne grain we can distinguish at least these

uses of Ving

PresentParticiple

a After progressive be

b As pre or p ostnominal mo dier

c In adjunct clause sometimes with nominative or accusative sub

ject

Argumental Accing



Horn and Schachter app ear to come indep endently to the conclusion that Poss

ing is a noun phrase at all levels Both claim the nontransformational analysis as an

innovation and neither includes the other in his bibliography

INTRODUCTION

PROing

Possing

Ingof

Traditionally is distinguished from the former b eing named

the Participle the latter the Gerund I will not b e much concerned ab out

the participle are distinguished from in that Ingof app ears

to involve a simple deverbal noun and lacks the verbal characteristics to

b e found in the other cases Accing and Possing are distinguished

chiey in the Case which is assigned to the sub ject of the gerund Ac

cusative in Accing GenitiveinPossing PROing diers from Possing

and Accing in lacking an overt sub ject It is an op en question whether the

structure of PROing is actually the same as that of Possing Accing or

mayhave either structure dep ending on context Less likely though not to

b e ruled out a priori is that PROing has a structure distinct from that of

either Accing or Possing

Eliminating the participle then and assuming provisorily that PROing

collapses with either Accing Possing or b oth wehave three basic typ es

of gerund construction Possing Accing and Ingof

Reulands Analysis of Accing

The most thorough recent analysis of the Accing construction is that of

Reuland I adopt his characterization of Accing at face value for the

time b eing to provide a backdrop against which to compare the prop erties

of Possing whichismychief concern I oer a new analysis of Accing in

section

These are the most imp ortantcharacteristics of the Accing construc

tion

The sub ject receives accusative case Weapprove of him studying

linguistics

The sub ject alternates with PRO We approveofPRO studying

linguistics

The Accing clause must app ear in a Casemarked p osition

The sub ject takes scop e within the Accing clause I counted on no

one coming vs I counted on no one to come

No overt complementizer no overt wh in Comp

CHAPTER THE GERUND

No raising from sub ject John was hated having to leavesosoon

Whmovement from sub ject p ermitted Who did you approveoft

studying linguistics

Anaphors p ermitted in sub ject p osition Weanticipated each other

winning his race

Accing can b e selected for

Reuland accounts for these facts by prop osing that the Accing con

struction is a CP with an empty Complementizer selecting an IP headed

by ing ing is a nominal element when Accing is an argument and

requires Case It shares that Case with its sub ject Ing lowers onto

the verb via axhopping or Rule R of Chomsky If it lowers in

the syntax no Case can b e assigned to the sub ject the sub ject p osition

is ungoverned and PRO app ears If it do es not lower until PF PROis

excluded and the sub ject receives accusativeCase Ing do es not count

as a Sub ject in the binding theory of Chomsky for the sub ject by

stipulation A matrix verb can govern IP and its head ing across an empty

complementizer but not the sub ject of ingasing counts as a closer gov

ernor For this reason the ECP is violated if raising is attempted from

the sub ject p osition or if one attempts to raise the sub ject out of the Acc

ing clause by QR Whmovement out of Accing is p ermitted on the other

hand b ecause it can use the emptyCompasanintermediate landing site

this option is not available to Amovement and QR

Noun Phrase Asp ects of Possing

As the rst order of business I would like to review the evidence which

leads us to the conclusion that Possing gerunds are noun phrases while

Accing gerunds are sentences

External evidence

a Distribution

The rst class of evidence indicating that Possing is a noun phrase and

not a sentence is its external distribution There are a numberofpositions



Though the morphological case which app ears on the sub ject of Accing may dier

from the abstract Case assigned to the Accing phrase as a whole as for instance when

the Accing construction app ears in sub ject p osition receiving nominative Case but

assigning accusative Case to its own sub ject Reuland oers no explanation for this

discrepancy

NOUN PHRASE ASPECTS OF POSSING

from which sentences are excluded Possing do es app ear in these p ositions

These p ositions include a ob ject of prep osition b sub ject of a sentence

where Sub jectAuxiliary Inversion has applied c sub ject of an emb ed

ded sentence d sub ject of a sentence following a sentenceinitial adverb

e topic p osition f cleft p osition

a I learned ab out Johns weakness for stogies

I learned ab out Johns smoking stogies

I learned ab out John smoking stogies

I learned ab out that John smokes stogies

I learned ab out for John to smoke stogies

b Do es Johns weakness for stogies b other you

Would Johns smoking stogies b other you

Would John smoking stogies b other you

Do es that John smokes stogies b other you

Would for John to smoke stogies b other you



As Horn notes topicalization of a clause is p ossible curiously if it originates

as a sentential sub ject

i That John died we b elieved

ii That John died we b elieved to b e horrible

This is esp ecially curious since the putative source is ungrammatical

iii We b elieved that John died to b e horrible

Descriptively when a sentential sub ject leaves its dstructure p osition it can either

move leftward and leave an empty category or it can move rightward and leaveanovert

pleonastic If it is unable to leave a pleonastic it is also unable to move leftward and

leave an empty category In this regard consider cases where an ob ject pleonastic is

p ossible

iv Wewere sure of it that John would win

That John would win wewere sure of

v You can count on it that John will win

That John will win you can counton

vi I said it rst that John would win

That John would win I said rst

The generalization breaks down with examples like the following

vii We resented it that John was given the prize

That John was given the prize we resented

viii I hate it when it snows on myFrench toast

When it snows on myFrench toast I hate

CHAPTER THE GERUND

c I b elieve that Johns weakness for stogies b others you

Ibelieve that Johns smoking stogies would b other you

I b elieve that John smoking stogies would b other you

I b elieve that that John smokes stogies b others you

I b elieve that for John to smoke stogies would b other you

d Perhaps Johns weakness for stogies b others you

Perhaps Johns smoking stogies would b other you

Perhaps John smoking stogies would b other you

Perhaps that John smokes stogies b others you

Perhaps for John to smoke stogies would b other you

e Johns weakness for stogies I cant abide

Johns smoking stogies I cant abide

John smoking stogies I cant abide

That John smokes stogies I cant b elieve

For John to smoke stogies I wont p ermit

f Its Johns weakness for stogies that I cant abide

Its Johns smoking stogies that I cant abide

Its John smoking stogies that I cant abide

Its that John smokes stogies that I cant b elieve

Its for John to smoke stogies that I wont p ermit

Accing gerunds present the least serious violation On the basis of

this evidence alone in fact one can make a case for including Accing

with Possing as a noun phrase The degraded status of Accing in b

f might b e ascrib ed to some problem with accusative Case assignmentin

these contexts or simply to the generally slightly marginal status of Acc

ing In section I will oer an analysis which predicts that Accing has the

distribution of a noun phrase but no other noun phrase prop erties Until

then I leavethebehavior of Accing in the paradigm as an anomaly

Atany rate the contrast b etween simple noun phrase and Possing on

the one hand and innitives and tensed clauses on the other illustrates

the p oint at hand that Possing has the distribution of a noun phrase not

that of a sentence

Another irregularityisthebehavior of indirect questions which pattern

like noun phrases in some contexts

a I heard ab out what you did

b the knowledge of that John came

the knowledge of who John saw

NOUN PHRASE ASPECTS OF POSSING

Two p ossibilities are that indirect questions in these contexts share

something of the structure of headless relatives which are arguably noun

phrases or that there is a wh AGR in Comp that licenses whwords

in Sp ec of C and this AGR supplies CP with certain nominal features I

will not pursue the issue here

There is one noun phrase p osition in which gerunds do not app ear

p

namely sub ject of noun phrase stagnatings evils Cf stagnations

evils This is due to other factors though Note that ing forms do not

make go o d p ossessors even when they are clearly nouns

the singings aect on them was heartwarming

the riotings p olarization of the country

b Agreement

The Possing gerund also diers from sentences in that it b ears agree

ment ie conjoined gerunds trigger plural agreementontheverb whereas

with conjoined sentential sub jects the verb shows default singular agree

ment Again note that Accing patterns with sentences not Poss

ing

a That John came and that Mary left b othersb other me

b John coming so often and Mary leaving so often b othersb other

me

c Johns coming and Marys leaving b othersb other me



Possibly the AGR in Comp acquires these nominal features in turn from the whword

it agrees withor we could take the more traditional line that whwords o ccupy Comp

It might b e ob jected that not all whwords are noun phrases but the Case requirement

remains

i I heard ab out what you did

I heard ab out whyyou did it

the knowledge of what you did

the knowledge of whyyou did it

We can follow Larson however in taking whwords like why howtobenoun

phrases that p erform adverbial functions on a par with bareNP adverbs like yesterday

last yearWewould need to assume that the inherent Case these words p ossess under

Larsons analysis is not passed on to the CP they app ear in a plausible assumption Note

that with true PPs as whphrases indirect questions do not show the same prop erties

ii I heard ab out in what wayyou did it

the knowledge of in what wayyou did it

CHAPTER THE GERUND

We can account for this fact if we assume as is natural that AGR can

coindex with nominal elements but not with sentences An unb ound

AGR shows default singular agreement

c Longdistance Binding

Finally Accing and Possing gerunds show dierences with regard to long

distance binding of their sub jects such binding is p ossible in noun phrases

and in Possing gerunds but not in Accing gerunds

a they thought that each others giving up the ship was forgivable

they thoughtthateach other giving up the ship was forgivable

b they thoughtthateach others desertion was forgivable

c they thoughtthatforeach other to desert would b e forgivable

cf they thought that for John to desert would b e forgivable

Internal evidence

In this section I turn to the asp ects of the internal structure of Possing

that indicate that it is a noun phrase

a Subject

With regard to their internal structure gerunds lo ok like noun phrases b e

cause of the prop erties of their sub ject First unlike sub jects of sentences

sub jects of gerunds b ear genitive Case

Secondly as noted by Horn and Reuland there are certain

semantic restrictions on the sub ject of Possing which makes it lo ok likeany

other genitive nounphrase sp ecier In particular inanimate sub jects make

p o or p ossessors

a the refrigerators do or

Johns do or

b wewere very upset at the refrigerators tipping over

wewere very upset at the refrigerator tipping over

c wewere very upset at our ideas b eing unfairly criticized

wewere very upset at our idea b eing unfairly criticized



Alternatively sentences but not noun phrases are forced to topicalize out of sub ject

p osition see Koster Stowell and the trace left b ehind always has default

numb er features

NOUN PHRASE ASPECTS OF POSSING

Likewise idiom chunks are not very happy in the p ossessor

a I was irked at advantages b eing taken of Johns situation

b The outcome justied muchs b eing made of Calvins foresight

The evidence of must b e taken with a grain of salt however There

are p erfectly go o d Possing gerunds where the p ossessor is not animate and

concrete

Wewould prefer its not raining just now

We might also cite the classic example the citys destructionPossibly the

contrast in b amounts to no more than a weak stylistic tendency to

prefer Accing over Possing when the sub ject is nonpronominal as noted

for example byPoutsma

Thirdly the Possing genitive b ehaves like a p ossessor in the requirement

that it b e headnal

a a friend of mines new house

a friend of the little b oys new bicycle

the man resp onsibles briefcase

the man who left earlys briefcase

Iwas upset at

b a friend of mines leaving early

a friend of the little b oys leaving early

the man resp onsibles leaving early

the man who came lates leaving early

Iwas upset at

c a friend of mine leaving early

a friend of the little b oy leaving early

the man resp onsible leaving early

the man who came late leaving early



Examples likethoseIhave starred here are frequently pro duced in conversation and

it is arguable that they are not ungrammatical but only bad style Whatever the status

of the deviance of ab though it is their contrast with the p erfectly acceptable

c that is relevant for the p oint at hand

CHAPTER THE GERUND

b Sp ecicity

Further extraction from gerunds shows sp ecicity eects In this gerunds

contrast minimally with Accing constructions Consider

a We rememb er him describing Rome

b We rememb er his describing Rome

c the citythatwerememb er him describing t

d the city that we rememb er his describing t

The ungrammaticality of d can b e accounted for by assimilating it to

sp ecicity eects in extraction from noun phrases

Who did you see a picture of t

Who did you see his picture of t

An alternative analysis is that sp ecicityisnotinvolved in the exam

ples of but simple sub jacencyIfthePossing construction but not

the Accing construction involves a noun phrase DP then d could

potentially b e subsumed under the Complex Noun Phrase Constraint

c Pied Piping

Possing gerunds containing wh sub jects can front under piedpiping not

so for Accing gerunds This groups Possing with noun phrases b and

Accing with sentences c

a the man whose irting with your wife you to ok such exception

to

the man who irting with your wife you to ok such exception

to

b the man whose opinions you to ok such exception to

c the man for who to leave early you would have preferred

d Scop e

The sub ject of Possing gerunds like the sub ject of noun phrases can take

wide scop e that of Accing strongly prefers narrow scop e

p

a John disapproves of everyones taking a dayo wide

John disapproves of everyonetakingadayo wide

NOUN PHRASE ASPECTS OF POSSING

p

b John disapproves of everyones happiness wide

c John prefers everyone to takeadayo wide

This is explained if QR cannot cross a barrier nor move Compto

Comp and Accing gerunds have a CPIP structure with an empty

complementizer On the assumption that the sub ject of the noun phrase is

emb edded under only one maximal pro jection DP and not two CP and

IP it is free to moveout

e Sentential Adverbials

Finally it is usually assumed in particular by Williams Jackendo

and Reuland that sentential adverbials are not very go o d

in Possing gerunds but that they are go o d in sentences including Accing

gerunds

a John probably b eing a spy Bill thought it wise to avoid him

Reuland

Johns probably b eing a spy made Bill think it wise to avoid

him

b John fortunately knowing the answer I didnt fail the test

Johns fortunately knowing the answer kept me from failing

This paradigm is called somewhat into question however by the fact

that Accing do es not takesentence adverbials when it is in argumentpo

sition

a I was worried ab out John probably b eing a spy

b I was grateful for John fortunately knowing the answer

Factivity probably contributes to the illformedness of a note that I

was worriedabout John being a spy involves the presupp osition that John

is aspy this would b e incompatible with an adverb like probably This

do es not account for the ungrammaticality of b however Whatever

the condition that prevents sentence adverbials from app earing in Accing

gerunds in argument p osition maywell also exclude them from Possing

gerunds whichmust always app ear in argument p osition I leave this as

an unresolved question

CHAPTER THE GERUND

Sentential Asp ects of Possing

In the previous section I summarized the evidence that has b een collected

over the years that makes it quite clear that Possing gerunds are noun

phrases whereas Accing gerunds are sentential

VP in Possing

If Possing gerunds are noun phrases though there is clearly a VP emb ed

ded in them The head of the gerundie the Vinga Caseassigns

its complement b takes adverbs rather than adjectives c takes aux

iliaries d takes double ob ject complements etc etc For a complete

catalog of the constructions that are found in the complementofverbs in

cluding Possing gerunds but not in the complement of nouns see section

I I In all these ways it b ehaves like a true verb and not a noun

a Johns discovering a thesiswriting algorithm

Johns discovery a thesiswriting algorithm

b Horaces carefully describing the bank vault to Max

Horaces carefully description of the bank vault to Max

c Guineves having presented a golden cup to Bertrand

Guineves haveing presentation of a golden cup to Bertrand

d Ilanas giving Marc a kiss in public

Ilanas gift of Marc of a kiss in public

These facts indicate that there is a VP emb edded within Possing that the

structure is NPs VP

NP

PRO in the Gerund

There is a bit of complicating evidence There are ways in which the genitive

noun phrase do es not b ehave likea typical genitive In particular the

sub ject of the gerund like the sub ject of the sentence but unlike the sub ject

of the noun phrase is obligatoryas we discussed in I Ib As discussed

at length byWasow Ro ep er Possing diers from Ingof in that Poss

ingor more accurately PROing since there is no sign of genitive case

shows obligatory control Wasow Ro ep er exx

a i I detest loud singing

ii I detest singing loudly

b i John enjoyed a reading of The Bald Soprano

ii John enjoyed reading The Bald Soprano

SENTENTIAL ASPECTS OF POSSING

c i The killing of his dog upset John

ii Killing his dog upset John

In the ii sentences the agent of the gerund is necessarily understo o d

to b e either the sub ject of the sentence or the ob ject in the psychverb

constructions ie I in a John in b and c This is the usual

pattern for control of innitives as well I would prefer to sing loud ly To

kil l his dog would upset John In the i examples on the other hand the

nominal need not b e understo o d as controlled This seems to indicate that

there is necessarily a PRO sub ject in the ii examples but necessarily none

in the i examples

There are two sets of apparent counterexamples to the claim that PROis

obligatory in the PROing examples First are examples like Shooting deer

is funil legalWasow Ro ep er argue that these involve a deleted onein

current terms PRO Supp orting their analysis wemay observethat

arb

examples of this sort are only p ossible in generic contexts and in general

corresp ond to PRO contexts for innitives It has b een suggested that

arb

such cases actually involve control by an implicit b enefactive argument

Shooting deer is fun for Xil legal for X If so these examples generalize

with the next set of apparently problematic examples

The second class of apparent counterexamples involvePROing con

structions as sub jects of passives suchasSeceding from the Union was

consideredWasow Ro ep er argue that the controller is the implicit agent

of the passive this seems quite reasonable esp ecially in lightofrecentwork

into the syntactic activeness of such implicit arguments

Baker c notes that not only are PROing gerunds obligatorily

controlled but they require pleonastic sub jects when no external role is

assigned

I am disapp ointed by

a itstheraining all day

b itsthe b eing certain that shell quit

c itsthe certainty that shell quit

Baker c ex

Baker also cites examples like I enjoyedPROrendition of the aria as

evidence that PRO is not only not required in nongerundive noun phrases

it is not allowed Such examples must b e considered with caution though

They crucially assume that sub jects of noun phrases o ccupy the same p o

sition as determiners This is called somewhat into question by examples

suchastheres no PRO xing this boat now where a determiner and PRO

CHAPTER THE GERUND

coo ccur As Quirk et al p oint out the presentational context is

one place in which gerunds pro ductively app ear with determiners Jesp er

son cites similar examples Be that as it may it is clear that controlled

PRO is excluded from nongerundive noun phrases

Baker explains the obligatoriness of PRO and pleonastics in gerunds

by app ealing to Rothsteins Rule of PredicateLinking Rothstein

argues that verb phrases are predicates and are thus sub ject to a syntactic

requirement that they have a sub ject Nbar on the other hand is not a

predicate and thus do es not require and apparently also do es not license

PRO or pleonastics

In section I Ib I adopted a mo died version of this hyp othesis

namelythatVP but not NP is a predicate that requires a sub ject VP

is found in b oth Accing and Possing hence the requirementthatPROor

an overt sub ject app ear when VP has an external role and a pleonastic

when it do es not Contrary to Rothstein I assumed that NP can but need

not license a PRO The fact that PRO is not obligatory correlates with

the fact that control is not obligatory with Ingof

There is a residual problem which this do es not solve however Consider

the examples where the context is a discussion ab out ones children

a Its the constantbickering at each other that b others me most

b Its bickering at each other that b others me most

In a wehave an Ingof in a control environment and the anaphor

each other seemstorequireaPROantecedent Control is not required

however as indicated bythewellformedness of the example If control had

b een required the antecedent me would havemadePRO singular thus an

unsuitable antecedentforeach otherJustsuch a situation is illustrated in

b with a PROing construction

If this argument is correct it indicates that it is not simply the presence

of PRO that determines whether a phrase must b e controlled but also

the typ e of phrase involved The generalization we made earlier was that

control is mediated by the phrase containing PRO and that sentences but

not noun phrases require control This hyp othesis is incompatible with

analyzing Possing as a noun phrase If PROing can at least optionally

b e an emptysub ject version of Possing and control of Possing is not

obligatoryinasmuchasPossing is a noun phrase then wewould exp ect

examples like b to b e grammaticalPossing should pattern with Ing

of with resp ect to obligatoriness of control

One option is to assume that Possing never exists with a PRO sub ject

Wemight supp ose for instance that the only determiner that selects VP

and thus heads a Possing typ e construction is AGR and excludes PRO

SENTENTIAL ASPECTS OF POSSING

by b eing a governor This do es not seem to conform to the facts however

There are a few AGR determiners that app ear in Possing constructions

wehave seen theres no xing this boat now for example Also there are

p ositions in which only Possing and not Accing can app ear

a the Administration defended Norths siphoning funds to the

Khmer Rouge

the Administration defended North siphoning funds to the Khmer

Rouge

b the Administration deplored Norths getting caughtatit

the Administration deplored North getting caughtatit

In these contexts it is still p ossible to nd PROing examples indicating

that these PROing examples must corresp ond to Possing structures as

exp ected wedohave obligatory control

a the Administration defended siphoning funds to the Khmer

Rouge

b the Administration deplored getting caughtatit

I do not have a solution to this residual problem I b elievethemost

likely line is to argue that the Possing construction indeed always has an

overt sub ject and all examples of PROing have the structure of Accing

Under this hyp othesis an explanation remains to b e found for the examples

of and examples like theres no xing this boat now cf eg fo otnote

A second p ossibility is that the obligatoriness of control is in some way

tied to the obligatoriness of PRO when PRO app ears as the sub ject of NP

it is only optionally controlled b ecause it is an optional PRO

Nbar Deletion

A second wayinwhich the p ossessor in gerunds diers from that in non

gerundive noun phrases is its ability to supp ort a deleted complement N

bar deletion is p ossible with concrete noun phrases but not with gerunds

Iwas surprised by Johns eagerness and by Marys to o

I was surprised by Johns pitching in and by Marys to o



A fact that calls this paradigm somewhat into question is that there are verbs under

which neither Possing nor Accing app ears yet PROing do es app ear These include

avoid cherish deny and p ossibly enjoy and detestThisweakens the claim that b ecause

Accing structures are illformed in these contexts by pro cess of elimination the examples

of must necessarily involvePossing structures

CHAPTER THE GERUND

This prop erty is not unique to gerunds though but is also p ossessed by

derived nominals

I was surprised by Johns discovery of an answer and by

Marys to o

It app ears to dep end only on the fact that these nominals denote situations

rather than ob jects The cut is b etween situations and ob jects not b e

tween concrete and abstract as indicated by the wellformedness of similar

sentences where an abstract ob ject is involved I was surprisedbyJohns

idea and by Marys too I return to this issue in section f

ANALYSES I FINDING THE SEAMS

Analyses I Finding the Seams

Several prop osals have b een made in the literature as to the prop er analysis

of Possing In this section I would like to discuss each of them as well as

some that have not previously b een prop osed

Schachter

Schachter argues for this structure

NP

DET NOM

NP VP

Johns fixing the car

Chomsky adopts much the same structure though he omits the

DET and NOM no des and generates VP and the p ossessiveNPdi

rectly under the topmost NP no de

Schachter assumes that auxiliaries are generated inside VP but mo dals

are generated external to VP explaining the absence of mo dals in gerunds

Fredericks musting depart

Alans canning burn toy soldiers

Schachters and Chomskys analyses are problematic under current views

concerning Xbar structure There are two problems with Schachters struc

ture assuming VP is the head of NOM and ultimately of NP how can a

maximal category head another category and how can a head dier in syn

tactic category from the phrase it heads ie how can a verbal category

head a nominal category On the other hand if VP is not the head of NP

Xtheory then NP is unheaded and we still have a violation of

Also to account for the app earance of genitive Case in the gerund it is

assumed that genitive Case is assigned to the structural p osition NPNP

All other Cases are assigned by lexical Case assigners though It would b e



ActuallySchachter notes that given his assumptions ab out phrasestructure there

is no principled way of excluding the rule NOM Aux VP in place of NOM VP

Thus the lack of mo dals is correctly captured in his rules but is not actually explained

CHAPTER THE GERUND

much preferable to assimilate genitive Case to the others in this resp ect

In Know ledge of Language Chomsky takes the noun to b e the genitive

Caseassigner but this leaves the presence of genitive Case in the gerund a

mystery since there is no noun present

On the p ositive side Chomsky gets some mileage from the fact that

no noun head is present in the gerund Sp ecically he argues that PRO

is p ossible in the gerund but not in nongerundive noun phrases b ecause

in nongerundive noun phrases the noun governs the sp ecier p osition

precluding PRO but in gerunds there is no lexical head and PROis

p ermitted

Horn

Horn prop oses

NPN

SpecN N

ing VP

Under Horns analysis as well as under Schachters the availabilityof

PRO is predicted though ing is a noun it is also an ax and presumably

do es not qualify as a lexical category hence it do es not preclude PROin

its governmentdomain

The two problems with Schachters analysisincompatability with cur

rent Xbar theory assignment of genitive Casereceive natural solutions

under Horns analysis Xbar theory is observed the head of NP is an

N VP is a complement of that N not the head of the gerund Since ing

app ears at PF merged with the verb we can account for the intuition that

the verb is the head The presence of genitive Case can b e ascrib ed to the

noun ing under assumptions like Chomskys viz that nouns are assigners

of genitive Case



Certainly there app ear to b e instances of Caseassignment without Caseassigners

in adjectival absolutives for example our fearless leader sick we al l pitchedinto

help Here a default Case app ears which is in English ob jective or common Case

Genitive Case assignment has little in common with such constructions



Chomsky claims that VP is the genitive Caseassigner in gerunds The mystery is

then why VP is the sole phrasal Caseassigner all other Cases are assigned byX s and

why VP assigns genitiveCase only when it app ears inside the noun phrase

ANALYSES I FINDING THE SEAMS

The DVP Analysis

a ing as Functional Head

A reason for b eing uneasy with Horns analysis is that ing is not a typical

noun Nouns are not normally axes Nouns do not normally select VPs

Nouns do not normally have obligatory complements

A related problem is why determiners cannot generally ll the sp ecier

p osition of ing esp ecially since a p ossessor is p ermitted Also if ing is

a noun why are adjectives PP mo diers relative clauses etc excluded

The lack of adjectives etc might suggest treating ing as a pronoun but

if it is a pronoun why do es it p ermit a p ossessor

The fact that ing shows up as a verbal ax and displaces mo dals

makes it app ear a priori to b e an In In fact if we accept Reulands

arguments ing is precisely a gardenvariety In in the Accing construc

tion Unfortunatelyifitwere an In in the Possing construction Possing

should b ehavelikea sentence not a noun phrase

Given the framework develop ed in Chapter I I we can take ing in Poss

ing to b e Inectional in the sense of b eing a functional element one

which is like In moreover in selecting VPWe can assume that it diers

from ing in Accing in that it p ossesses the feature N rather than N

This idea is attractive in that it p ostulates minimal variance b etween the

ing of Accing Possing and Ingof yet still accounts for the substantial

dierences in their b ehavior The ing of the Ingof construction wemay

assume is likethePossing ing in b eing N It diers from Possing ing

in that it selects V not VP it is not an ax with an indep endentsyntactic

domain

By changing N to N in the lexical entry of Accing ingwe in eect

create a Determiner FN not a Noun FN under the feature

decomp osition of syntactic categories whichwe prop osed earlier Thus if

we take seriously the ways in which Horns ing b ehaves like a functional

element rather than a lexical element we are led to recast his structure as

a DP structure

DP

Possr D

D VP

ing

CHAPTER THE GERUND

The unavailability of determiners and adjectives follows from the fact that

they are not licensed by D but by N The fact that ing is an ax and

obligatorily selects a nonargument complement are typical prop erties of

functional elements

This analysis preserves solutions provided by Horns analysis for the

problems in Schachters analysis First the VP is not the head of the

noun phrase the Determiner is The intuition that V is the head of the

phrase is preserved if we assume that D functionallyselects VP Namely

if D functionallyselects VP then it inherits its descriptive content from

VP and b ecomes an spro jection of V But since D cpro jects the noun

phrase ie DP Xtheory is not violated What is involved is merely the

substitution of one maximal categoryVP for another NP

Second genitive Case in the gerund is accounted for given our earlier

hyp othesis that AGR in the Determiner assigns genitive Casewe need

only assume the AGR which assigns genitive Case can coo ccur with ing

The availabilityofPRO is also predicted given that ing is a functional

element thusnotagovernor for PRO

b Turkish Again

The DVP analysis is also rendered particularly attractive b ecause it exactly

parallels Kornlts analysis of gerunds in Turkish Recall that there

is an overt AGR which assigns genitive Case in Turkish noun phrases and

thus strong evidence for the existence of a D no de The gerund construction

as in English is a mixed construction externally and as concerns the

sub ject it b ehaves like a noun phrase while internallyitbehaves likea

VP

a Halilin her dakikaisime karIsmasI

HalilGEN every minute businesssDATinterfereINGs

Halils constantly interfering in my business

b Halilin geldiginibiliyorum

HalilGEN comeINGsACC knowPROGs

I know that Halil is coming

c Kediyeyemek vermediginiz dogru mu

catDAT foodACC giveNEGINGp true Q

Is it true that you did not give fo o d to the cat

The verb takes all its usual complements and mo diers except for the

morphology on the verb the phrase including the verb and its complements

is indistinguishable from any other verb phrase On the other hand the

ANALYSES I FINDING THE SEAMS

AGR is nominal AGR and assigns genitive Case rather than nominative

Case also the phrase as a whole is assigned Case likeany nongerundive

noun phrase Clearly the structure of the Turkish gerund is precisely

what the DVP analysis prop oses for English Possing

DP

Halilin D

D VP

D AGR V

in gel

What is less clear is precisely where dIg attaches and where the case

marker b elongs For this reason I have omitted them from the diagram I

will return to this question b elow

c s and Determiners

An apparent problem for the DVP analysis is that there are a few cases of

lexical determiners coo ccurring with ing Jesp ersen volVp

cites the following examples the rst of them is also cited by Jackendo

and Schachter similar examples are noted in Ross

a There is no enjoying life without thee

b This telling tales out of scho ol has got to stop

c The judgementofheaven for mywicked leaving my fathers

house

d Between rheumatism and constant handling the ro d and gun

Jesp erson ascrib es c to Defo e d to Kingsley

The app earance of determiners in Possing class gerunds was apparently

much freer until early in this century Poutsma cites numerous

examples from Dickens

a The having to ght with that b oisterous wind to ok o his

attention Chimes I



The absence of a casemarker in c is not indicative of failure of caseassignment

The accusative casemarker is often omitted even with nongerundive noun phrases

CHAPTER THE GERUND

b the b eing cheerful and fresh for the rst moment and then

the b eing weighed down by the stale and dismal oppression of

remembrance David Coppereld ChIV a

c I am not disp osed to maintain that the b eing b orn in a work

house is in itself the most fortunate and enviable circumstance

that can p ossibly b efall a human b eing Oliver Twist ChI

Poutsma cites further such examples from Dickens Fielding Samuel Butler

Hume Thackery Jane Austen Scott Shakesp eare and several others

c and d are the most disturbing b ecause they include ad

jectives This suggests a structure in which the VP is inside of Nbar It

is dicult to knowhowtoevaluate them however as they are denitely

ungrammatical in the mo dern idiom a on the other hand illustrates

a construction that is quite pro ductive to the present Consider

Theres no xing it now

Theres no turning back the clo ck

Gerunds with this are also fairly acceptable as noted also byJackendo

This telling tales out of scho ol has to stop

This mixing business and pleasure is going to catch up with you

Neither of these examples are overwhelming The construction of

is clearly a xed phrase No cannot take gerunds in other contexts I would

recommend no stung bal lot boxes this time John thought no teasing his

dogcould bother the general And the examples of are really not very

go o d and to the extent that they are acceptable the construction has the

avor of examples like This Why Mommy every time I tel l you to do

something has got to stop where what follows this is disquotationalone

can even imagine having a silent gesture after this

The DIP Analysis

Avariation on the DVP analysis is what wemight call the DIP analysis

ANALYSES I FINDING THE SEAMS

DP

DP D

D IP

DP I

I VP

John s PRO ing hit the ball

Under this analysis s and ing o ccupytwo distinct functionalelement p osi

tions The complement of D is basically In but it is nominalized by the

ing to some extent Its syntactic category is In but it has certain lexical

features whichmake it suciently nominal in character that D can select

it In eect this analysis involves the emb edding of a PROing structure

under a nounphrase sp ecier

I argued for the DIP analysis in Abney it was originally sug

gested to me byRichard Larson Larsons suggestion was that PROV

ing

denotes a prop ertywhich is p ossessed by the sub ject see b elow section

e In his view s is a rough semantic equivalent of the verb have

The DIP analysis is required if we are to take s to b e a determiner

an analysis which I considered earlier in section I Ib but did not

adopt In particular supp osing that s o ccupies the determiner p osition

raises a conict with the supp osition that ing is in the determiner p osition

Possibly b oth share the determiner p osition we might supp ose that s is

a sp ellout of AGR and that in the same wayAGR in the sentence can

coo ccur with eg Tense s can coo ccur with an inectional element viz

ing

But this raises the question why s cannot coo ccur with eg theifit

can coo ccur with ingwhyisJohns the book bad where Johns

D D

ing leave early is not This is not a problem under the DIP analysis

There are considerations that make the DIP analysis seem plausible

at least initially

a Determiners

First if one found unsatisfying the way I explained away the apparent cases

of determiners in gerunds or if one wishes to assign a structure to the ar

chaic sentences cited by Jesp ersen the DIP analysis makes ro om for a full

CHAPTER THE GERUND

range of determiners The fact that determiners do not general ly app ear

with gerunds might b e explained along lines suggested bySchachter to

wit that gerunds are like prop er nouns in taking only a restricted set of

determinersor by supp osing that only certain determiners are satised

with the nominal character of the gerundiveIP and most determiners re

quire true NPs

b The Position of ing

A conceptual problem with the DVP analysis as well as Horns analysis

is the p osition of ing Under the DVP analysis wemust assume an ing

lowering rule to get the rightword order but lowering rules raise certain

problems with regard to the prop er government of the trace of movement

If we assume the verb raises to ing on the other hand we are unable to

derive gerunds like

Johns hurriedly putting t out the re

D VP

Hurriedly app ears outside of VP in a p osition where it cannot b e licensed

Under the DIP analysis on the other hand wemay assume V raises

to ing and still have a p osition available for hurriedlythe same p osition

it o ccupies in the nite clause b

a Johns PROhurriedly putting t out the re

IP I VP

b John hurriedly putAGR t out the re

IP I VP

Counterbalancing this argument to some extent is the fact that the D

IP analysis makes ro om for sentence adverbials as well howeveraswe

noted ab ove these adverbials are generally considered ungrammatical in

gerunds On the other hand I expressed some question as to whether they

were actually excluded from gerunds if we decide that they are not there

is no problem for the DIP analysis

c Spanish El Innitive

In Spanish we nd the denite article taking b oth innitives which are

the equivalent of gerunds in English and que clauses examples from Plann



Though the p ossibilitythat hurriedly originates in the VP and is moved to its ob

served p osition cannot b e dismissed

ANALYSES I FINDING THE SEAMS

el lamentar la p erdida de las elecciones es inutil

the lament the loss of the elections is futile

lamenting the loss in the elections is futile

el que tu vengas no es imp ortante

the that you come not is imp ortant

it is not imp ortant that you are coming

The fact that el takes a clause in Spanish lends credence to the claim that

determiners can take clausal complements

d Scop e of Not

There is also evidence from scop e phenomena which seems to supp ort the

DIP analysis over the DVP analysis and Horns analysis In the sentence

it is preferred for not in In to take wide scop e over the sub ject of the

sentence Consider the sentence

Everyone didnt come

IP I

Both readings xx came and xx came are p ossible but the former

is preferred Wemay assume that b oth scop e relations are p ossible b ecause

the two op erators mutually ccommand and that the negation op erator has

wide scop e preferentially b ecause it is more prominent b eing the head

of the constituent

Now consider the Possing gerund

Everyones not coming

Here the narrow scop e reading for not is actually excluded the only inter

pretation is the fact that xx came This is exp ected under the DIP

analysis Assuming the scop e of not to b e IP everyone is outside its scop e

everyone s PRO not ing come

DP IP I

Under the DVP analysis on the other hand wewould exp ect the scopal

relations to b e the same as in the sentence assuming that not app ears in

D in the gerund in the same way it app ears in I in the sentence

everyone s not ing come

DP D

The crucial contrast though is b etween Accing and Possing gerunds

Under the DIP analysis wewould exp ect that they would dier Accing

should b ehave exactly likethesentence Unfortunately the judgements are

very subtle but it do es seem that giving not wide scop e is b etter in the Accing construction

CHAPTER THE GERUND

a I was irked at everyone not coming but at least George and

Maria were there

b I was irked at everyones not coming but at least George

and Maria were there

Oddly enough a seems slightly b etter with stress on everyone Also

in the context of b the widescop e reading for not is not so bad as it

is out of context And here as well stress on everyone causes considerable

improvement In sum it seems that robust judgements are not to b e had

concerning scop eassignmenttonot but to the extent that they go as I

have indicated they provide supp ort for the DIP analysis

e s as Assigner

In Abney it was assumed that s uniformly assigned a role to its

sub ject accounting in this way for the lack of raising and pleonastics in the

noun phrase The gerund diers from nongerundive noun phrases in that

raising is p ossible

a Johns b eing likely t to win will only spur Bill on

b Johns b eing certain t to win will makeBillgiveup

c Johns app earingseeming t to wantustoleave him alone

mied Muy

The DIP analysis allows one to preserve the assumption that s is a

assigner in that it makes ro om for a PROantecedent of the NPtrace

without assuming that John moved into a p osition The problem which

arises now is getting the prop er interpretation with regard to the role of

John in the situation denoted by the IP In Abney I presented

an accountwhich also solved a problem which arises generally in analyses

in whichAmovement in the noun phrase is rejected Grimshaw

presents such an analysis this problem is the construal of p ossessors which

app ear to receivea role other than Possessor from the noun namelyin

derived nominals like Caesars destruction of the city the citys destruction

The accountIgave in Abney in a nutshell is as follows First

consider a phrase like Johns honestywhich denotes an attribute Presum

ably this do es involve simple p ossession and not Amovement Yet there

is entailment that if Johns honesty succeeds in denoting something ie



The central idea of p ossession of a prop erty is due to Richard Larson



Though an analysis in which all deadjectival nouns were unaccusativewould not

b e inconceivable

ANALYSES I FINDING THE SEAMS

if we are not dealing with a sentence like Johns honesty is nonexistentin

which Johns honesty fails to denote then honestJohn If John p ossesses

the attribute of honesty where we assume the interpretation of honesty to

b e the prop erty xhonestx then John is honest This is what I called

the Possessional Entailment

Possessional Entailment

Where is an entityand is an attribute Poss

Nowwe can get the prop er construal of eg John in Johns leaving by

claiming that the interpretation of PROleaving is xee is a leaving

IP

Agentx e PRO in eect providing the variable of abstraction for the

prop erty Predicating this attribute of John is to say that John left

A similar account can b e given for derived nominals by claiming that

they also denote prop erties namely that when the noun destruction is

formed from the verb destroy the interpretation of destruction is a prop

ertyformedby abstracting over one of the two p ositions of destroy

ie either xe destructione Agentx e or xe destructione

Patientx e

Though there may b e something to this account as it stands it seems to

b e a complex x for an unnecessarily complex analysis It would p erhaps b e

necessary if other evidence supp orted the claim that the sub ject p osition of

Possing is a p osition Wewould exp ect for instance that pleonastics and

idiom chunks b e disallowed in this p osition as they are in nongerundive

noun phrases Idiom chunks are indeed not very go o d

a Advantage was taken of Johns situation

I was irked at advantage b eing taken of Johns situation

I was irked at advantages b eing taken of Johns situation

b The bull was taken by the horns

I approve of the bull b eing taken by the horns in this matter

I approve of the bulls b eing taken by the horns in this matter

c Muchwas made of Calvins foresight

The slim margin by which global thermonuclear warfare was

averted justied much b eing made of Calvins foresight

The slim margin by which global thermonuclear warfare was

averted justied muchs b eing made of Calvins foresight

But pleonastics are rather go o d Judgments are somewhat mixed but there

is a clear contrast b etween pleonastics with gerunds and pleonastics with

nongerundive noun phrases Baker c gives a gerund with its being

likely as fully grammatical

CHAPTER THE GERUND

a Im happy ab out its b eing likely that John will nish so on

I was surprised at its seeming that John might not win

b its likeliho o d that John would win

its app earance that John would win

cf the likeliho o d that John would win

The illformedness of the examples with idiom chunks we can ascrib e to the

indep endent condition on p ossessors that they b e animate Nonanimate

even nonconcrete p ossessors are acceptable with some degradation This

degradation is most severe wemay assume with noun phrases like idiom

chunks that do not denote anything at all In fact the examples of

do seem to vary in acceptability according to the extent to which they can

be interpreted as metaphoric rather than outandout nonreferential We

can account for the marginality of the pleonastic examples of in like

fashion This is myintuition for instance ab out the dierence b etween the

example with belikelyand that with seem it is forced to b e understo o d as

referential With be likely it can b e fairly easily construed as denoting the

prop osition John wil l win and prop ositions can b e likelyWithseemon

the other hand even if we construe it as the prop osition that John might

notwinwe cannot sp eak of prop ositions seeming hence the additional

illformedness of the example we are forced to recognize it as truly non

referential

In sum none of the arguments for the DIP analysis are particularly

strong and the relativewellformedness of the examples with pleonastics

is rather p ersuasive evidence against it Thus I reject it and with it the

prop osition that s is a assigning head of DP



Burzios examples i are relevanthere

i it was likely without PRO b eing obvious that S

it seemed without b eing obvious that S

A p ossible interpretation of the contrast in i is that it as sub ject of be likely o ccupies

a p osition hence can control a PRO It as sub ject of seem on the other hand cannot

control indicating that it is a true pleonastic thanks to N Chomsky for reminding me of these examples

ANALYSES I I THE MORPHOLOGICAL ANGLE

Analyses I I The Morphological Angle

There is another approach to the problem of gerund structure exempli

ed by the analyses of Jackendo Leb eaux and Baker In this view the

question of gerund structure is a question of the interaction of morphology

and syntax it is a question of the b ehavior of phonologically dep endent

morphemes that at some level b ehave like indep endent morphemes syn

tactically

Jackendo

a The Deverbal Rule Schema

Jackendo recognizes that gerunds are problematic for a restrictive

Xschema The assumption that gerunds involve a noun phrase headed bya

verb violates his Uniform ThreeLevel Hyp othesis that every category X

pro jects to X andevery X is headed byanX He subsumes gerunds

along with ve other structures under a single exceptional rule schema the

Deverbalizing Rule Schema

i i

X af V

His structure for Possing gerunds results from instantiating this schema

with XN i and afing

N

Poss N

ing V

V

V Obj

ing subsequently lowers to V yielding the correct surface form

In this way he accounts for the presence of a genitivewhich is regularly

  

aN sp ecier the presence of VP V for him V is S and the absence

of a nominative sub ject mo dals and sentence adverbials which are all



daughters of V

CHAPTER THE GERUND

b The History of the English Gerund

As Jackendo p oints out this view p ermits a straightforward accountof

the history of the construction Apparently the oldest form of the gerund

is a simple deverbal noun suchasbuilding writing Jackendo sp eculates

that the historical development of the gerund involved a raising of the

attachment site of the nominalizing ax from where XN and i

to XN i

N

N

N

N

V ing

Emonds and Poutsma givechronologies for the develop

ment of the gerund that supp ort Jackendo s claims Emonds is a

study of gerunds in Chaucer with the intent to demonstrate that the Poss

ing construction is not used by Chaucer but only the Ingof construction

He gives a list of criteria for distinguishing the Possing and Ingof construc

tions and applies these criteria to all the examples of Ving in Chaucers

The Parsons Tale Virtually all examples are either clearly Ingof or

do not show clear indications of their status There are only a handful of

examples whichappeartobePossing or PROing these Emonds attempts

to explain away with more or less success Even if he do es not showPoss

ing to b e nonexistent in Chaucer he do es demonstrate that it is very rare

much more so than in current usage

Poutsma gives a much more general chronology of the developmentof

the gerund This is his account in brief The gerund ending was originally

ung that of the participle ende inde in Southern dialects As

with mo dern German nominals in ungorDutch nominals in ing the Old

English gerund in ung had only nominal characteristics and none of the

mixed quality of presentdayPossing The gerund and participle endings

collapsed in the development of Middle English Poutsma reconstructs

thecourseofchange as loss of the dental stop in the participle ending

followed byfreevariation b etween a dental and velar p oint of articulation

for the nasal By the fourteenth century b oth endings were ing except

in some Northern dialects where distinct endings had b een preserved at

ANALYSES I I THE MORPHOLOGICAL ANGLE

least to the time of Poutsmas writing and for the participle ing

for the gerund The collapse of participle and gerund paved the way for

the mixing of the verbal prop erties of the participle and the nominal

prop erties of the gerund The b eginnings of the mixed gerund o ccurred

in the mid fteenth century First gerunds b egan app earing with particles

previously according to Poutsma particles were found with gerunds only

as prexes not as separate words

a the making up of the seide evidencez Paston Let No ca

b smytynge of of hese feteris smiting o of his fetters Paston

Let No ca

Examples of gerunds taking a direct ob ject b egin to app ear in the late

fteenth centuryFinally it is only much later the end of the sixteenth

century that gerunds b egin to app ear with asp ect and voice distinctions

Until that time active gerunds are used in a passive sense this usage is fre

quenteven in Shakesp eare and survives to the presentday in constructions

like to be worth seeing synonymous with to be worth being seen

This chronology accords well with Jackendo s claim that the develop

ment of the gerund involved attaching ing at an ever higher p ointinthe

expansion of NP The only glitch app ears to b e accounting for the stage

at which auxiliaries are not generated but particles and barenounphrase

direct ob jects are This would seem to indicate application of the Deverbal

izing Rule Schema at the X levelJackendo generates auxiliaries under

V However adjectives and sp eciers like many three are generated out

side N predicting that at the stage in which auxiliaries were not generated

adjectives were p ermitted which is highly unlikelythough I do not have

data one way or the other

c Ingof

A third p ossible instantiation of the Deverbalizing Rule Schema with XN

and afingwhichJackendo do es not discuss is the following where i

CHAPTER THE GERUND

N

N

N

ing V

V

In Jackendo s system such a construction would have the following prop

erties it would have the distribution of a noun phrase it would have b oth

 

N and N sp eciersie p ossessors determiners quantiers and ad

jectives it would have b oth nonrestrictive and restrictive relative clauses

but ob jects would not b e marked with ofbutwould b e bare noun phrases

It would lack mo dals auxiliaries all adverbials but would haveverbal

sub categorizations including particles Casemarked noun phrases double

ob jects etc

There is a construction which has some but not all of these prop erties

namely the Ingof construction

Johns xing of the car

the lo oking up of the information

This construction app ears to involve a simple deverbal noun like derived

nominals In particular it lacks the primary characteristic of a verbal

construction viz Casemarking of the direct ob ject However it diers in

imp ortantways from other derived nominals which p oint to a more verbal

character Firstly it p ermits particles as wehave seenthough it do es not

p ermit particle movement the looking of the information up It is also

likeaverb and unlike a derived nominal in that it do es not p ermit passive

without passive morphology

a Their carefully rebuilding the city

Their careful rebuilding of the city

Their careful reconstruction of the city

The citys carefully rebuilding t

The citys careful rebuilding t

The citys careful reconstruction

Thirdly it patterns with Possing rather than derived nominals in not p er mitting temp oral sub jects examples from Emonds

ANALYSES I I THE MORPHOLOGICAL ANGLE

a Their renewing our contract this year

Their renewing of our contract this year

Their renewal of our contract

b This years renewing our contract

This years renewing of our contract

This years renewal of our contract

On the other hand determiners and relative clauses are p ermitted

and mo dals and auxiliaries are excluded

a the counting of the votes that to ok the longest was in the th

district

b the having xed of the car

In short the prop erties of the Ingof construction are not precisely what

Jackendo would predict assuming the structure but they are close

enough to merit further investigation

PesetskyLeb eaux

A structure similar to that of has b een prop osed by Leb eaux

Leb eaux following Pesetsky argues that there is LFmovementof

axes and that the verbal prop erties of the Ingof construction can b e

accounted for by assuming LFraising of ing to Nbar

Pesetsky argues for using LFraising of axes to account for a number

of paradoxes in morphology Most of his examples involve a stem with

b oth a prex and a sux where the phonology indicates that the prex

is attached after the sux whereas the syntax or semantics indicates that

the sux is attached after the prex For instance consider the form un

happier er attaches only to monosyllabic stems or disyllabic stems with

esp ecially light second syllables directer complexer This indicates



Restrictive relative clauses are often not as go o d as one might like This seems to

have to do with the fact that these items denote situations it is a prop erty they share

with derived nominals

i the sinking of a ship that b othered me the most was when the Lusitanic went

down

ii the destruction of a city that b othered me the most was when they b ombed

Dresden



Though I am not entirely convinced that the combination of light rst syllable

stressed second syllable and semivowel third syllable allows er even where the rst

syllable is not a prex I have b een unable to nd existing words of this form but the

CHAPTER THE GERUND

that for the phonology the analysis must b e un happy er However the

meaning is not not more happy but more not happy indicating that

for the semantics the analysis must b e un happy er Pesetsky solves this

puzzle by satisfying the phonology at sstructure and the semantics at LF

he raises er at LF so that it has narrow scop e at sstructure and broad

scop e at LF

A A

un A A er

happy er un A

happy t

Leb eaux suggests using this device to accountfortheverbal

prop erties of the Ingof construction He suggests that the Ving noun in

eg the singing of the song has manyverbal prop erties b ecause at LF it

is a verb

NP NP

N N

N of the song V ing

V ing V of the song

sing V t

sing

Note that syntacticfeature p ercolation reapplies at LF with the result

that some of the category lab els change b etween sstructure and LF In

particular morphological traces do not p ossess syntactic category features

so the former complement sing b ecomes the new head as far as p er

V

colation of syntacticcategory features is concerned

neologism corrodey corrode y disgusting sounds quite happywith er This is

corrodier than anything my moms ever made me do before This do es not b ear on the

other paradoxes whichPesetsky has collected however

ANALYSES I I THE MORPHOLOGICAL ANGLE

The similarity to the analysis I suggested to ll out the Jackendovian

paradigm is striking It is attractive to attempt to account for part of

Ross range of nounphraselike vs sentencelike constructions by p ostu

lating dierences in the scop e of the nominalizing ax ing In lexicalized

forms like building it takes scop e over N in Ingof it takes scop e over

Nbar in Possing it takes scop e over NP and in Accing it takes scop e

beyond the pro jections of N heading its own indep endent syntactic pro

jection

Baker

Baker c argues that the dierence b etween Possing and Ingof gerunds

is a matter of scop e of ing He takes the Possing construction to b e a case

of syntactic axation on a par with nounincorp oration in contrast

to Ingof whichinvolves lexical axation of ing More precisely he as

sumes that Possing gerunds have dstructures exemplied by and

sstructures like

IP

NP Infl VP

ing V NP

sing the aria

NP

NP NP

N NP

V ing the aria

sing

ing has lowered to ax itself to sing it is the head of the new complex

lexical item sing ingFollowing Pesetsky Baker assumes that

pro jection conventions reapply at sstructure with the eect that the no des formerly lab elled V and VP are relab elled N and NP The

CHAPTER THE GERUND

former In disapp ears without leaving a trace and ing b ecomes remains

head of the former IPwhich is accordingly relab elled NP Baker ascrib es

the sentencelike prop erties of gerunds to the fact that they are sentences

at dstructure and their nounphraselike prop erties to the fact that they

are noun phrases at sstructure and b eyond

There are a numb er of details whichBaker do es not iron out First

Baker considers ing to b e the head of IP at dstructure this would indi

cate that ing is of syntactic category I however not N The alternativeis

to assume an empty In at dstructure which disapp ears at sstructure Sec

ondly there is a paradox concerning the timing of axmovement and Case

marking For the complements of sing Baker requires Casemarking to

apply b efore axmovement inasmuch as after axmovement the Case

assigner sing has b ecome the nonCaseassigning noun singing On the other

hand the gerund as a whole b ehaves like a noun phrase for the purp oses of

Caseassignment it is not Caseresistant it in fact requires Case This re

quires Caseassignment to apply sometime after axmovement when the

gerund has b ecome a noun phrase In this case an empty In will not help

however IP cannot b ecome NP until after axmovement has o ccured

but by then it is to o late to Casemark the complements of singThus

to makeBakers account coherent wemust assume that the gerund is a

noun phrase at all levels Caseassignment precedes axmovement and

axmovement precedes PF and probably sstructure

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

Conclusion Syntactic Axation

A Final Analysis

a The Scop e of Ing

The analysis of gerunds I would like to defend is very close to that of

Jackendo except that I will generalize my analysis to Ingof and I adopt

a DP structure for the noun phrase The essence of the analysis is this

the dierences in the structures of the various typ es of gerund in English

reduce to dierences in the scop e of the nominalizer ing Ing has the

same basic prop erties in all three gerund structuresAcc ing Possing

Ingofnamelyittakes a verbal pro jection and converts it into a nominal

category The three typ es of gerund dier only with regard to the p oint

on the spro jection path of V that the conversion to a nominal category

o ccurs at V atVPoratIP

Most of the prop erties of Accing Possing and Ingof fall out correctly

if weinterpret take scop e over as meaning b e sister of creating the

following structures at sstructure

a Accing

DP

ing IP

John I

I VP

V DP

sing the Marseillaise John singing the Marseillaise

CHAPTER THE GERUND

b Possing

DP

Johns D

D NP

ing VP

V DP

sing the Marseillaise

Johns singing the Marseillaise

c Ingof

DP

Johns D

D NP

N PP KP

ing V of the Marseillaise

sing

Johns singing of the Marseillaise

Ihavetaken ing to adjoin to a spro jection of V pro jecting its own

nominal features to the category resulting from the adjunction after the

manner of morphological axation despite the fact that the adjunction

is in the syntax If we assume that ing can only adjoin to a maximal

pro jection when it adjoins in the syntax then under the DPanalysis we

correctly predict three p ossible adjunction sites for ing viz those of

adjunction to V ie adjunction in the morphology adjunction to VP

adjunction to IP For sake of preciseness let us assume that ing has



A fourth p ossibilitywould b e adjunction to CP Preliminarilywemayfollow Chom

sky a in assuming that adjunction to CP is excluded by as yet obscure universal

principles The structure C ing is excluded b ecause the selection

CP DP IP prop erties of C are violated

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

the feature N Assuming V VP have the features FN adjoining ing

overrides the N value creating categories of typ e FN ie N NP

Assuming IP has the features FN adjoining ing pro duces a FN

category ie DP

I should makevery clear that I assume that ing axestoaverbal

pro jection converting it directly into a nominal pro jection without pro

jecting any structure of its own For example in the Accing construction

I assume that ing axes to IP and converts it into DP ing is not a D

it simply substitutes its N feature into the IP matrix pro ducing a DP

There is no D and no Dbar If ing were a D pro jecting DP in accor

dance with Xbar theorywewould exp ect it to take a sub ject or to license

other dep endents such as lo cative PPs but it do es not I sp ell out the

mechanisms of this axation to XP in section e

b Accing

The only nounphrase prop erty of Accing if its structure is as given in

a is its external distribution All the prop erties of the sub ject includ

ing the Case it receives and all the prop erties of the verb phrase contained

within Accing are the same as are found in the sentence This diers from

Reulands accountwhichwehave assumed to nowin that it predicts a

nounphraselike distribution for Accing Reuland ascrib ed no nounphrase

prop erties to Accing at all The predictions made by assigning Accing the

structure in a seem to accord b etter with the facts As we noted in

discussing the external prop erties of Possing section ab ove the dis

tribution of Accing is more like that of Possing than wewould exp ect if

Accing were a CP plain and simple Accing is somewhat marginal in most

nounphrase p ositions from which sentences are excluded but not as bad

as wewould exp ect under Reulands analysis cf the examples of section

a

In addition to its distribution we identied in two other ways in

whichPossing had the external b ehavior of a noun phrase but Accing

did not If we are now to assume contrary to our earlier assumptions that

Accing is a noun phrase at its outermost level these ways that Accing

diers in b ehavior from other noun phrases must b e accounted for The

two prop erties in question are the fact that conjoined Accing phrases in

sub ject p osition do not trigger plural agreement and that an anaphor

in the sub ject of Accing in sub ject p osition cannot b e longdistance b ound



I am assuming as I have since I that N and V are distinguishedby their value

for the single feature N Under more standard assumptions ab out their feature com

p osition wewould have to assume that ing has the features NV

CHAPTER THE GERUND

a John coming so often and Mary leaving so often b othersb other

me

vs John and Mary b othersb other me

b they thought that each other giving up the ship was forgivable

p

vs they thought that each others desertion was forgivable

Both of these dierences can b e straightforwardly explained given one

assumption which I wish to make for indep endent reasons namely that

the determiner is the site of p erson numb er and gender features socalled

Phi features In Possing but not in Accing there is a D hence Phi

features For this reason conjoined Possings trigger plural agreement like

other plural noun phrases Since Accing do es not have Phifeatures on

the other hand AGR cannot coindex with it hence AGR shows default

agreement when it has an Accing sub ject in the same waythatitshows

default agreement when it has a sentential sub ject Likewise since AGR

do es not coindex with Accing AGR counts as an accessible SUBJECT

for anaphors within Accing accounting for the dierence in longdistance

binding prop erties b etween Accing and noun phrases that do b ear Phi

features including Possing

Thus all the external evidence distinguishing Possing as noun phrase

but Accing as sentence can readily b e accounted for under hyp othesis

under which b oth are noun phrases externally They continue to dier with

regard to the exp ected b ehavior of their sub jects cf a the sub ject

of Possing b ehaves like the sub ject of a noun phrase but the sub ject of

Accing b ehaves like the sub ject of a sentence

The assignment of accusative Case to the sub ject of Accing b ears a

bit of discussion I will part ways with Reuland and assume not that

accusative Case is assigned from outside and transferred by ing to the

sub ject but that there is an AGR present I assume there is a nominal

AGR in Possing assigning genitive Case and a verbal AGR in Accing

assigning common Case or nominative Case nominative Case is usually

only assigned in absolutive constructions suchasMary was wasting her

time on John he being a conrmedbachelor I take the p ossibilityof

the presence of AGR in In to b e the default case not the exception The



I discuss my reasons for wishing to make this assumption in Chapter IV In brief

determiners and pronouns whichI take to b e of category Determiner are the elements

which mark these features to the highest degree uniformly across languages This sug

gests that the Determiner is the grammatical lo cus of these features



In the binding theory of Chomsky b the dierence is one of the availabilityof

a BTcompatible indexing AGR do es not count as a p otential binder for anaphors in

Possing b ecause of the iwithini condition AGR does countasa potential binder for

anaphors in Accing b ecause it do es not coindex with Accing See Chomsky b

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

one place where it is not p ossible to haveAGR in In is in the innitive

In the innitive wemay assume that it is the presence of to in In which

precludes AGR

c Possing

The analysis of Possing presented in b varies only slightly from the

DVP analysis examined earlier and most explanations of prop erties of

Possing given under the DVP analysis carry over into the current analysis

Possing has the distribution of a noun phrase b ecause it is in fact a noun

phrase DP With regard to agreement and longdistance binding when

Possing lls sub ject p osition wehave just noted that Possing diers from

Accing in p ossessing a D p osition hence Phifeatures The sub ject

receives genitive Case from D I assume that there is a nonovert AGR

AGR

in D assigning genitive Case and that s is a p ostp ositional casemarker

K If sentence adverbials are licensed by the presence of an In then we

predict they will b e found in Accing but not Possing this seems to b e

correct though as we noted earlier x e there is some unclarityinhow

to interpret the facts

We also observed that quantier sub jects of Accing strongly prefer nar

row scop e interpretation whereas quantier sub jects of Possing strongly

prefer wide scop e interpretation If quantiers need to adjoin to IP to take

scop e the inabilityofquantiers to take narrow scop e in Possing and their

ability to do so in Accing is immediately accounted for under the current

analysis there is an IP in Accing but not in Possing What wehave not

yet explained is why quantier sub jects in Accing resist wide scop e inter

pretation whereas corresp onding sub jects in eg innitival complements

are amenable to either scop e

a John disapproves of everyone taking a dayo wide

p

b John wanted every girl in the chorus line to b e his wife wide

Iwould like to suggest that there is a stronger relation b etween bridge

verbs and their sentential complements than simply assignment and that

this relation is p ossible only b etween verbs and other verbal pro jections ie

IP CP hence the fact that Accing is a DP at the highest level explains

its inability to clausemerge with the matrix verb We can explain the



Recall that Accing is a DP but there is no D ing converts IP directly into DP

See section e for an account of the mechanisms involved



Fiengo Higginb otham argue that quantiers can also adjoin to Nbar NP

under the DPanalysis This do es not aect the question at hand as long as quantiers

cannot adjoin to DP NP under the standard analysis

CHAPTER THE GERUND

inabilityofquantiers in Accing to take matrix scop e by claiming that the

lack of clausemerging creates a barrier to quantier climbing

Finallywe noted twootherways in which Accing and Possing are

dierentiated Possing shows sp ecicity eects and p ermits pied piping

Accing do es not There is no standard accountofthemechanism which

p ermits pied piping I would like to suggest that it involves the p ercolation

of a whfeature along nonverbal pro jections The whfeature of a whPP

can p ercolate to a licensing ie marking noun at least in some cases

but never to a licensing verb at least in English

a my mother a picture of whom you saw t

b my mother examine whom I thought the do ctor never would

t

Assuming the sub ject is licensed by the functional head containing AGR

In in Accing D in Possingthe ability or inabilityofthe whfeature to

p ercolate to the phrase as a whole is correctly predicted under the cur

rent analysis In is a verbal categorythus p ercolation of the sub ject

whfeature and pied piping of the Accing phrase are prohibited D is a

nominal category hence pied piping of DP is p ermitted

the man who irting with your wife you to ok such exception to

the man whose irting with your wife you to ok such exception to

Concerning sp ecicity eects If we lo calize the source of this eect

in the presence of a D no de it follows straightforwardly from the current

analysis that Possing but not Accing will show sp ecicity eects The

current analysis makes it more dicult to give a sub jacencybased account

for the distinction in question ie the city which I remember him describing

t vs the city which I remember his describing t There is no concensus

on the prop er way to treat sp ecicity eects but it has b een frequently

observed that even among nongerundive noun phrases the degree to which

a noun phrase no de is a barrier to extraction corresp onds to the degree

to which that noun phrase is interpreted as referential If this intuition

can b e develop ed into a satisfactory formal account it will plausibly cut

prop erly b etween Possing constructionswhich p ossess Phifeatures and

are to that extent referentialand Accing constructions whichlackaD

no de

As a closing note recall that the primary problem with the DVP anal

ysis was explaining the coo ccurence of ing and either AGRs or lexical

determiners in the D p osition Since ing is not generated in the D p osition

under the current analysis this is no longer a problem

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

d The Site of Ing

The question I would like to address in this section is precisely what licenses

the conguration a or b

DP NP

ing IP ing VP

This app ears to b e adjunction of ing to IP or VP except that adjunction

do es not change category lab els Ihave describ ed this conguration as

axation to a maximal pro jection It is similar to axation in that

the features of the top no de are determined by combining the features of

the ax ing and the features of the stem IPVP In particular DP

and NP inherit the feature N from the ax and the feature F from

the stem This is similar to the way that eg destruction inherits some

features eg syntactic category from the ax tion and other features

eg grid from the stem destroy

Before I can sp ell out precisely what I mean by axation to a maximal

pro jection I must lay some groundwork First I would like to present

a certain interpretation of Xbar theory which though nonstandard is

extensionally indistinguishable from the standard interpretation of Xbar

theory Let us b egin by considering the tree

AP

A

PP

to calligraphy

A

V A

prefer able

As it is usually conceived there are two quite separate trees here ab ove

the line is the syntax to which Xbar theory applies and b elow the line is

morphologytowhich quite dierentwellformedness principles applyItis

CHAPTER THE GERUND

only a coincidence that one no de A b elongs to b oth trees On the other

hand the distinction b etween syntax and morphology is b eing blurred more

and more in recentwork such as that of Baker in which parts of words

play imp ortant indep endent syntactic roles If we simply erase the line

between syntax and morphologyhowever and assign to phrases structures

like including b oth syntactic and morphological no des Xbar

theory must b e revised Otherwise for instance Xbar theory would b e

violated by a subtree like

A

X A

un happy

Under standard morphological assumptions un is the head of the higher

A ifsohowever A do es not agree in syntactic category with its head but

with the complement of its head violating Xbar theoryFurther the lower

A is not a head yet it is also not a maximal pro jection again violating

Xbar theory

There is an obvious reinterpretation of Xbar theory that avoids these

problems Let us take Xbar theory to b e a set of wellformedness principles

which apply to subtrees of depth one

X

Y Z Z

Xbar theory states that in such a subtree

i there is a head of X let it b e Y

ii where n is the barlevel of X n and the barlevel of Y is n

or n

iii X andYhave the same sp ecications for all inheritable features

including syntactic category

iv all nonheads Z are maximal pro jections

i

Let us supp ose that every subtree must b e licensed with resp ect to a

set of congurational principles Tonow wehave assumed that the only

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

congurational principleset is Xbar theoryIfwe extend phrase markers to

include b oth syntactic and morphological no des however wemust include

a second set of congurational principles the principles governing axation

and comp ounding They say roughly that in the subtree

i there is a head of X let it b e Y

ii there is exactly one nonhead Z

iii X Y and Z all have Xbar level

iv for all features for which Y is sp ecied X and Y have identical

featuresp ecications

v for all features for which Y is not sp ecied but Z is sp ecied X

and Z haveidentical featuresp ecications

Every subtree must b e licensed either by the syntactic conditions

ie Xbar theory or by the principles governing axation and comp ound

ing If we include the statement immediately following what

wehave said so far is not a revision but simply an alternative formalization

of the standard view a theory that do es not have distinct syntactic and

morphological structures but do es include is extensionally indistin

guishable from the current theory with distinct syntactic and morphological

structures

A subtree must b e licensed by Xbar theory if its head has Xbar

level n otherwise it may b e licensed either by Xbar theory or

by the principles governing morphological congurations

This is true b ecause we can still draw a line b etween the morphology and

the syntax as in In every path from ro ot to leaf there will b e a

unique no de b elow which all subtrees are licensed by the morphological

conditions and ab ove which all subtrees are licensed by the syntactic

conditions This is guaranteed by the fact that all no des must b e

X s for a subtree to b e licensed by the morphological conditions but any

subtree licensed bythesyntactic conditions will have at least one no de of X

bar level greater than namely the ro ot Thus in ascending a path from

leaf to ro ot it is p ossible to switch from using the morphological conditions

to license subtrees to using the syntactic conditions but it is not p ossible

to switch back

Given this alternative formalization of conditions on structural cong

urations as background the revision I would like to prop ose is simply this

in the morphological conditions I would like to revise the clause iii

which reads X Y and Z have Xbar level to iii

CHAPTER THE GERUND

iii if Y has Xbar level then Z has Xbar level

Given this revision will have no eect if Y has Xbar level greater

than the subtree will b e sub ject to Xbar theory not to the morphological

principles If Y has Xbar level equal to then X has Xbar levelby

inheritance and Z has Xbar level by the revised clause iii Finally

wemay assume that Xbar levels less than are universally prohibited

The revision will have no eect that is unless there are elements

which are unsp ecied for Xbar level It is p ossible to have elements un

sp ecied for Xbar level if we treat Xbar level as a multivalued feature on

a par with syntactic category or p erson numb er and gender For instance

N would b e a shorthand for FNBar I would liketocounte

nance the p ossibility that there are elements that are not sp ecied for the

feature nBar in the same way that there are elements like un which are

not sp ecied for the features FN In particular I would like to assume

that ing is such an ax Consider then the conguration

FNBar NP

N FNBar VP

ing make hay

Since ing do es not have a Xbar level which is greater than inasmuch

as it has no Xbar level at all p ermits us to license by Xbar

theory or by the morphological conditions If we try to license

it by Xbar theorywe fail inasmuch as the head do es not have an Xbar

level which is equal to or one less than that of the maximal pro jection In



To b e more precise I should not represent ing as a separate no de but as an abbre

viation for a phonological representation Switching to a p ostx feature representation

for clarity the tree should actually b e

i

where

 

F

N

NP

Bar

 

N ing

 

F

N VP

Bar

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

particular the head has no Xbar level at all If we try to license

by the morphological conditions though everything is in order the ro ot

no de inherits its syntactic features from ing and since ing is unsp ecied

for Xbar level the ro ot no de inherits its Xbar level from the complement

of ing

Imust emphasize that with regard to elements sp ecied for Xbar level

the assumptions I have presented here are extensionally equivalentto

ie a notational variant ofstandard assumptions The assumptions

presented here dier extensionally from standard assumptions only in the

constraints they place on elements unsp ecied for bar levelunder standard

assumptions such elements do not exist The entire extentofmy revision

of the theory is to say let us supp ose elements unsp ecied for barlevel

exist I have presented a notational variant of the standard theory and

made the minimal mo dication which p ermits elements unsp ecied for bar

level to exist The resulting theory without any additional assumptions

predicts a certain b ehavior for elements unsp ecied for Xbar level this

b ehavior is precisely the b ehavior of ing

e Lowering ing

One outstanding question is whether the structures of are represen

tations at dstructure sstructure or LF Leb eaux needed to assume that

movementof ing in Ingof constructions under his analysis o ccured at LF

b ecause if ing were adjoined higher than V at sstructure then the verb

should Caseassign the direct ob ject for instance but this is of course

characteristic of Possing not Ingof As concerns Caseassignment we

would wish to say that the representations of are sstructure repre

sentations the direct ob ject receives Case in a and b but not in c

For this reason we should take the representations of to b e s

structure representations This creates the problem though that V and

ing form a morphological unit at least at PF It would seem that we

are forced to assume either that ing lowers onto the verb at PF or that

Casemarking is done before sstructure and the verb raises to ing bys

structure Horn Jackendo and Baker adopt the former course This

requires some comment b ecause there are problems whichlowering move

ments raise for the ECP these problems have led to lowering movements

b eing generally disfavored Axhopping Rule R of Chomsky for

instance has b een replaced byverbraising in Chomskys more recentwork

Under lowering movements the trace of movement is not ccommanded by

the moved element hence the trace cannot escap e the ECP by means of

b eing antecedentgoverned by the moved element On the other hand there are empirical diculties facing the assumption

CHAPTER THE GERUND

that all movements are raising movements particularly as concerns ax

hopping In French there is clear evidence for raising of the verb into In

Tensed verbsverbs whichhave merged with the AGR which originates in

Inprecede negative adverbs but innitival formswhere there has b een

no merging with AGRfollow negativeadverbs

a je ne sais pas

je ne pas sais

b ne savoir pas

ne pas savoir

This receives a ready explanation if the verb raises into In to merge with

AGR and fails to do so when no AGR is present and items like pas app ear

between In and VP

In English however no similar evidence has b een discovered and the

evidence in fact app ears to p oint in the opp osite direction In most registers

adverbs can app ear b etween innitival to and VP indicating that adverbs

do appear between In and VP in English as in French

to thoroughly read the article

If the verb raises to In to merge with AGR wewould predict that

is grammatical when it is in fact ungrammatical

John read thoroughly t the article

V

This app ears to indicate that in English unlikeinFrench AGR lowers to

the verb rather than the verb raising to AGR Thus the fact that the

present analysis and those of Horn etc involvelowering of axes cannot

be taken to weigh against them We can preserve the ECP by assuming one

of the following ing leaves no trace the trace of ing is not sub ject

to the ECP or the lowering of ing o ccurs in PF where the ECP do es

not apply The third option lowering at PF is least problematic If one

wishes to take either of the rst two courseslowering in the syntax a

caveat is in order Assuming that ing lowerstoVbetween dstructure and

sstructure means that the representations of are in fact dstructure

representations not sstructures The sstructures and LFs must b e iden

tical to in relevant resp ects though In particular to account for

Caseassignment prop erties lowering ing cannot b e allowed to convert the



The argumentpresented here is originally due to Emonds



Note that Caseadjacency is not a problem the trace of the verb not the verb itself

is the Caseassigner this mustbesoastheverb itself no longer governs the direct ob ject

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

VintoanNinPossing and Accing wemust assume that syntactic cat

egories once set at dstructure cannot b e changed at sstructure though

if we follow Leb eaux in taking the ing of Ingof to raise at LF wemust

allow lab els to change b etween sstructure and LF Also if welower ing

without leaving a trace we cannot allow the structure created by ing to

b e destroyed by the movementof ingFor instance wemust assume that

the LF of the Possing construction is

DP

D NP

VP

V ing

Otherwise the selectional prop erties of D would not b e satised at LF

An alternativetobothlowering of ing and presstructure Caseassignment

is this let us assume that the ing which axes to VP or IP is not the

overt morphological ax but a separate abstract element let us write it

ING The structure of eg Possing is

DP

D NP

ING VP

V

V

V ing

V raises at LF as a normal case of abstract headraising yielding the LF

ing



This analysis was suggested to me by N Chomsky

CHAPTER THE GERUND

DP

D NP

N VP

Ving N V

V ing ING V

t

At LF wemay assume morphological selectional requirements of ING

guarantee that the verb has the ing ax The sstructure and LF of Acc

ing are similarly

ss DP LF DP

N IP N IP

ING DPs I I N DPs I

I VP V I VP

V V ing t V

V ing t

An alternative to head raising is the p ercolation of some feature dis

tinguishing ingsay ing for lackofanything more inspiredto the

sstructure complement of ING Note that this would require that In in

Accing inherits the feature ing from its VP complement

Note that under either version of the ING analysis it is still neces

sary to license ING by the morphological conditions not by Xbar

theory ING is not an indep endent syntactic head which pro jects a full X

bar pro jection First unless we p ermit ING to b e sp ecied only for N

and inherit its sp ecications for the feature F from its complement we

cannot assume the same item ING in all gerunds Accing Possing and

Ingof Secondly if ING pro jected a full set of Xbar pro jections wewould

exp ect much more structure in Accing and Possing gerunds than we nd

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

For instance wewould exp ect to nd adjectives in Possing and p ossessors

in Accing

DP DP

D NP DPs D

AP N ING IP

ING VP DP I

Ving I VP

Ving

In conclusion if we assume a separate abstract item ING we can as

sume LFraising of V rather than PFlowering of ingWemust take

ing

ING to have precisely the characteristics we assigned to ing in the previous

section and the conditions and of that section continue

to b e necessary

f App endix VP and NPDeletion

One of the unexp ected ways that Possing and Ingof dier is in their ability

to participate in Nbar Deletionwhichwemust rename NPDeletion

under the DPanalysis Consider

a Johns xing the sink was suprising and Bills e was more so

b Johns xing of the sink was skillful and Bills e was more so

Under the current analysis b oth involve the deletion of an NP under iden

tity with a preceding NPWhy then is there a dierence in grammaticality

The rst thing to notice is that Johns xing of the sink is actually

ambiguous it can either mean the manner in which John xed the sink

Act reading or the fact that John xed the sink Fact reading

Only under the Act reading is NPDeletion p ossible

a Johns xing of the sink was skillful but Bills e was more so

b Johns xing of the sink was surprising and Bills e was even more so

CHAPTER THE GERUND

The explanation of the contrast in is that a involvesaFact

reading while b involves an Act reading Possing diers from Ingof

in that the Act reading is not available

a Johns xing the sink was skillful

b Johns xing the sink was surprising

Accing also do es not admit of an Act reading and is not sub ject to NP

Deletion

a John xing the sink was skillful

b John xing the sink was surprising

John xing the sink was surprising and Bill e was more so

In Accing there is of course the additional factor that there is no NP

present only a VP This raises the question though why VPDeletion

cannot apply in b VPDeletion unlike NPDeletion do es apply to

constructions with a Fact reading

That John xed the sink was surprising but that Bill did e was

more so

In fact VPDeletion applies only to o constructions with Fact readings sim

ply b ecause there are no VPs with Act readings We can explain the failure

of VPDeletion to apply to Accing byhyp othesizing that the domains in

which NPDeletion and VPDeletion apply are mutually exclusive NP

Deletion always applies within DP VPDeletion always applies in IPs that

are not within DP Thus the Accing construction is in the domain of

NPDeletion not VPDeletion But even if we generalize NPDeletion to

apply to either NP or VP indiscriminately but again within DP it still

will not apply in Accing b ecause Accing do es not have an Act reading

This account of the application of NPDeletion reduces to three p ostu

lates then

A NPDeletion applies only within DP

B NPDeletion applies only in constructions with an Act reading

C A construction has an Act reading only if it contains an N



Of course not within DP is not precise enough Weshouldsay IPs that are not

on an spro jection path which terminates in a DP This distinguishes b etween the IP

in Accing and IPs in the complement of a noun The latter are within a DP but not

on an spro jection path terminatingina DP

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

Possing and Accing dier crucially from Ingof in lacking N hence an

Act reading

Notice that derived nominals are like Ingof in b eing ambiguous b etween

Act and Fact readings As predicted they p ermit NPDeletion only under

the Act reading

a Caesars destruction of his eet was thorough

Caesars destruction of his eet was thorough but Antonys e

was more so

b Caesars destruction of his eet was quite unexp ected

Caesars destruction of his eet was quite unexp ected and

Antonys e was even more so

Supp ose we adopt Leb eaux claim that Ingof and derived nominals are

distinguished from other nominals in that the ax ing tion etc can

raise at LF creating a VP where an NP had b een at surface structure

translating now into the DPanalysis

SS NP LF NP

N VP ing

tion

V ing V

tion

If the ax raises wehaveaFact reading if it do es not wehaveanAct

reading Then we can put forward the complement of

A VPDeletion applies only within IP not in DP

B VPDeletion applies only in constructions with a Fact reading

C A construction has a Fact reading only if it contains a V

CHAPTER THE GERUND

Axes in the Syntax

This analysis in whichwe analyze the various gerunds as involving axa

tion of ing to maximal categories accounts for the facts extremely well A

natural question then is the place this pro cess has in the grammar more

generallyIsing unique in b ehaving in this manner How do es the pro cess

of axation in the syntax relate to other structures particularly those

created by functional heads

a The New Morphology

The idea of having axes o ccupy syntactic p ositions indep endent of their

ro ots is not a new idea byany means cf the classic analysis of Ax

Hopping in Chomsky But it is an idea that has come to playa

central role in the new morphology develop ed in works such as Selkirk

Fabb Sproat and esp ecially Baker b

Baker a shows that the syntactic eects of morphemes are cal

culated in the same order as those morphemes are axed to the ro ot In

Baker b he gives an explanation for this observation for a certain

subset of cases by prop osing that the ro ot of a complex verb actually b e

generated in a lower clause The fact that the eects of the outer ax are

felt later is simply a result of the cycle lo osely sp eaking

An example is Bakers treatment of causative The causative morpheme

is generated in the matrix clause and the verb ro ot is generated downstairs

subsequently raising to the causative morpheme

S

NP VP

caus S

NP VP

V NP

b Turkish Gerunds and the Mirror Principle

We see a Mirror Principle of a slightly dierent sort op erating in Turkish

Recall that we had left a few lo ose ends in our discussion of Turkish gerunds

in section a namely the lo cation of some of the axes such as the case

marker Consider a fairly complex example

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

Herkes benim Istakoza bayIldIgImI biliyor

everyone meGEN lobsterACC adoreNOMsACC knowPROGs

everyone knows I adore lobster

lit everyone knows of my adoring lobster

The skeleton of the structure of the gerund is

XP

benim X

X YP

Istakoza Y

bayIl

XP receives Accusativecaseundergovernment from outside this suggests

that the case marker I should b e adjoined to XP or it is a functional head

selecting XP Benim receives genitive case as argued from the nominal

AGR Im hence Im must govern benim The obvious site for Im then

is X since Im is nominal AGR presumably XD D selects NPonthe

one hand but the complements of Y are typical verb complements not

noun complements Istakoza is dative here but accusative ob jects etc

can also app ear in gerunds This suggests that YV and dIg axes to

YP converting it to an NP This leaves the bare verb stem in the lowest

p osition The complete structure is

KP

K DP

I KP D

benim D NP

Im dIg VP

KP V

Istakoza bayIl

CHAPTER THE GERUND

A kind of Mirror Principle is observed in that if we place the axes in the

syntactic p ositions whichtheybehave as if they o ccupiedas wehave done

in the resulting hierarchy of axes exactly mirrors the observed

morphological hierarchy with the highest axes syntactically b eing out

ermost morphologically This is the same kind of syntacticmorphological

corresp ondence as we observed in Bakers analysis of

c Generalizing the Mirror Principle

It is tempting to try to generalize the typ e of syntactic accountwhich suc

cessfully yields the Mirror Principle eect in the case of causatives and

gerunds to all the cases discussed in Baker a A strong hyp othesis

would b e that all axes o ccupy indep endent syntactic p ositions in a hier

archy corresp onding to the order of their morphological o ccurence This

hyp othesis has a certain attractiveness to it The acquisition of gerund

structures under the current analysis would b e somewhat less of a mys

tery if it were the default case that axes take phrasal scop e I will not

attempt to seriously evaluate the hyp othesis here though I only note

an a priori diculty in defending it Namely certain of the grammatical

function changing axes whichBaker a discusses have eects which

would b e dicult to ascrib e to the presence of a syntactic ax I havein

mind particularly reexiverecipro cal axes It is dicult to see how the

presence of recipr in would bring ab out the syntactic eect that is

apparently required viz that DP and DP are marked as coreferential

DP is externalized and DP suppressed not allowed to b e overt



Though I should hasten to make clear that the kind of Mirror Principle observed

in Turkish is not the same Mirror Principle that Baker prop osed Baker cast his Mirror

Principle in terms of order of application of morphological and syntactic pro cesses the

order of application of the morphological pro cesses broughtonby axes mirrors the

order of application of the syntactic pro cesses broughtonby those axes In Bakers

analysis of causative but not in his analyses of many other morphosyntactic pro cesses

the order that syntactic pro cesses o ccur is also mirrored in the hierarchy of p ositions

morphemes o ccupysyntactically



Even if this hyp othesis could b e established it would still b e necessary to demon

strate that the order in which syntactic pro cesses apply which are broughtonby the

morphemes mirrors the syntactic hierarchy of the morphemes



These are the eects expressed by Bakers grammaticalfunctionchanging rule

i NP VERB NP NP VERB

sub j ob j sub j ob j

NP NP

Baker a ex

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

IP

DP I

I VP

recipr VP IP

DP V

stem t

The nature of the eects of the reexiverecipro cal morpheme seem to

require that they b e expressed as op erations on lexical argument structure

prop erties not on syntactic structure

Verbal and Adjectival Passive

It is reasonable to exp ect that other verbal axes would b ehave like ing

in taking varying scop e A p ossibility that deserves mention but which

I will not pursue here is that participial ing derives adjectival categories

from verbal categories in the way gerundive ing derives nominal categories

from verbal categories Arguably participles usually involve axation of

ing to VP or IP but there are some words in ing that function like

pure adjectives eg seething glowing mentioned earlier These involve

axation of adjectival ing to V

A p ossibilityI would like to pursue here is that the passive morpheme

en b ehaves like ing in axing in either the morphology or the syntax

In particular I would like to explore the p ossibility that the dierence

between verbal and adjectival passives is a matter of scop e of en rather

than a matter of category as commonly assumed I prop ose the following

analysis for verbal a and adjectival b passives

CHAPTER THE GERUND

a VP b VP

V AP V AP

be en VP be A

V t en V

close close

a Distribution

The chief dierence b etween this analysis and the standard analysis is that

verbal passive phrases are analyzed as VPs externally in the standard

analysis but as APs in this analysis There are indications that the present

analysis is more adequate

First verbal passivedoesnothave the distribution of a typical VP

Anywhere a verbal passive can app ear an AP can app ear this is not true

of tensed and innitival VPs

a the do or was closed

the do or was red

b the do or closed in Bills face on that fateful day has long since

rotted away

the do or full of bulletholes

c closed in the plant has never reop ened

rst fashionable in the miniskirt has b ecome a p ermanent

part of American life

a John came

John busy

b Iwatched John leave

I watched John tipsy

On the other hand as has often b een p ointed out there are a few

contexts in which APs including adjectival passives app ear but verbal

passives do not Such cases in whichverbal passives do not have the

distribution of APs consititute prima facie counterevidence to the present

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

analysis The primary suchcontext is the complement of the verbs seem

remain look sound and a few others

a the do or remained closed by the wind

the do or remained full of bulletholes

b the do or lo oks closed by the wind

the do or lo oks full of bulletholes

the do or lo oks red

One way to dismiss this evidence would b e to claim that the constraint

illustrated in is not VP versus AP but activeversus stative as Levin

Rapap ort note there are some adjectival passives that are ex

cluded in this context apparently b ecause they are not stative the books

remained unsent to the factoryHowever even clearly stativeverbal pas

sives are not go o d John remains known by everyone cf John remains

known to everyone Another p ossibility is that the failure of verbal pas

sives to app ear under remain etc can b e asso ciated with the failure of

active participles to app ear in this context

Johns tribute to Bill remained glowing through the years

John remained seething at Bill

cf

Johns tribute to Bill remained heartfelt through the years

John remained angry at Bill

What is interesting ab out participles like glowing and seething is that they

are clearly adjectives having undergone semantic drift cf John seethed

at Bil l Johns tribute to Bil l glowed I will assume that an account for

the examples of can b e given along these lines hence that they do

not constitute counterevidence to the present analysis

It has also b een claimed that verbal passives are excluded from prenom

inal adjective p osition but here it is much more dicult to test To b e sure

one is dealing with a verbal passive and not an adjectival passive it is usu

ally necessary to include some sort of adjunct likea byphrase but phrases

containing p osthead material are excluded from prenominal p osition on

indep endent grounds

In short the distributional evidence is mixed but app ears to favor an

analysis in which b oth adjectival and verbal passives are APs

CHAPTER THE GERUND

b Internal Evidence

Adjectival and verbal passives are more clearly dierentiated by their in

ternal structure Here the standard analysis and the present analysis are

in agreement verbal passives have the internal structure of VPs adjectival

passives have the internal structure of APs

The rst p ointisthesemantics of the two constructions Verbal passives

frequently denote actions adjectival passives always denote prop erties We

have already seen this as a dierence b etween gerunds where ing axes in

the morphology eg Johns writing on one reading at least it denotes

an ob ject not an action and where ing axes in the syntax eg Johns

writing the letter only denotes an action

Secondlyverbal passives can assign Case whereas adjectival passives

cannot Of course this cannot b e demonstrated with the simplest examples

as the case assigned to the direct ob ject is absorb ed in passivization but

this can b e demonstrated with verbs that take double ob jects

a A book was sent John

John was sent a book

b The b o ok remained unsent John

John remained unsent a book

This is straightforwardly accounted for under the current analysis inasmuch

as verbs can assign Case but adjectives cannot in English In a the

ob ject is adjacenttoaverb at sstructure but not in b

a en send a b o ok

AP VP V

b send en a b o ok

AP A V

c A Digression On Case Absorption

This raises the question however of what the mechanism of Case absorp

tion is If we assume that the passive morpheme absorbs the verbs

Accusative case we are forced to generate en adjoined to V ifitisad

joined to VP it is to o high to absorb the Accusative case assigned to the

direct ob ject

An alternative is to assume that Accusativecaseisnot absorb ed but re

mains unassigned for some other reason We might follow Rothstein

for example in supp osing that the motivation for NPmovement in passive

is not to provide Case for the ob ject but rather so that the highest VP

can satisfy the requirements of Predication is bad b ecause VP is a

predicate whichlacks a sub ject

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

IP

VP

be AP

en VP

kiss Mary

Anumb er of questions arise why can VPs predication requirements not

b e satised by a pleonastic Why do es VP not require a sub ject The

most distressing question however arises from consideration of passive con

structions as p ostnominal mo diers Consider sentence a with p ossible

structures biii

a the b oy kissed the girl is John

i the b oy en PRO kiss the girl

AP VP

b

ii the b oy OP en t kiss the girl

AP i AP VP i

We might argue that bi is out b ecause PRO is not high enough to

construe with the boy This could b e solved by using an op erator as in

bii parallel to the structure the man OP t to x the sink Then we

might claim that the problem is the ECP the sub ject trace is not prop erly

governed This is not defensible however b ecause wewould presumably

assign an exactly parallel structure to the active participle construction

the boy OP ing t kiss the girl whichisgood

Another alternative for the problem of Case absorption is that we adopt

for en the analysis suggested at the end of our discussion of inglowering

vs verbraising namely that there are two en elements one abstract

whichwe can write EN and one concrete The structure of a verbal

passive is actually

AP

EN VP

V DP

V en

CHAPTER THE GERUND

V raises to EN at LF to satisfy ENs morphological selectional require

en

ment that it b e axed to a V

This op ens the p ossibility that EN and en divide the prop erties of the

passive morpheme b etween them In particular supp ose that EN has

adjectival syntactic features while en has Caseabsorption prop erties

en is in the right p osition to make the Caseabsorption asp ect of pas

sivization felt while EN is in the right p osition to p ermit verbal passiveto

contain a full VP

Wemust b e careful how this is sp elled out though Wemust distin

guish b etween the assignment of Accusative case and the assignmentof

the second Case in double ob ject constructions Wemust haveanac

count under which the former is absorb ed by en but the latter is not A

likely hyp othesis is the following The ability to assign Accusative Case

isaproperty sp ecic to certain lexical items which en can negate sup

p ose for concreteness that AccusativeCaseassigning verbs have a feature

A and en p ossesses the feature A whichoverrides the stems sp eci

cation for A in the usual way The ability to assign the second Case

of doubleob ject constructions on the other hand dep ends only on syn

tactic category let us assume If a head can license a second ob ject by

assignment then it need only have the syntactic category V in order to

Caseassign that ob ject The trace of en has the feature A but is not

sp ecied for syntactic category The complex verb Ven inherits the fea

ture A from en but since en is unsp ecied for syntactic category the

complex verb inherits the category V from the stem Hence the V com

en

plex do es not assign Accusative case but it do es assign the secondob ject

Case if it takes a second ob ject

This is only a sketch of an account There are many questions left

unanswered suchaswhy the secondob ject Case is apparently assigned

to the rst ob ject in eg a book was given Johnandwhy the second

ob ject Case is unavailable when there is only one ob ject If the hyp othesis

is to b e defended that the verbal passiveadjectival passive distinction is to

b e accounted to a dierence in the scop e of en the details must b e worked

out I leave that for future investigation however

d More Internal Evidence

Returning to the main line of discussion a third wayverbal and adjectival

passives dier is that raising is p ossible with verbal passives but not with

adjectival passives



Assigning Caseabsorption prop erties to en is reminiscentoftheway that it is

the trace of verbmovement not the moved verb which retains the Caseassignment

prop erties of the verb that moves

CONCLUSION SYNTACTIC AFFIXATION

a John was known to b e a genius

b John was unknown to b e a genius

This plausibly also follows from the fact that the head is a verb in a

but an adjective in b Arguably adjectives like nouns do not ac

cept reducedclause complements this was argued for nouns in section

I I I follow Levin Rappap ort in assuming that raising adjectives

like likely possible are exceptional and that the nonraising adjectives like

obvious are the norm

Fourthly idiom chunks can b e the sub jects of verbal passives but not

of adjectival passives

a Advantage was taken t of the new computers

Tabs were kept t on Jane Fonda

b Advantage remains untaken t of the new computers

Tabs remain kept t on Jane Fonda

This is explicable on the assumption that the parts of an idiom must b e

sisters This is satised in a but not in b as a more detailed

examination of the structure makes clear

a en keep tabs

AP VP V

b keep en tabs

AP A V

Under more standard assumptions this account of the absence of raising

and idiom chunks in adjectival passives is not available The assumption by

which these facts are accounted for in the standard analysis eg in Levin

Rappap ort is that adjectival passive diers from verbal passivein

b eing required to assign an external role This assignment explanation

is also available under the present analysis I do not knowofany evidence

on which to base a decision b etween these two p ossible explanations

There are a handful of other prop erties that are less clearcut in their

implications but suggest that the head of a verbal passiveisaverb but

the head of an adjectival passive is an adjective Agentive byphrases for

example are much happier in verbal passives than in adjectival passives

a the do or was closed by the janitor

b the do or remained closed by the janitor

Also too and similar degree words are more acceptable with adjectival

passives than with verbal passives this would fall out from the current

analysis if we assume they are sp eciers of adjectives but not of verbs



This assumption runs counter to assumptions I will explore in Chapter IV viz that

degree words in AP are heads like determiners in noun phrases

CHAPTER THE GERUND

a the gravestone was to o damaged bythevandals last nightto

read

EN to o damaged bythevandals to read

AP VP V

b the gravestone remained to o damaged to read

to o damaged EN to read

AP A V

In sum it is at least plausible that the dierence b etween adjectival and

verbal passives is to b e accounted to a dierence in the scop e of en along

the lines of myaccount of the dierences among the three ma jor classes of

gerunds If so this supp orts my account of gerund structure byshowing

that the mechanisms I p ostulated for gerunds have a more general validity

My account of gerunds supp orts the DPanalysis in turn in that the

prediction of the existence of precisely three typ es of gerund relies crucially

on an analysis of Possing in whichitisheadedby D and D selects a

nominal maximal pro jection

Chapter

Lexical Determiners

Wehave b een concerned to now primarily with the question whether there

is an AGR o ccupying a functional ie Inlike head p osition in the noun

phrase I b elieve the evidence of section I I from languages that haveovert

AGR in the noun phrase and the evidence provided by the gerund pre

sented in the previous chapter constitute a very strong case for adopting

the p osition that the noun phrase is in fact a DP where D is a nominal

functional element the nounphrase equivalent of In Now in the same

way that Mo dal is the class of indep endent ie nonaxal words of cat

egory I and Complementizer is the class of indep endentwords of category

C wewould exp ect there to b e a class of indep endentwords of category

D and the natural candidate is the class of Determinersthe choice of

the designation D was of course based on the tenuous hyp othesis that

Determiners are the nounphrase equivalents of Mo dals The question I

would like to address in this chapter is whether this hyp othesis is true Are

determiners of category D Do determiners head the noun phrase

In the rst section I discuss the evidence which b ears directly on the

question whether determiners head the noun phrase First I discuss ev

idence from Hungarian which shows that the strongest piece of evidence

in favor of the standard analysis namely the fact that determiners and

p ossessors are in contrastive distribution in English do es not in fact decide

between the two analyses I then discuss p ositive evidence for the Detas

head analysis One piece of evidence is that when determiners stand alone

they continue to b ehave precisely like noun phrases which is unexp ected

unless the phrase they pro ject is in fact a noun phrase I argue that

pronouns are in fact intransitive determiners However the most con

vincing reason for adopting the Detashead analysis is that the standard

analysis simply do es not provide enough distinct p ositions to accommo date

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

the range of elements which app ear b efore the noun in the noun phrase

Jackendo assumed three barlevels in the noun phrase and he fully

exploited them the Detashead analysis provides the required extra sp ec

ier p ositions under a twobar Xbar theory

There are ve ma jor categories whichtmy pretheoretic character

ization of functional elements complementizers mo dals determiners

pronouns and degree words If complementizers mo dals determiners

and pronouns head larger phrasesCPIPDP and DP resp ectivelywe

would exp ect degree words to do the same In section I argue that this

is in fact the case that adjective phrases are in fact DegPs This is al

most unavoidable under the Detashead analysis given the high degree of

similarity in English b etween adjective phrase and noun phrase I show

that the DegP analysis p ermits an elegant accountofthevery rich sp ecier

structure of the English adjective phrase

In section I return to a question of the internal structure of the noun

phrase which I had slighted in section namely the p osition of descriptive

adjectives I argue that prenominal descriptive adjectives are the nominal

equivalent of auxiliaries in the verb phrase and as such are syntactic heads

of the noun phrase they app ear in This accounts for a large range of

dierences in the b ehavior of pre and p ostnominal adjective phrases

Determiner As Head

In this section I consider the evidence which b ears directly on the Det

ashead hyp othesis First I consider evidence in favor of treating N as

the syntactic head of the noun phrase arguing that it do es not in fact

supp ort the standard analysis over the Detashead analysis In the second

subsection I present a handful of direct evidence in favor of the Detas

head hyp othesis And in subsection three I showhow the Detashead

analysis accommo dates the range of sp eciers found in the noun phrase the

wealth of which is something of an embarrassment for the standard analysis

inasmuch as the standard analysis only provides one sp ecier p osition for

all these elements



There is actually a fth namely conjunctions Conjunctions havea number of

unusual prop erties and I will not attempt a treatment of their syntax

Adp ositions meet some of the criteria of functional elements though not others for ex

ample adp ositions freely app ear in comp ounds other functional elements are uniformly

excluded from comp ounds Earlier I briey discussed the p ossibility that adp ositions

divide b etween true adp ositions P which are thematic elements and casemarkers K

which are functional elements and do not assign roles to their complements

DETERMINER AS HEAD

Arguments for the Standard Analysis

a Selectional Restrictions

There are two ma jor arguments in favor of the standard analysis First

it is the noun head which determines whether the noun phrase meets se

lectional restrictions imp osed on it Selectional restrictions are notoriously

bad criteria for syntactic headship however Consider for example

a large numb er of her friends admire a large numb er of her virtues

a large numb er of her virtues admire a large numb er of her friends

If selectional restrictions determined syntactic headship wewould b e forced

to take friends and virtues to b e the syntactic heads of alarge number of

her friends and a large number of her virtues in This is in fact the

p osition Chomsky to ok in Chomsky he considered a large number

of to b e a predeterminer which precedes the determiner her in Sp ec of

Nbar This hyp othesis has since b een generally abandoned as indefensible

For instance of her friends is not a constituent in the predeterminer

analysis yet there is a go o d deal of evidence that it is a constituent in fact

It can b e extracted for instance

Of her friends a large number t admire her virtues

Selectional restrictions only require that wegive an account of the way

that the noun is the semantic head of the noun phrase Wehave already

provided such an account under the Detashead analysis In section I I

we assumed that NP provides a predicate over individuals and that the

determiner is a functor which relates that predicate to the predicate denoted

by the rest of the sentence Consider a simple case like the man admires

sincerityIfwe abbreviate the predicate xx admires sincerity as F the

selectional restriction it imp oses on its sub ject is this F x animatex

The NP man translates as xmanx The binds the variable p osition

in this predicate the translation of the DP the man is xmanxItisa

tautology that manxmanx hence it follows that animatexmanx

and wehave accounted for the satisfaction of the selectional restriction

imp osed by the predicate xx admires sincerity Similar demonstrations

can b e given for other determiners though I will not give them here

b Determiners and Possessors

The second ma jor argumentinfavor of the standard analysis is that lexical

determiners are in contrastive distribution with p ossessors



An exception to which I will return is every Johns every book

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Johns thethatsome b o ok

Under the standard analysis p ossessors and determiners o ccupy the same

structural p osition hence they cannot coo ccur

In contrast under the Detashead hyp othesis wemust say something

extra to account for the complementarity of p ossessors and determiners

Wemust adopt some constraint along the lines of

AGR in D do es not coo ccur with lexical determiners

Assuming that p ossessors only app ear when there is an AGR in D which

assigns genitive case the inabilityofAGR to coo ccur with lexical deter

miners explains the inability of p ossessors to coo ccur with lexical deter

miners

Because the Detashead analysis requires the added constraint

the standard analysis would app ear to b e minimal

In defense of the Detashead hyp othesis consider rst that do es

not in fact involveintro ducing a new mechanism into the grammar We

already assume a constraint of the form do es not coo ccur with AGR

namelyfor innitival to To unlike mo dals precludes AGR Further I

will show that in Hungarian unlike in English determiners and p ossessors

do coo ccur Determiners app ear in precisely the p osition wewould exp ect

if they o ccupy the p osition of D This leads us to conclude that determiners

occupy the D p osition in Hungarian For the sake of crosslinguistic gener

alitywewould like the same to b e true in English Under the Detashead

analysis the dierence b etween English and Hungarian is only whether

the constraint applies or not Under the standard analysis on the

other hand English and Hungarian have radically dierent nounphrase

structure Thus the Detashead analysis is in fact the minimal hyp othesis

c Hungarian

In English there is at least one counterexample to the generalization that

determiners do not coo ccur with p ossessors namely everyasinJohns

every wishIfwe assume that determiners app ear in Sp ec of D wewould

probably take Johns every wish to involve an exceptional categorization of

every as a quanticational adjective parallel to Johns many wishesBut

then the problem is to explain whywedonothave the every wish an

every wish this every wishEach every wish some every wish etc are

presumably out for semantic reasons The only nounphrase sp ecier that

every coo ccurs with is the p ossessor This would seem to indicate that

the p ossessor do es not app ear in the same p osition as lexical determiners despite app earances

DETERMINER AS HEAD

We might ignore Johns every wish as an anomaly an idiom on a par

with in as much as or the be al l and end al lHowever in Hungarian the

literal translation of Johns every wish Johns each apple Johns which book

are all grammatical as Szab olcsi p oints out



minden

 

 

 

 

ezenazon

 

 



valamennyi

Peter kalap ja

mindket

 

 

 

 

semelyik

 

 

melyik



every

 

 

 

 

thisthat

 

 



each

Peters hat

both

 

 

 

 

neither

 

 

which

This makes it clear that we cannot take determiners to b e in Sp ec of D in

Hungarian

The determiners of app ear precisely in the p osition of D

DP

DP D

Peter D NP

minden kalapja

A problem for this hyp othesis is that D has two realizations in

there is the determiner minden but there is also the inectional ending

ja on the noun A comparable situation in the sentence would b e if there

was a mo dal yet the verb continued to agree with the sub ject AGR do es

coo ccur with mo dals as indicated by the fact that the sub ject continues to

receive nominative case it is only that AGR cannot b e overt when mo dals

are present AdmittedlyifAGR were overt wewould exp ect it to app ear

on the mo dal not on the verb

Below section c I argue that there are axal degsdeterminers in

English and other languages which app ear on the noun and raise to D at LF I argue that doublylled Ds are prohibited at sstructure but

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

not at LF If this hyp othesis is correct it provides an explanation for the

structure In wemust assume that there is an AGRinDats

structure to assign Case to the sub ject Assume that a prohibition against

doublylled Ds holds in Hungarian but it applies at PF in Hungarian

This would p ermit ja to o ccupy D at sstructure and Caseassign Peter

then lower onto the noun b efore PF

The claim that determiners app ear in the p osition of D in Hungarian is

corrob orated by the fact that Hungarian unlike English app ears to have

an equivalent of Comp in the noun phrase as well as an equivalent of In

There are twoways of expressing the p ossessor in Hungarian either in the

nominative case as wehave seen or in the Dative case

Peternek a kalap ja

PeterDAT the hat

Peters hat

Szab olcsi argues that the Dative p ossessor o ccupies the sub ject p osition

of a nounphrase equivalent of Comp which she calls Komp K She

shows clearly that noun phrases like that of form a constituent they

can undergo fo cus movement as a constituent for instance The dative

p ossessor diers from the nominative p ossessor in that it can b e extracted

whereas the nominative p ossessor cannot

a Peternek lattam t a kalap jat

PeterDAT Isaw the hatACC

Peters hat I saw

b Peter lattam a t kalap jat

PeterNOM Isaw the hatACC

Szab olcsi ascrib es this assymetry to the ECP claiming that the nominative

p osition cannot b e prop erly governed from outside the noun phrase but

the dative p osition can

In the same way that Hungarian has determiners of category D there

is also one determiner that is arguably of category K namely the de

nite article az Precisely as wewould predict az app ears after dative

p ossessors but b efore nominative p ossessors

a Peternek a kalap ja

PeterDATthehat



Though wewould not necessarily wish to assume it holds in all languages



Horro cks Stavrou make a similar claim for Greek

DETERMINER AS HEAD

b aPeter kalap ja

the PeterNOM hat

That the determiner in b b elongs with the matrix noun phrase and

not with Peterisshown by the fact that in the ma jority dialect from

which the examples of are drawn determiners are unable to co

o ccur with prop er nouns a Peter In all dialects determiners are unable

to coo ccur with pronouns eg a te the you yet determiners are found

in structures like even when the p ossessor is a pronoun a te kalapja

your hat indicating clearly that a b elongs with kalapja not with te

The twotyp es of determiner can also coo ccur

aPeter minden kalap ja

Peters every hat

To the extent that it is correct to p ostulate the structure DATK

KP

NOM D N for Hungarian noun phrases there seems to b e little

DP NP

choice but to place az in the K p osition as b oth the sp ecier of K and the

sp ecier of D are sp oken for by the twotyp es of p ossessor

In conclusion Hungarian provides rather striking evidence that deter

miners head DP and even KP at least as an option provided byUGIn

the ideal case determiners would have the same syntactic b ehavior in all

languages The minimal assumption is thus that determiners head DP in

English the burden of pro of is on those who would wish to make determin

ers heads of noun phrases in Hungarian but sp eciers of noun phrases in

English

Sundry Evidence For Det As Head

Having disarmed certain arguments against the Detashead analysis I turn

in this section to p ositive evidence for the Detashead analysis

a Dets That Cannot Stand Alone

First there are determiners like the which absolutely require following noun

phrase material and which cannot app ear alone in any capacity There are

few words that so strongly require accompanimentas the and a In the cases

where suchwords are to b e found their inability to stand alone is enco ded as

the obligatory selection of a complement Examples are complementizers

like if which select a sentence prep ositions like of which select a noun

phrase and conjuctions like and which select a range of complements but



Though they cannot b e adjacent in PF a minden kalapja Szab olcsi argues for a

PF rule deleting az when it app ears stringadjacent to another determiner

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

must app ear with some complement We can account for the coo ccurence

requirements imp osed by the without intro ducing new mechanisms into the

grammar if weassumethe obligatorily selects an NP complement hence

that it heads the noun phrase DP

b Dets That Can Stand Alone

On the other hand there are other determiners which can stand alone such

as that that man that was sil ly In this case to o the standard analysis

predicts something slightly dierent from what we actually nd Under the

standard analysis the p osition of the determiner is similar to that of an

adjective in that b oth are prenominal nonhead maximal categories

NP NP

DetP N N

Det N AP N

A

AP can app ear outside of the noun phrase and when it do es so it has its

own distinct b ehavior it do es not b ehave like a noun phrase

a he seems nice

AP

he seems afool

NP

he seems the fo ol

NP

b nice just walked in

AP

thea fo ol just walked in

NP

Under the standard analysis ie wewould exp ect DetP to do

likewise when it app ears outside the noun phrase wewould exp ect it to

b ehave dierently from the noun phrase just as AP do es In fact however

a DetP standing alone b ehaves exactly like a noun phrase



There are a few problematic examples suchasthe up to a year that it takes students

to complete this requirement or John runs the better of the twowherethe app ears

to take a PP and AdvP resp ectivelyHowever these examples are to b e explained I do

not b elieve they call into serious doubt the p oint b eing made in the text



Of course there are many complexities that the toy paradigm do es not take

into account but I take the p oint to b e clear enough that a more thorough discussion is

unwarranted

DETERMINER AS HEAD

a he seems the fo ol

he seems that

b the fo ol just walked in

that just walked in

DetP b ehaves exactly like a noun phrase The simplest explanation is

that it is a noun phrase

DetP DetP

Det NP Det

that N that

There is of course an alternative analysis for these structures one

involving an empty noun head

NP

DetP N

Det N

that e

There is some justication for such a structure in Nbar gapping construc

tions inasmuch as in Nbar gapping constructions a noun complement

is left b ehind even though the head noun has disapp eared

There were some pro ofs of Fermats Theorem in Johns new b o ok

and several of the Law of Diminishing Returns as well

When several takes an ofcomplement the interpretation is partitive sev

eral of the problems In if of the Law of Diminishing Returns is a

complementof several its interpretation pro ofs of the Law of Dimishing

Returns is inexplicable We are led to p ostulate an empty head noun

whose content is supplied by proofs



Actually there is at least one way that pronouns like that if they are indeed pro

nouns do not b ehave like noun phrases they cannot b e p ossessors thats paws This

p

is not true of p ersonal pronouns its paws

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

The evidence for an empty noun head is rather weaker in Nbar dele

tion constructionsin fact several recent analyses eg Nap oli

Lob eck Chao p ostulate no empty head but treat determin

ers in these constructions as pronominal The assumption that there is an

empty noun is esp ecially questionable for the demonstratives which func

tion pronominally in virtually every language regardless of the existence

of a Nbar deletion construction in that language

Whether or not there are noun phrases with empty heads if we admit

of any noun phrases consisting solely of determiners without the supp ort

of an empty noun head we are led to adopt the Detashead analysis

c Pronouns

The case for an emptynounheadisweakest in the case of p ersonal pro

nouns In this section I argue that pronouns are of the syntactic category

Det If so they provide a yet stronger example of noun phrases consisting

solely of hence headed by determiners

It is generally assumed that pronouns are nouns If this is the case

howeveritismysterious why pronouns do not app ear with any noun sp ec

iers determiners p ossessors adjectives quantiers measure phrases are

all prohibited

the she that I talked to was nice

my she has always b een go o d to me

dep endable them are hard to nd

many they make housecalls

two dozen us signed the p etition

This distinguishes pronouns sharply from eg prop er nouns which though

they most commonly app ear without sp eciers can pro ductively app ear

with sp eciers in the meaning of someone named N or someone resem

bling N

the Mary that I talked to was nice

mySanta Claus has always b een go o d to me

dep endable Marilyn Monro es are hard to nd

manyDoctorWelbys makeyachtcalls

two dozen John Smiths signed the hotel register



The resemblance b etween determiner and pronoun is not a new observation It is

noted for instance by Emonds who prop oses to treat pronouns as noun phrases

containing only sp eciers

DETERMINER AS HEAD

If pronouns were nouns wewould exp ect them to do likewise app earing

in usual noun p ositions with a minor meaning shift We could exp ect the

she that I talkedtoto mean the female that I talked to for instance

Further as Postal observes there are situations in which p ersonal

pronouns also b ehavelike determiners

I Claudiusidiot

we tradesmenidiots

you sailoridiot

you idiotssailors

he tradesmanidiot

they sailorsidiots

There are idiosyncratic gaps admittedly It is not clear that I Claudius

is restrictive or if it is only go o d as an app ositive It is not clear why

the deprecatory usage is bad in the rst p erson it is go o d in German

ich Idiot or why the nondeprecratory usage is bad in the second p erson

singular The lack of third p erson forms is arguably due to demonstratives

b eing suppletive in the paradigm those tradesmen those idiots

Another prop erty pronouns and determiners have in common is that

b oth app ear to b e the basic site of the grammatical features of noun phrases

such as p erson numb er and gender the socalled Phi features In par

ticular in many languages determiners show the most distinctions in their

inections more so than adjectives and much more so than nouns In Ger

man for instance determiners display a full paradigm of p erson numb er

and gender marking whereas nouns are marked for the most part only

for numb er And like determiners German pronouns mark a full range

of inectional distinctions In English and French pronouns are the only

items which still mark case If the determiner p osition is the actual site of

the noun phrases grammatical features and in particular do es not simply

agree with the noun after the manner of a mo difer this indicates that the

determiner is the head of the noun phrase

Recall that some of the arguments wehave already made rely on the

assumption that D is the site of a noun phrases referential features In

section I I I our accounts for many of the dierences b etween Possing

and Accing were based on the presence of a D no de in Possing as the

site of p erson numb er and gender features If Determiner is the lexical



It has b een argued that the examples of are merely app ositives If this is

correct the paradigm fails to provide evidence for the categorial identicationof

pronouns with determiners but the other arguments I present remain unaected



In a few cases dative is marked on nouns in the dative plural regularly in the

dative singular of some nouns obsolescentand genitive is marked on masculine and neuter nouns

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

category which is the lo cus for these features then we are led to supp ose

that D Determiner hence that Determiner heads the noun phrase

More generally pronouns are clearly functional elements They b elong

to a closed lexical class and though they refer they do not describ e they

do not provide a predicate over individuals but merely mark grammatical

features

If we account for the similarities b etween determiners and pronouns by

assigning them to the same lexical category namely D and if we assume

that b oth are accordingly heads of their phrases the structure of illustrative

noun phrases containing pronouns and those containing determiners is as

follows

a DP b DP c DP

D D NP DP D

we we linguists Johns D

those those

AGR

we are ready we linguists that is Johns

I like those those linguists

In conclusion the Detashead analysis allows us to accountforthe

similarities b etween determiners and pronouns and generate them in the

same p osition without b eing forced to generate all pronouns with empty

noun heads

d Dets As Functional Elements

Thirdly the fact that determiners have the prop erties of functional elements

like complementizers and mo dals suggests that they should receive a parallel

syntactic treatment Determiners are closedclass elements They lack de

scriptivecontent ie they do not provide predicates over individualsif

Barwise Co op er are right they are predicates over predicates

at any rate they are quanticational rather than predicational They

are often stressless in many languages they are clitics French Hebrew

Classical Greek or axes Norwegian Soninke



One way determiners dier from other functional elements is that determiners some

times app ear without a complementif pronouns are in fact determiners as I have

suggested Possibly though the app earance of functional elements as intransitives

DETERMINER AS HEAD

e HeadToHead Movement

Finally another piece of evidence is supplied by headtohead movement

Consider examples like the following

a au a le

b everyone every one

If we assume that these morphological mergers are made p ossible by head

movement wemust assume that determiners are the heads of noun phrases

Otherwise the ECP will b e violated at least in b the moved head

do es not ccommand hence do es not govern its trace under the standard

analysis a but do es under the Detashead analysis b

a NP b DP

DetP N D NP

Det N D N N

Det N t everyone N

everyone t

There is some evidence which supp orts the analysis b Most

adjectives cannot stand alone when they app ear p ostnominally

a man clever

a p erson go o d

Systematic exceptions are observed with everyone someone everything

something

someone clever something clever

someone go o d something go o d

everyone clever everything clever

everyone go o d everything go o d

in a pronominal usage constitutes a systematic exception to the otherwise general re

quirement that they take an obligatory complement It has b een argued Nap oli

eg cf Lob eck Chao that Sluicing and VPDeletion are instances of

Complementizers and Ins resp ectively b eing used intransitively as pronouns



As p ointedouttomebyRKayne pc

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

This is explained under the analysis b The structure of the examples

of is as in

DP

D NP

D N AP N

someone good N

t

The Range of Sp eciers

a TwoBars vs Three Bars

What is p erhaps the most p ersuasive motivation for assuming determiners

head noun phrases however is somewhat indirect and theoryinternal The

version of Xbar theory which is implicitly adopted in most currentwork

and explicitly argued for in Stowell is quite restrictive The standard

analysis fails to conform to it If the standard analysis is mo died to

conform to the letter if not the spirit of Xbar theory it is still inadequate

to account for the full range of English nominal sp eciers If we assume

that determiners head the noun phrase on the other hand we conform to

Xbar theory strictly interpreted and we are able to account for the full

range of English sp eciers

To b e sp ecic I take the most widely accepted version of Xbar theory

to include these two clauses

A All nonhead no des are maximal pro jections and

B Twobar pro jections are maximal pro jections for all categories

what we might call the Uniform TwoLevel Hyp othesis to

adapt a term from Jackendo



Residual questions for whichIhavenoanswers are Why do es the morphological

combination of eg some and one yield someone and not onesome on the pattern of

girlchaser chase girls ingrown grow in and Why is this an exception to the

general rule that functional elements never app ear in morphologically complex words

in any language With resp ect to determiners cf the wellknown examples NewYork

lover vs TheBronx lover

DETERMINER AS HEAD

What I mean by the standard analysis of the structure of the noun

phrase is the structure

NP

DET N

N

Interpreted strictly the Xbar requirement A that nonhead no des

b e maximal pro jections rules out the structure inasmuchasDETis

a nonhead which is not a maximal pro jection To preserve Xbar theory

wemust mo dify the standard structure for the noun phrase to

NP

DetP N

Det N

But the structure is made highly susp ect by the fact that DetP under

this analysis never contains any material except Det It is dicult to

motivate a phrasal no de XP where there is no memb er of the class X which

ever takes sp eciers or complements If it means anything to b e a phrasal

no de it is that the no de in question dominates more than one word at

least p otentially This is the sense in which the standard analysis can b e

made to conform to the letter but not the spirit of Xbar theory

The prop erty B of Xbar theorythe Uniform TwoLevel Hyp othesis

raises unsolved problems under the standard analysis of noun phrase struc

ture in that the standard analysis simply do es not provide enough distinct

p ositions to accommo date the full range of nominal sp eciers The most re

cent and most thorough study of the phrase structure of the noun phrase

and related categories particularly AP is Jackendo Jackendo

showed that the sp ecier systems of nouns and adjectives far from b eing

sparse and uninteresting circumscrib e a highlyarticulated range of struc

tural distinctions Jackendo assumed there were three barlevels in all

categories and made full use of the range of distinctions that hyp othesis af

forded in his analysis of nounphrase sp eciers The problem of accounting

for this range of distinctions under a twobar hyp othesis has not previously b een addressed

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

b Noun Phrase Sp eciers

Let us consider the range of sp eciers in the noun phrase Determiners

and p ossessors wehave already consideredthey alone exhaust the single

sp ecier p osition provided under the standard analysis Descriptive ad

jectives coo ccur with determiners and p ossessives prenominally It is not

clear that they are sp eciers however they are usually considered to b e

adjoined to Nbar I will return in section to the question of the p osition

of prenominal adjectives in the noun phrase

Between determinersp ossessors and descriptive adjectives we nd a

range of elements There are quantier phrases as in the many good men

the little soggy ricewehad There are also four distinct constructions

which according to Jackendo involve a noun phrase in this p osi

tion measure phrase seminumeral numeral and group noun These are

illustrated in the following

a two parts steel measure phrase

one half garbage

b two dozen roses seminumerals

a million stars

c three men numerals

six eggs

d a group of men group nouns

a bunch of mistakes

To accommo date these elements Jackendo assumes a second lower

sp ecier p osition in the noun phrase

N NP

PossrD N

QP N

NP

N

It is sometimes dicult to show that the noun phrases of actually

app ear in this lower p osition b ecause they vary in their ability to app ear

with an overt higher determiner There app ears to b e a constraint ruling

out two determiners in a row making go o d examples illustrating the struc

ture dicult to nd Jackendo and Selkirk note the

DETERMINER AS HEAD

contrast in numb er agreementbetween examples like that threeweeks and

those threeweeks attributing it to attachmentofthat

N N

D N D N

those NP N NP N

three weeks D N weeks

that three

Examples which clearly show seminumerals and quantiers to b e full

phrases app earing b elow the p osition of the determiner are the following

Selkirk and Jackendo overlo ok examples of this sort

a the nearly a dozen men who fell

the precisely a thousand pap er birds we folded

b the nearly as many men who didnt fall

If we wish to preserve the standard analysis wemust assume that these

QPs and NPs do not o ccupyalower sp ec p osition One p ossibilitywould

b e that they are simply a sp ecies of prenominal adjective There are a

number of ways that they dier from descriptive adjectives though that

render this hyp othesis untenable First though Qs are in fact a variety

of adjective the noun phrases are clearly noun phrases not adjectives If

they pattern with descriptive adjectives it is not at all clear whywe cannot

have descriptive noun phrases here such as

the nearly a do ctor medical student

Further though there are ordering restrictions on descriptive adjectives

that are not syntactic Dixon for example identies seven seman

tic classes of descriptive adjective and argues that the preferred order of

prenominal adjectives is determined by their memb ership in these classes

these semantic ordering restrictions are generally very weak and are of

ten violated for the sake of emphasis The requirement that QP and NP

precede descriptive adjectives cannot b e so readily violated

a fancy new car a NEW fancy car

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

the many honest men

the HONEST manymen

Third descriptive adjectives can b e iterated even within semantic classes

this is of course one of the original motivations for generating them adjoined

to NOM Nbar Quantiers and measure noun phrases cannot b e iterated

a large round red smo oth ball

the few six men

I submit that the inability to iterate quantiermeasure phrases is that

they receivea role from the noun whereas descriptive adjectives are sim

ply predicated of the noun and hence can b e iterated ad libitum In par

ticular I take plural and mass nouns to translate as

Nx Meas dx

N

where Meas dx i fd fx under a measure f p ossibly one of many

N

determined by the meaning of N For example the translation of two cups

rice is

ricex Meas twocupsx

rice

where rice is true of arbitrary quantities of rice and at least one p ossible

measure for rice is f such that fd fx i d and x are equivoluminous

Under this account measure phrases dier from descriptive adjectives

in that measure phrases are genuine arguments of the head noun

I conclude with Jackendo that it is necessary to havetwo distinct

sp ecier p ositions within the noun phrase one for p ossessorsexter nal ar

guments and one for quantier phrasesmeasure phrases Jackendo as

sumed three bar levels in order to accommo date b oth sp ecier p ositions

illustrates how the DPanalysis makes ro om for the extra p osition

under a TwoBar Xbar theory

Jackendoff N NP DP DP

D N D

N D NP

N N

N

DETERMINER AS HEAD

My analysis is not merely a translation of Jackendo s analysis into a

TwoBar DPanalysis however It is an advance over Jackendo s analysis

in that there is no need for phrasestructure rules not even the fairly gen

eral schema which Jackendo assumes Wehave already seen in detail how

the sub ject of D is licensed via an interaction of Case and theoryIfIam

correct the lower sp ecier is also licensed by theory The elements which

can app ear in this p osition are precisely those which satisfy the Measure

role I assume that the Measure role is leftdirectional hence the re

quirement that its recipients app ear in sp ecier p osition not complement

p osition and I assume that measure phrases are not Caseassigned by the

noun but have their own inherent Case

c PseudoPartitive

Finally there is one p oint on which I take issue with Jackendo s analysis

Namely following Selkirk Jackendo assumes that group nouns see

d also o ccupythelower sp ecier p osition in the noun phrase Sp ec

of NP under the DPanalysis

DP

NP

DP of N

a group men

I am reluctant to adopt this analysis b ecause it requires one to assume

a dangling of which do es not take a complement The ma jor though not

the only evidence which Selkirk adduces for this constructionwhich she

calls the pseudopartitiveis that the of N of the pseudopartitiveisnot

extractable whereas the of DP of the sup erciallysimilar partitive con

struction is extractable

a a numb er of men like anchovies PSEUDOPARTITIVE

of men a number tlike anchovies

a number twere killed of men who like anchovies

b a numb er of the men like anchovies PARTITIVE

of the men a number tlike anchovies

a number twere killed of the men who likeanchovies

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Jackendo adapting Selkirks analysis explains these facts by treating par

titives as involving a simple noun phrase with a PP complement and as

signing pseudo the structure The ofphrase cannot b e

extracted in pseudopartitives very simply b ecause it is not a constituent

I claim that partitives and pseudopartitives have the same structure

D N of DP The dierences in extractability can b e accounted

DP NP PP

for by nonstructural dierences in the ofPPs In particular let us supp ose

that the noun phrase under of in partitives is referential ie the men in

a number of the men but the noun phrase under of in pseudopartitives

is predicational ie men in a number of men The former is assigned a

role but the latter is not Instead it is on a par with predicational of

DP in examples like

a a monster of a machine

afoolofalawyer

a little slip of a girl

b acoatofwool

a coat of red

None of these of PPs can b e extracted either

a of a machine it was a monster t

of a lawyer he was a fo ol t

of a girl she was a little slip t

a monster twas delivered of a machine

that fo ol tshowed up of a lawyer

a little slip t came in of a girl

b of wo ol I have a coat t

of red I haveacoat t

a coat tiswarm of wo ol

a coat twas lost of red

Possiblyifno role is assigned to these PPs as I claim the ECP is

violated if they are extracted The same explanation extends to the non

extractability of the PP in pseudopartitives a

In this waywe can give an account for the prop erties of the pseudo

partitive without assuming a dangling of as in Selkirk and Jackendo s analysis

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

The Adjective Phrase

In this section I examine the adjective phrase and a nal category of

functional element namely Degree words As Jackendo notes the

adjective phrase has a sp ecier system that parallels that of the noun phrase

in manyways and rivalsitinrichness I show that analyzing the adjective

phrase as a pro jection of Deg allows us to accommo date the varietyof

adjectival sp eciers under a twobar Xbar theory

Deg as Head

A corollary of analyzing noun phrases as DetPs is that determiners are

found only in noun phrases This corollary app ears to b e falsied by APs

suchas



this big



that big It was

all red

In fact these are arguably not determiners but rather elements that are

ambiguous b etween determiners and Degree elements Deg such as

so big

as big

to o big

howbig

big enough

Nonetheless if we adopt an analysis in which determiners are the head of

noun phrases wemust either analyze Degs as the head of adjective phrases

or explain why they dier from Dets I will take the former course here

and consider the consequences of analyzing adjective phrases as DegPs

An immediate problem is that not only adjectives strictly sp eaking can

app ear with degree words but other categories as well

a to o many Q

as much

few enough

b to o quickly Adv

as hungrily

passionately enough

c far down the road P long after dark

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

d as under the weather as anyone I haveever seen P

to o o the wall for mytastes

c and d can b e eliminated fairly easily as irrelevant d arguably

involves an exo centric comp ound functioning as an adjective ie under

A

theweather othewall First only a restricted set of idiomatic PPs

A

shows this b ehavior cf John was as in the running as any other candidate

Second the degree word do es not mo dify the head prep osition but the

entire phrase in contrast to the examples of c Consider

a they went far down

long after they discovered the truth

b the p o or b oywas so under

he was to o o

Concerning the examples of c observe that these degree words

dier from the degree words of ab in b eing able to take other degree

words

a as to o sick

to o as happy

b as far down the road

to o long after dark

The degree words in PPs are not Degs but QPs such as are illustrated

in a QPs app ear not only in the sp ecier of PP as far down the

road but also of APasin as much toobig furthermore far and long

are not limited to app earing in PPs far toopermissive long overdue

I discuss the p osition of QPs shortly Jackendo also classies the

PPsp eciers of as QPs noting that they alternate with nounphrase

measure phrases as is typical for QPs six miles down the road cf six

inches toobig

Adjective Adverb and Quantier

As for the remaining two examples of nonadjectives taking degree words

quantiers and adverbsI claim that these are in fact sub classes of ad

jectives For concreteness I distinguish them from adjectives prop er by

using the features Q and Adv quantiers are QAdvadverbs are

QAdv and adjectives prop er are QAdv Quantiers dier from

adjectives prop er primarily in their semantics in supp orting the partitive

construction and functioning as pronouns Adjectives take on at least the

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

latter two prop erties in the comparative and sup erlative the older of the

two the oldest of the men Adverbs dier from adjectives primarily in

taking an ly sux and mo difying verbs instead of nouns With regard to

their internal structure adjective phrases and adverb phrases are virtually

identical as has b een frequently noted eg byBowers a Both ad

jectives and adverbs take the same degree words including comparative and

sup erlative forms and b oth are mo died by adverbs eg suciently quick

suciently quickly Manyadverbs do not even dier from the corresp ond

ing adjectiveby taking ly and ly is always lacking in the comparative and

sup erlativeofadverbs If we follow Larson b in taking ly to b e a

Caseassigner for adjective phrases then the internal structure of adjec

tive phrases and adverb phrases is indeed identical as b oth are the same

category Let us follow Larson in assuming that adjective phrases like

noun phrases require Case Adjective phrases acquire Case by agreeing

with Casemarked noun phrases Certain nouns and adjectives are lexically

marked with a feature C which Larson assumes Casemarks the phrase

which b ears it These are the bareNP and bareAP adverbs like I

left yesterday he runs fast Larson assumes that ly is a prep ositional

adjective Casemarker Wemay take it to b e a sux like ing that axes

to an adjective phrase and provides it with the intrinsic Case feature

C

NFAdjC adverb phrase

NFAdj C

adjective phrase

ly

so quick

If this is correct we can disp ense with the Adv feature replacing it with

the intrinsicCase feature C which also distinguishes bareNP adverb

nouns from other nouns

As we pro ceed the fact that adjective phrase quantier phrases and

adverb phrases are identical in internal structure will b ecome abundantly

clear I conclude that they are subvarieties of the same syntactic category

NAdj

One piece of evidence weighing against the DegP analysis is that certain

adjectives resist all degree words For example



Larson gives the feature as F not C I have altered his notation to avoid

confusion with the functionalelement feature F

 See Larson

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

everyone here tested for drugs has come up negative

AP

as tested for drugs as anyone else

to o tested for drugs for there to b e anychance of error

more tested for drugs than me

so tested for drugs that I think Im going to scream

If adjective phrases are consistently DegPs there must b e an empty Deg

even in cases such as these The app earance of an empty Deg is not

disturbingI assume an empty Deg in all adjective phrases consisting just

of an adjective just as I assume an empty D in all noun phrases without

an overt determiner What requires explanation is whyanovert Deg can

never app ear with these adjectives

Adjectives which resist degree words app ear to b e rather consistently

participles particularly past participles as in Perhaps their inability

to app ear with degree words generalizes with the inability of gerunds to

app ear with determiners the singing the song Unfortunatelyhowever

the analysis of adjectival passives I gave in section I I I groups adjectival

passives with Ingof gerunds not Possing gerunds Ingof gerunds do ap

p ear with determiners the singing of the songIleavethisasanunsolved

problem

One nal question raised by the prop osal that adjective phrases are

uniformly DegPs is that unlike noun phrases adjective phrases usually

app ear without a Deg This is probably semantically motivated though

and do es not reect any dierence in syntax The twotyp es of noun phrase

with which adjectives have the most in common frequently app ear without

determiners namely massplural noun phrases gradable noun phrases

ie noun phrases that like adjectives take measure phrases and predicate

nominals which uniformly lack determiners in many languages eg most

IndoEurop ean languages and sp oradically lack determiners in English

Henceforth I assume that adjective phrase quantier phrase and ad

verb phrase are all actually DegPs Deg selects AP in the same

AdvQ

way Det D selects NP In referring to adjective phrases I will follow the

same conventions as with noun phrases adjective phrase is used in its

pretheoretic sense it refers to AP under the standard analysis DegP un

der the DegPanalysis AP denotes dierent no des under the standard

analysis and under the DegPanalysis AP under the DegP analysis corre

sp onds roughly to Abar under the standard analysis DegP corresp onds

to AP QP AdvP under the standard analysis

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

The Subject of Deg

If noun phrase and adjective phrase are similar in b eing headed by a func

tional category it is fair to ask if they are similar in taking sub jects There

are a numb er of phrases which can app ear in Sp ec of Deg quantier phrases

and nounphrase measure phrases for instance

a much to o good

DegP AP

DegPQ

far to o p ermissive

he was little er kind than b efore

b six miles to o far

DegP DP AP

a little er kind

ten times as fast

Another class of phrases that app ear in this p osition which Jackendo

do es not take note of are AdvPs

quite as nice

entirely to o naive

nearly so friendly

To b e precise the structures I prop ose are these



There are also a few cases where adjectives app ear to take adjective phrases or PPs

as measure phrases

i a close to a year overdue

nigh on a year long

less than an inch to o wide

more than a mile o the mark

b up to a year overdue

under an inch long

over a mile long

One op en question is whether the prop er bracketting is not in fact eg close to a

year overdue less than an inch too wide over a mile long despite the fact that

prep ositions do not usually take adjectival complements close to overdue less than

too wide I will not attempt a prop er analysis of these examples

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

DegP DegP

DegP Deg DegP Deg

Q Adv

Deg AP Deg AP

AP AP

Q too tall Adv as nice

much quite

Degree words in quantier and adverb phrases b ehave identicallyas

predicted

a much to o little

ten times as many

precisely as few

b muchtooquickly

ten times as passionately

precisely as densely

Alsoitisworth noting that this is the same range of elements which

app ears in the sp ecier of P

a much to his liking

far down the road

little to the p oint

b six miles down the road

ten times around the track

ten years after graduation

c precisely in the middle

nearly o the chart

practically at the end

IfollowJackendo in taking these phrases to b e in the sp ecier of P

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

PP

DegP P

DP

P DP

The sp ecier phrases of and are obviously not sub jects of

the same typ e as the sub ject of the sentence or sub ject of the noun phrase

there is no Caseassigning AGR for instance When they are noun phrases

they are noun phrases which are intrinsically Casemarked they can often

app ear as adjuncts in the VP

they ran six miles

they ran around the track ten times

I assume that they are marked however in the same way that measure

phrases in the noun phrase are marked The case for marking of measure

phrases within the adjective phrase is in fact somewhat clearer than in

the noun phrase Measure phrases in the adjective phrase alternate with

p ostp osed PPs

a much to o go o d

to o go o d by far

b much to o slow

to o slowby an order of magnitude

They can also b e extracted out of the adjective phrase unlike eg adverbs

howmany inches is the do or t wider than b efore

how many miles is the course t long

how suciently is the do or t wider than b efore

Let us consider rst the simpler case of measure phrases with p ositive

adjectives

six feet tall



Though admittedly rather sp oradically Also sp eciers of too cannot b e very easily

extracted how many inches is he t too tal l to serve on a sub

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Itake the semantics of adjectives to b e similar to that of mass nouns

tal l denotes a certain quantity of tallness in the waythat rice denotes

a certain quantity of rice This corresp onds with the approachtoverb

meanings esp oused earlier in section I I where a verb like destroy was

taken to have the same denotation as its nominalization destruction The

two dier only syntactically not semantically In the same way here I

take the adjective tal l and its nominalization tal lness to denote the same

thing a certain quantity of abstract stu Or more precisely the DegP

tal l denotes a certain quantity of tallness the adjective tal l is a predicate

over individual quantities of tallness On this view then verbs nouns and

adjectives are all rstorder predicates ie predicates over individuals

They dier only in the kind of individual that makes up their denotation

Verbs are predicates over situations nouns are predicates over ob jects and

adjectives are predicates over attributes The union of situations ob jects

and attributes is the universal set of individuals

The adjective tal l translates as

talle Measme Themexe

Meas and Theme are b oth roles As with mass nouns Measme i

fefm for the relevant measure function f

A phrase where these roles have b een assigned eg John is six feet

tal l translates as

talle Meassixfeete ThemeJohne

ie John p ossesses a tallness which is equimetric with six feet

Too suppresses the adjectives Measure role and adds one of its own

John is six inches too tal l translates as

talle ThemeJohne To osixinchesetall

where To omeF i the measure of e equals s concatenate mwheres is the

maximal satisfactory measure for the attribute F That is Johns tallness

exceeds the maximal satisfactory tallness by six inches



To b e more precise Meas and Theme are actually classes of roles as argued

byegMarantz or rather functions from words to individual roles We

should write more prop erly Meas me i f ef m Given this renement

tall tall tall

we can account for the semantic illformedness of eg six feet intel ligent the measure

function of intelligence is undened for the measurement six feet ie f six

intelligent

feet is undened Dierentwords mayhave the same measure function For example

f f hence the wellformedness of eg John is as tal l as Bil l is wide But

tall wide

f f hence the illformedness of John is as tal l as Bil l is intel ligent

tall intelligent

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

This sketch has not b een intended as a serious semantic account Rather

it is a cursory examination of the relation b etween measures and attributes

to illustrate that Meas has as go o d a claim to role status as any other

relation

If six inches is marked by too in six inches too tal l though it still is

not quite a true sub ject As noted there is no indication of agreement

between too and the measure phrase Also Sp ec of Deg is not a valid

landing site for movement That is there are no examples like

Your symptoms are rub ellas indicative t

cf indicative of rub ella

Syntactically I b elieve this is mostly an accidental gap though there are

semantic motivations Syntactically the AGR we nd in the English noun

phrase seems to b e a rather marked element There are few languages

with true overt noun phrase sub jects They are nonexistent in Romance

languages Even other Germanic languages havemuch stronger restrictions

on the elements that can app ear in sub ject of noun phrase in German for

instance it is more or less restricted to prop er names Since nounphrase

like adjective phrases are marked in themselves they are lacking in many

languages it is not surprising that their internal structure lacks the more

marked asp ects of nounphrase internal structure

On the semanticthematic side the markedness of sub jects in adjec

tive phrase is surely amplied by the fact that adjectives are uniformly

nonagentiveintheir structure Possibly adjectives are uniformly un

accusative as suggested for instance by the fact that the external argu

ments of adjectives can systematically app ear as internal arguments when

the adjectives are nominalized the happiness of Bil l cf the destruction of

Caesar If such an analysis can b e defended the lack of a sub ject p o

Agent

sition in adjective phrases would correlate with the fact that it would never

b e needed except for passives like rubel la indicative your proposal

supportive

Extent Clauses

Degree words license various typ es of extent clauses

big that I couldnt see over it so

as big as John saidas a house

to o big to use

er big than the other one wasthan the other one



On the other hand ing nominalizations of nonunaccusativeintransitiveverbs

have the same prop erty the crying of the baby the shooting of the hunters

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

These clauses are not p ermitted when the degree word is absent

big that I couldnt see over it

big as John said

big to use

big than the other one was

Further the various typ es of clause are sp ecic to one degree word Even

if a degree wordispresent if it is the wrong degree word the clause is not

p ermitted

to o big that I couldnt see over it

as big than the other one was

bigger to use

These facts clearly illustrate that the extent clauses are licensed by partic

ular degree words

As has b een frequently noted the relation b etween degree words and

the clauses they license is very similar to the relation b etween a denite

article and relative clause The denite article often app ears to b e licensed

by the relative clause

a the Paris

the Paris that I love

b the b o ok of Johns

the b o ok of Johns that I read

There are clearly dierences b etween this case and that of extent clauses

however First in the examples just given it is the relative clause which

licenses the article not vice versa Relative clauses can app ear with other

determiners and even when no determiner app ears

a b o ok that I read

that b o ok that I read

b o oks that I read

On the other hand relative clauses are prohibited with p ossessors

Johns b o ok that I read

my b o ok that I lost

We can claim that the dierence b etween relative clause and extent clause

is only that the relative clause is less sp ecic to a particular determiner It

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

can b e licensed by a range of determiners including the empty determiners

that app ear with mass and plural nouns But it is not licensed by AGR

D

As Jackendo p oints out the paradigm is also somewhat mislead

ing in that it is not only a relative clause which p ermits the determiner to

app ear but any restrictive mo dier

the Paris of the Thirties

the b o ok of Johns on the table

In resp onse note that there are a core of cases where this is not true

up to a year that it has taken p eople to complete this requirement the

this up to a year that it has taken

your up to a year that it takes you to complete such pro jects

In conclusion it do es seem that there is a sp ecial relation b etween de

terminer and relative clause which parallels the relation b etween degree

word and extent clause This supp orts the hyp othesis that the two o ccupy

parallel structural p ositions

An advantage of the DegP analysis emerges when we consider the ques

tion of how the relation b etween degree word and extent clause is expressed

structurally It is most economical to generate the extent clause as a sis

ter of the degree word which licenses it this p ermits us to express the

coo ccurence restrictions b etween degree word and extent clause as normal

complement selection The account adopted by eg Selkirk is to

generate the extent clause adjacent to the degree word and extrap ose it

to the end of the adjective phrase eg as as a house big as big as

a house Likewise for relative clauses the that I read book the book

that I read The DegP analysis op ens another p ossibility we can generate

the extent clause as sister to the degree word in its surface p osition

DegP DP

Deg AP CP D NP CP

as A as you want the N that I read

big book



Admittedlythisisa very curious construction whose syntax is not at all clear It

app ears to involve the exceptional selection of a PP by the determiner

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

In this way the DegP analysis allows us to preserve the selectional rela

tion b etween degree word and extent clause without assuming systematic

obligatory displacement of extent clauses from their dstructure p osition

In fairness though wemust observe that this analysis do es not elimi

nate all cases of extent clause extrap osition Extentclause extrap osition is

necessary even under the DegP analysis for examples like

a a more b eautiful woman than Id ever seen

b as much to o much as last time

Two Sp eciers in the Adjective Phrase

If we could show that there are two distinct sp ecier p ositions in the ad

jective phrase as in the noun phrase that would constitute supp ortive

evidence for the DegP analysis inasmuch as the DegP analysis but not the

standard analysis provides a sp ecier p osition b oth under DegP and under

AP

Consider for example adjectives with adverbs but without degree words

as in

thoroughly b efuddled

hop elessly lost

entirely dark

understandably distressed

obviously content

Is the structure that of a or b

a DegP b DegP

DegP Deg Deg AP

Adv

Deg AP DegP A

obviously Adv

content content

obviously

It is dicult to nd clear cases of degree words coo ccuring with fol

lowing adverbs where the structure is clearly that of b Usuallyitis

at least arguable that the degree word has scop e over the adverb not the

adjective

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

a so thoroughly b efuddled

b to o obviously content

c so heavily favored to win

Consider for instance the contrast

he was to o content to get up

he was to o obviously content to get up

cf he was to o obviously content for us to have the heart to disturb

him

Likewise adjectival passivesaswehave seen do not accept degree words

so favoredtowin indicating that the structure of c is as given there

In other cases the unavailability of degree words seems to b e traceable

to the adverb involved

to o entirely mixedup

cf to o mixedup

entirely mixedup

to o entirely

so always right

cf so right

always right

so always

But since the adverb contributes to the meaning of the AP even under

b this do es not seem to constitute decisive evidence in favor of a

The question extends to the other two categories app earing in Sp ec

of Deg viz measure noun phrase and quantier phrase Wehave for

instance

a two miles long

three years old

b much alike

little dierent

Here there are clear meaning dierences two miles is clearly dep endenton

too in two miles toolong but on long in two miles long On the other hand



b is somewhat misleading in that alike and dierent are the only adjectives

which take noncomparative nonsup erlative quantiers

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

if there is an emptyDegin two miles longwiththeinterpretation p osi

tive degree the dierence in interpretation can b e accounted for without

assuming a dierence in syntactic attachment

With the measure phrases a preceding degree word is imp ossible

a to o two miles long

as three years old

b to o miles long

as years old

The a examples are arguably semantically illformed b eing doubly sp ec

ied Even without a numeral in the noun phrase though the examples

are still bad as the b examples show

The imp ort of the discussion so far is that it is dicult to nd clearcut

examples deciding one way or the other However I b elieve the example

do es give clear indication that the lower sp ecier p osition is necessary

If its already needlessly long it wont hurt to make it six inches

more needlessly long will it

In this case need lessly is clearly within the scop e of moreyet more mo dies

long not need lessly

I conclude that the adjective as well as Deg takes adverb quantier

and measurenounphrase sp eciers The full structure of the adjective

phrase excluding complements is then



The only exceptions are examples that are arguably adjective comp ounds suchas

eonsold as eonsold as the cities of Babylon Eonsold is dierent from eg years old

in that it can app ear inside a noun phrase despite b eing plural

i an eonsold statue

a years old statue

cf

six years old

a six years old b oy

a sixyearold b oy

THE ADJECTIVE PHRASE

DegP

qp Deg

mp

advp Deg AP

qp A

mp

advp A

where qp mp and advp are abbreviations for DegP DP

Q measure

and DegP resp ectively

Adv

Overview of Structures

To sum up these last two sections I give in the full range of sp ecier

structures whichJackendo argues for

N Deg

Art N Deg

N

Q A N Q Deg

N N

N Deg

A Q

Deg A Deg Q

Q A Adv Q

N

Adv A Q

Adv P

Deg Adv P

Q Adv Q P

Adv N

Adv Adv P

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

I have added the Adv under Q I b elieve Jackendo omitted it only

b ecause he had not intro duced the category Q in the chapter in which

he discussed adverbs Clearly there are adverbs in QP suciently many

exceedingly few

Under the DP and DegP analysis the structures of translate

into those of again recall that mp qp and advp abbrevi

ate DP DegP and DegP resp ectively

measure Q Adv

DP DegPQAdv

DP D mp Deg

qp

D NP advp Deg APQAdv

mp DegP N mp A

qp qp

N advp A

PP

mp P

qp

advp P

These structures dier in empirical predictions from Jackendo in that

they conate adjective phrase adverb phrase and quantier phrase all as

DegP and predict that there should b e measurephrase quantierphrase

and adverbphrase sp eciers in all three Adverb phrases are attested in all

three but measure phrases are not attested in adverb phrases or quantier

phrases and quantier phrases are not attested in quantier phrases The

lackofquantier phrases in quantier phrases is not surprisingthere are

only two adjectives dierent alike that take quantier phrases and only

one adverb dierently The lack of measure phrases I leave unaccounted

for

In conclusion the DPDegP analysis is quite adequate to capture the

full range of English sp ecier structures in fact it makes ro om in a two

bar Xbar theory for the distinctions whichJackendo needed three bars

to make

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

The Position of Prenominal Adjectives

Two Hyp otheses

Having considered the internal structure of the adjective phrase I would

like to return to a question we p ostp oned in section namely the place of

prenominal adjective phrases within the noun phrase

Jackendo assumed prenominal adjective phrases were sisters of N

Translating into the DPanalysis

DP

D NP

qp ap ap N

N

There are two problems with this analysis it esp ouses an arbitrary

numb er of sp eciers of N and it do es not capture the scop e relations

between the sp eciers of N This is most clear with syncategorematic

adjectives Consider the example an al leged lb canaryIfal leged

lb and canary are all sisters wewould exp ect the op eration bywhich

N

their meanings are combined to b e asso ciative and commutative Obviously

though an alleged lb canary is not the same thing as a lb alleged

canary the latter weighs lbs while the former might not

A second and mucholderhyp othesis is that prenominal adjective

phrases are adjoined to a nominal pro jection presumably Nbar

DP

D NP

qp N

ap N

ap N

N

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

A problem with this analysis is that it esp ouses adjunction in the base

and furthermore adjunction to a nonmaximal categoryAnembarassing

question is why there are no elements adjoined to any other singlebar

pro jection at dstructure not to V P A I C etc

A problem for b oth of these hyp otheses is that there is a range of evi

dence which suggests that prenominal adjectives are in some sense heads of

the noun phrases in which they app ear I present this evidence in the next

section

Adjective as Head of NP

a To o Big a House

There is one set of examples in which it app ears wehavenochoice but to

take adjectives as heads of noun phrases

to o big a house

yea long a sh

howoldaman

to o smart a racco on

Examples like this are not discussed byJackendo though they are dis

cussed at length by Bresnan What sets these examples apart is

that the noun phrase app ears to b e a complement of the adjective In some

dialects including myown there can b e an interp osed of

to o big of a house

as nice of a man

how long of a b oard

This suggests a structure like

DegP

Deg AP

too big PPDP

of a house

The only alternative app ears to b e to take toobigto b e some sort of sp ecier

of a house p ossibly

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

DP

DegP D

too big a NP

of house

This leaves of dangling though without a satisfactory attachment site

What is remarkable ab out the structure is that despite b eing

headed by an adjective the phrase as a whole b ehaves like a noun phrase

not like an adjective phrase

a Ilive in to o big of a house

b Ilive in a mansion to o big to clean

I live in a mansion to o big of a house

This indicates that it is p ossible for an adjective to pro ject a phrase which

is interpreted like a noun phrasebut only when it takesanounphrase

complement I live in too big An explanation ready at hand is that the

relation b etween big and a house in too big of a house is fselection and

that the adjective inherits certain nominal features from the noun phrase

it fselects This hyp othesis explains two additional facts Adjectives

are not Casemarkers yet the noun phrase app ears without a prep osition

in too big a house If the noun phrase is fselected it is not an argument

hence do es not require Case The noun phrase complementmust b e

predicative not referential and it cannot b e extracted

a I live in to o big that house

b whichhousedoyou live in to o big of t

a house I live in to o big of t

This indicates again that the noun phrase is not an argument fselected

complements are in general not arguments

In sum examples like too big of a house indicate that devices are

necessary which p ermit adjectives to head phrases that b ehave like and

are interpreted like noun phrases The indep endent need for such devices

op ens the way for an analysis of prenominal adjectives in which they head

the noun phrase they app ear in In the next subsections I consider evi

dence that suggests that some such analysis is the right analysis Most of

The interpretation of a would b e I live in that house which is to o big

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

the facts I consider involve dierences in the b ehavior of prenominal and

p ostnominal adjectives If b oth are simply syntactic and semantic mo diers

of the head noun diering only in which side of the noun they app ear on

these dierences are not exp ected

b Complements

Prenominal adjectives dier from p ostnominal adjectives in that prenominal

adjectives may not have complements whereas p ostnominal adjectives must

have complements

a the proud man

the proud of his son man

b the man proud

the man proud of his son

There are exceptions to the requirement that p ostnominal adjectives have

complements First it is sucienttohave conjoined adjectives p ostnom

inally a man bruisedandbattered Second it is sometimes sucientto

have a sp ecier for the adjective a sh this big asteak just right Third

there are a handful of adjectives which can app ear p ostnominally with

out complements a man alone the man responsible six dol lars even

the example fol lowing etc Fourth indenite pronouns p ermit p ostnomi

nal adjectives without complements as noted by Smith someone

bold something terrible etc though if our analysis in section d is

correct these last examples only app ear to involve p ostnominal adjectives

and actually involve prenominal adjectives where the noun has b een raised

to D

If prenominal adjectives fselect NP as complement the lackofthe

adjectives usual complements is explained

DP

D AP

a A NP

proud man

An analogy that is suggestive is that of auxiliary verbs It is sometimes

supp osed that auxiliary verbs are verbs that take VPs and pro ject VPs

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

Averb like have can take eg a noun phrase when it app ears as a main

verb but not when it app ears as an auxiliary in the same waywe might

supp ose adjectives cannot take their usual complements when they app ear

as auxiliary nouns Wehave already noted the very close syntactic simi

laritybetween A and N Plausibly adjectives are defective nouns let us

supp ose that they lack only one feature say substantive to b e nouns

If prenominal adjectives are like auxiliary verbs and take an NP comple

ment it is conceivable that they inherit their complements substantive

sp ecication and hence pro ject a category that is featurally indistinct from

an NP

c Mere and Utter

There are certain adjectives suchasmere and utter that app ear only in

prenominal p osition never in p ostnominal or predicative p osition

the utter indignity cf the big ball

the indignityisutter the ball is big

the indignity utter and unrelenting the ball big and round

We could say that these adjectives are exceptional only in obligatorily f

selecting an NP complement

d Semantics

Something must b e said ab out the semantics of adjectives when they f

select noun phrase complements Wehave assumed that adjectives denote

attributes yet obviously a big house or toobigahouse do es not denote

a quantity of bigness but rather a house Obviously big has dierent

semantic values dep ending on whether it fselects a noun phrase or not

Let us supp ose that there is a general function Aux converting adjective

meanings to auxiliary noun meanings as a rst approximation

AuxF eGaFae Ge

For example the translation of black cat will b e

A NP

Actually featurally indistinct is probably to o strong It app ears that prenominal

adjectives do app ear with degree words as we will discuss b elow If degree words take

prenominal adjectives as complements and prenominal adjectives are featurally indis

tinct from NPs wewould exp ect degree words to take NPs as complementswhichis

of course false Therefore wemust consider prenominal adjectives and NPs distinct

Determiners are not sensitive to the distinction but degree words are

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Auxblackcat

eGablackae Ge cat

eablackae cate

where blackae i black a Themeea

If the function Aux seems just a ploy for making adjectives t semanti

cally into an unwonted syntactic frame there is a class of adjectivesthe

syncategorematic adjectiveswhichintheirbasic meaning must takeNP

as argument A standard example is al leged The meaning of the adjective

al leged is derived from the meaning of the verb al lege in a manner something

along the following lines

alleged xFeyallegeeFxy

where allegeePx i allege e ThemePe Agentxe ie e is a

situation of x alleging that P The translation of al leged Communist is

xeyallegeeCommunistxy

It is sometimes p ossible for syncategorematic adjectives to app ear in

p ositions other than prenominal p osition ie without an NP complement

In these cases wemaytake the adjectivetobeintransitivized by supply

ing the ob ject from context That is the intransitivized reading for al leged

is

xeyallegeeFxy

where the predicate F is supplied from context Thus the translation of a

Communist al leged but not proven is

Y Y xGx where

G xCommunistx allegedx provenx

xCommunistx eyallegeeFxy

where context determines that FCommunist

This accounts for the dierence in meaning b etween a Communist al

leged but not provenandan al leged Communist but not a proven Commu

nist The former denotes a Communist but the latter may fail to denote

aCommunist as predicted by the translations wehave assigned to these

noun phrases and resp ectively This indicates that for the

syncategorematic adjectives prenominal and p ostnominal adjectives dier

precisely in whether they take the NP as an argument or not

If there is a class of adjectives which take NPs as complements in a

nonvacuous mannerthe syncategorematic adjectives then the semantic

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

typ eraising function Aux b ecomes rather less suspicious in that it is

not simply a warping of the semantics of adjectives to make them t an

unintuitive syntax but rather the optional assimilation of one class of

adjectives to the semantic structure of another indep endent class so that

b oth may app ear in the same syntactic structure

e Comparatives

Another dierence b etween pre and p ostnominal adjectives is illustrated

in the following contrast discussed at length by Bresnan

a I havenever known a taller man than my mother

b Ihavenever known a man taller than my mother

Bresnan assumes that the identity of the deleted phrase in the thanclause is

determined by the phrase to which the thanclause is adjoined at sstructure

In a the clause adjoined to is a tal ler man hence the reconstructed

thanclause is than my mother is a X tal l man In b on the other

hand the than clause is adjoined to tal ler and the reconstructed clause is

than my mother is X tal l

If it is the sstructure p osition of the than clause which determines its

content however it is dicult to account for sentences like

a taller man arrived than Bill

In this case than Bil l is presumably adjoined to the sentence a tal ler man

arrived Reconstruction of the thanclause yields the nonsensical than Bil l

was an X tall man arrived This indicates that the than clause must

b e reconstructed at LF after the thanclause itself has b een restored to

its presstructure p osition in the noun phrase If the thanclause can b e

restored to the p osition of one of its traces b efore having its internal struc

ture reconstructed however we should b e able to move than my mother in

a backinto the AP from which it came b efore we reconstruct it

a taller than my mother man

a taller than my mother is X tall man

Thus Bresnan would incorrectly predict that a tal ler man than my mother

do es have a nonanomalous interpretation

Under the analysis in which adjectives take NPcomplements on the

other hand the explanation is straightforward at all levels of representa

tion er has scop e over tal l man in a but only over tal l in b it

is the scop e of er not the attachmentofthan S that determines how the

than clause is to b e reconstructed

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

a aer tall man than my mother

AP NP

b a man er tall than my mother

AP

It is the scop e of er not the attachmentofthe thanclause that determines

howthe thanclause is to b e reconstructed

f Determination of Noun Phrase Typ e

A prenominal adjective can determine the typ e of the noun phrase in a way

that p ostnominal adjectives cannot There is a contrast b etween predica

tive the term used by Bresnan and nonpredicative noun phrases

Certain contexts select for one or the other Bresnan uses the ob ject p osi

tion of know for instance when it is not emb edded under a mo dal or neg

ative as a context that selects nonpredicative noun phrases Ive known

many dogs Ive known a dog like Fido Under a negativeormodal

b oth are p ermitted Ive never known many dogs Ive never known a dog

like FidoNow consider

a Ivenever known a smarter dog than Fido

Iveknown a smarter dog than Fido

b Ivenever known a dog smarter than Fido

Ive known a dog smarter than Fido

Noun phrases with prenominal comparatives count as predicative in the

desired sense hence are barred from complement p osition of nonnegative

know but noun phrases with p ostnominal comparatives are p ermitted in

this p osition Noun phrases with predeterminer APs b ehavelike noun

phrases with prenominal adjectives Ive never known as smart of a dog

as Fido Ive known as smart of a dogasFido

It app ears that the predicative nature of the comparative adjective

p ercolates to the enclosing noun phrase from prenominal p osition but

not from p ostnominal p osition Determining the features of the enclosing

phrase is a prop ertytypical of heads

g Idioms

For completeness sake I will mention a nal dierence b etween pre and

p ostnominal adjectives though I have no explanation for it Certain adjec

tives in idiomatic usages are excluded from prenominal p osition

a a thrown party

p

cf a thrown ball

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

b a party thrown on Saturday

the party planned and the party thrown were twovery dierent

parties

If this do es not provide evidence for the adjectiveashead analysis it do es

emphasize the p oint that there are substantial dierences b etween pre and

p ostnominal adjectives

TwoMore Hyp otheses

a AP vs DegP

If we adopt the hyp othesis that prenominal adjectives fselect NP com

plements there are twomajorvariants to cho ose b etween diering as to

whether a prenominal adjective phrase is a DegP or a bare AP

a DP b DP

D AP D DegP

A NP Deg AP

N A NP

N

a seems a priori preferable for the following reason Wehave as

sumed that D necessarily selects a F category in order to explain the

illformedness of eg the each boy eachboy is a F category hence

DP

not a legitimate complement for the Note that the problem is not se

mantic the wordforword translation of the each boy is grammatical in

Hungarian If this is correct it rules out the structure b DegP is a

F category In fact if prenominal adjectives inherit the feature subst

from their NP complements the APs in are featurally indistinct from

NPs and the DegP in b is featurally indistinct from DP

This app ears to b e corrob orated by examples like the following

a a to o tall man

a so big sh

cf

b a man to o tall to b e a submariner a sh so big

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

The nonapp earance of Degs do es not entail the elimination of the Sp ec

of APhowever And in fact we nd eg adverbs in prenominal AP

DP

D AP

a DegP A

very A NP

big dog

More subtle yet more striking evidence against b and in favor of

a is provided by the fact that all marked sp eciers of degree words

are excluded in prenominal p osition

a six millimeters to o narrow lens

your six grams to o heavy counterbalance

a six times as eective medication

a several seconds quicker time

cf

six millimeters to o narrow

six grams to o heavy

six times as eective

several seconds quicker

This is not the result of a general prohibition against measure phrases

buried inside prenominal adjective phrases If the measure phrase is more

deeply buried the examples improve even though they b ecome more dif

cult to pro cess

their six millimeters to o narrowly ground lens

your six grams to o heavily weighted counterbalance

a six times as eectively administered medication

Further if the measure phrase is not in the sp ecier of the degree word

but in the sp ecier of the adjective itself it is acceptable



Admittedly when the measure phrases are plural their acceptability degrades sub

stantially

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

a six inch long p encil

a six millimeter wide lens

a several month long hiatus

This otherwise mysterious array of facts is predicted under the analysis

a The examples of are ungrammatical b ecause there is no Deg

allowed hence no Sp ec of Deg for measure phrases to o ccupy In contrast

the examples of and have the analyses which are well

formed

DP DP

D AP D AP

a DegP A a DP A

DP Deg A NP six inch A NP

six times Deg AP administered N long pencil

as effectively medication

The facts of not only supp ort a over b they also

supp ort a over the other two p ossible analyses of prenominal adjective

attachment discussed at the b eginning of this section As far as I can see

the only analysis that can account naturally for is a

b Quantiers

If we adopt the analysis a wemust reconsider the p osition of quanti

ers If quantier phrases app ear in Sp ec of N and prenominal adjectives

take NP as complement we predict that quantiers are grammatical fol

lowing adjectives but ungrammatical preceding adjectives

i a six inches long p encil

a six millimeters wide lens

etc

By the same token singular measure phrases are not very go o d in predicate aps

ii the p encil is six inch long

the lens is six millimeter wide

etc

Ihave no explanation

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

DP DP

D AP D AP

A NP qp A

qp N A NP

N N

Of course just the opp osite is in fact the case

The alternative is to revise our earlier analysis and assume that quan

tiers like descriptive adjectives app ear on the path that leads from DP

to N

DP

D QP

exceedingly Q

Q AP

many very A

A NP

beautiful women

There is some evidence in favor of this analysis In particular there is

evidence that comparative and sup erlative adjectives are quantiers We

have already seen evidence that comparatives and sup erlatives takeanNP

complement therefore wehave p ositive evidence that at least some quan

tiers take NP complements

This is the evidence that comparative and sup erlative adjectives are

quantiers comparatives and sup erlatives must precede all descriptive

adjectives

a big fancy car the big fancy car

a big fancier car the big fanciest car

a fancier big car the fanciest big car

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

comparatives and sup erlatives license partitives and missing noun heads

the b etter of the two will win

the b est of all will win

This is otherwise a prop erty solely of determiners and quantiers

each of the men will win

several of the men will win

many of the men will win

few of the men will win

the many go o d of the men will win

an old of the men will win

b eautiful of the women will win

The analysis provides us with a simple characterization of the ele

ments that license missing noun heads and partitive We can say that there

is a unique emptynounwhich takes the partitive ofphrase as an optional

complement N Determiners and quantiers select N but descriptive

e e

adjectives do not Under this account there is a hierarchy of selectional

prop erties

D selects NPAPNP QP

e

Q selects NPAPNP

e

A selects NPAP

Given these lexical selection prop erties we correctly predict a large part of

the range of internal noun phrase structures

c Problems

The analysis I have argued fora supplemented with app ears

to account most successfully for the broadest range of data of the four

analyses I have considered in this section However there are a couple

of dicult residual problems One is that we are left with no sp eciers

within NP I consider this problem minor for two reasons if adjectives

corresp ond to auxiliaries and NP corresp onds to VP then the absence

of sp eciers of NP corresp onds to the absence of obvious candidates for

Sp ec of VP the lack of Sp ec of NP might seem to undermine one of

our arguments on b ehalf of Detashead presented in section that there



There are of course the examples like the poor but these are quite restricted in

English they are p ossible only when they t the template the A Cf a poor is

pl

among us poor are always among us the old poor are always among us etc

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

are to o many sp eciers in the noun phrase for the standard analysis to

accommo date But wehave only eliminated Sp ec of N by adopting an even

more radical version of the Detashead analysis one in which adjectives

are heads of noun phrases as well Further even if wehavenoSpecofN

we do still have sp eciers of complements of D namelywhenQPorAP

are complements of D

A more serious problem is that we are left with no analysis for examples

like the following

the nearly as many men who didnt makeit

a nearly as devastating attack

These examples suggest that the illformedness of examples like a too

beautiful woman is the result of a surface constraint against adjacent Ds and

Degs not the result of a structural constraint against DegP complements

of D

I will suggest a p ossible approach to this problem though I must note

from the outset that my solution is not fully satisfactory

A rst observation is that Degs vary widely in their ability to app ear

in structures like In my judgment the b est examples are with er

and est or more and most as degree wordsthese are go o d even without

an intervening adverb With an intervening adverb as is rather go o d and

too sometimes other Degs suchasso that are never go o d

I havenever b efore encountered a nearly so virulent strain

I havenever b efore seen a quite that b eautiful woman

cf

p

I havenever b efore encountered a strain nearly so virulent

p

I havenever b efore seen a woman quite that b eautiful

Let us b egin with er and estAsmentioned these Degs app ear con

sistently under determiners even without an intervening adverb

the b etter man

the b est man

There are even examples that seem to show that er and est app ear

under Degs

a he do es it the b est of all

b he ran the quicker of the two

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

c the quicker you run the quicker Ill catchyou

d the b etter to eat you with

All of these phrases function as adverbs not arguments For this reason

their structure would app ear to b e eg

DegP

Deg AP

the best

ie thelike that can function b oth as a Det and as a Deg I do not adopt

this analysis however b ecause of the fact that partitive of is licensed in

these structures see ab I have assumed that partitive of is licensed

only byN this requires the structure for the examples

e

DP

D AP

the A NP

better N PP

e of the two

We can take these to b e bareNP adverbs as Larson christens

examples like yesterday The prop er semantics are obtained by allowing N

e

to range over adverb meanings manners sp eeds etc

The abilityof er and est to coo ccur with determiners seems clearly to

b e related to the fact that they are axes It is rather reminiscent of cases

of doubled determiners in languages like Norwegian and Soninke that have

axal determiners In Norwegian doubled determiners are not normally

grammatical but doubling do es o ccur when the second determiner is the

denite ax en

denne hver sko

this each sho e

 Data from Hellan

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

denne skoen

this sho ethe

Similarly in Soninke a Mande language of Mali doubled determiners are

p ermitted when the second determiner is the axal denite determiner

ke samaqen

this snakethe

These examples suggest that there is a constraint against doublylled

Dets at sstructure but not at LF The axal determiner can raise at LF

yielding eg

denne en skot

DP D i NP N i

A similar pro cess is necessary in English if we are to assume that the de

terminer is the site of Phifeatures as I suggested earlier hence that the

plural morpheme must raise into a p ossibly lled Det at LF

Let us return to comparatives and sup erlatives now We can assign the

following wellformed LF to comparatives and sup erlatives under determin

ers

aer prettyt girl

DP D i AP i NP

If this is correct it implies that examples like as prettiest are not

ungrammatical b ecause there are two Degs er should b e able to raise

into a lled Deg in the same way it raises into a lled Detbut rather for

semantic reasons presumably for the same reasons that examples like very

so pretty are out

The structure is not available for Degs other than er and est

b ecause other Degs must b e basegenerated in the DegDet p osition not

axed to adjectives

However more and most behave just like er and est with resp ect to

their ability to app ear under determiners

a more b eautiful woman

the most b eautiful woman

One p ossibility is that these are simply quantiers in Sp ec of A the com

parative and sup erlativeofmuch As has long b een puzzled over though

Bresnan Jackendo this leaves unexplained why much



Data from myown eld work conducted in



The intended reading is not as much prettier where as takes scop e over er not

prettybut rather something like as prettywhichistosay the prettiest

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

in the p ositive degree is illformed in these examples a much beautiful

woman

Iwould like to suggest that more and most are exactly like er and est in

every resp ect except that they are not phonological axes In particular

I suggest that they are syntactic axes much like ing They ax to

AP and raise into DegDet at LF in this way they escap e the sstructure

prohibition on doublylled D

SS DP DP

D AP D AP

more AP A NP

A NP A er N

N

LF DP D a morei AP ti AP beautiful woman

The subtree more AP is licensed by morphological conditions not by

AP

Xbar theory More is not adjoined to AP rather it is the head of more

AP

AP in the same waythat er is the head of A er Hence more o ccupies

A

an Ap osition not an Abar p osition and its raising into DegDet is prop er

movement

In short I prop ose that there are certain elementsmore and most

which are not phonologically axes but nonetheless b ehave syntactically

like axes

Possibly a similar analysis can b e applied to problematic cases like a

nearly as devastating attack As I noted only certain Degs can app ear

in these structures and then only sp oradically and with large variances in

sp eaker judgments There also app ear to b e idiosyncratic PF constraints

on the pro cess In addition to the prohibition against stringadjacent Dets

and Degs there is a prohibition against monosyllabic adjectives in this

construction a nearly as long interview vs a nearly as lengthy inter

view These facts suggest that whatever pro cess is involved it is rather

marked A reasonable hyp othesis is that Degs other than more and most

are sp oradically reanalyzed as syntactic axes as more and most havedone

completely As is fairly susceptible to this reanalysis too somewhat less so

and so and that not at all

Some tenuous supp ort for this hyp othesis is supplied by examples like

his tooeager grin where too actually app ears adjacent to a determiner but

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

there is a strong intuition that it forms a comp ound with eager in some

sense Under the presenthyp othesis it comp ounds with eager in that it

is a syntactic ax on the AP headed by eager

A nal stumblingblo ck is the fact that not only adjectives and quanti

ers but also measure nouns t into the paradigm of anearly as devastat

ing attack Consider

the a dozen men who came

the nearly a dozen men who came

In this case there are two courses op en to us We might assume that a

reanalyzes as an ax on dozen Alternativelyitmay b e that a dozen is in

fact an NPnotaDPPerlmutter argues that a is not a determiner

but a reduced form of the numeral one Whether his analysis is correct

or not there are certain advantagesthataccruetotakinga to have some

analysis other than as a determiner There is a class of phrases of the form

aANPthat are set apart from argumental noun phrases in a number of

ways Examples are

to o big a house

a monster of a problem

two of a kind

Semantically these phrases are predicates not arguments The examples

of are interpreted very roughly as

to obigx housex

monsterx problemx

twoX ofakindX

In particular the aphrases do not intro duce a separate variable ranging

over ob jects but are simply predicates which are applied to the variable

intro duced by the matrix phrase

Corresp ondingly these phrases can never b e extracted

a house thats to o big of

a problem thats a monster of

a kind theyre twoof

only to o big of was available of a house

a monster of came up of a problem

two of were there of a kind

THE POSITION OF PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES

Both of these facts would b e explained if the aphrases in question were

NPs not DPs NPs are predicates not arguments NPs cannot b e extra

p osed like DPs If this is correct we can take nearly a dozen in the nearly

a dozen men who came to b e an NP not a DP

An added b enet is that singular and plural dozen dier markedly less

under this analysis than under most analyses Consider the paradigm

a dozen men

dozens of men Pseudopartitive

dozens of the men Partitive

Under the current analysis the structures are

a DP b DP c DP

D NP D NP D NP

N NP N KP N KP

dozen men dozens of NP dozens of DP

men the men

Dozen diers from dozens only in that it fselects an NP rather than a

KP Dozens fselects either an argumental KP one containing a DP or a

predicative KP one containing an NP recall that pseudopartitives ie

b cannot b e extracted whichwould b e explained if they are NPs

p

not DPs severaltwere asked of the questions concerning electro

magnetism

In its current state this solution to the problems which face the Adj

ashead analysis is based on somewhat scanty evidence and to that extent

sp eculative I must leave renements or a new and more adequate solution

to future research

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Conclusion

To sum up the Detashead analysis is thoroughly defensible and has a

number of advantages over the standard analysis The chief motivation

for adopting the Detashead analysis is conceptual however The DP

analysis p ermits us to preserve the same restrictivecharacterization of X

bar theory which motivates the IPanalysis of the sentence and the Det

ashead analysis involves assigning determiners an analysis which parallels

current analyses of other functional elements such as complementizers and

mo dals Further the Detashead analysis provides ro om for the full

range of sp eciers found in the noun phrase

Supp ort for this analysis of determiners is derived from examination

of the adjective phrase In English noun phrase and adjective phrase

have a great deal in common including the existence of degree elements

as adjectivephrase correlates of determiners in the noun phrase I argue

that degree elements are exactly parallel to determiners and accordingly

head the adjective phrase DegP This provides two distinct sp ecier

p ositions in the adjective phrase in addition to the p osition of the degree

word and I argue that as in the noun phrase all p ositions are exploited

More generally I argue that there are two ma jor dichotomies of syn

tactic categories functional elements F vs thematic elements F and

nominal elements N vs verbal elements N I havegiven lengthycharac

terizations of the distinction b etween functional and thematic elements the

most imp ortant structural dierences are that functional elements do not

p ossess a distinct index from that of their complement and that functional

element p ositions are sites for AGR hence functional categories but not

thematic categories freely takeovert sub jects

The functionalthematic and nominalverbal dichotomies are extremely

robust much more so than the alleged dichotomybetween V elements

VA and V elements NP For this reason I challenge the traditional

four ma jor categories NVAP also b ecause the notional category ad

jective do es not corresp ond to a single category with a stable syntactic

characterization but rather to two distinct categories one a sub category

of verbs the other a sub category of nouns the latter b eing predominate in

English

My discussion of the feature comp osition of syntactic categories is spread

throughout the thesis I would like to sum up here I recognize at least

ve features F N Adj Q C F and N are the ma jor features

Adj distinguishes nouns from nominaltyp e adjectives presumably we

should also use it to distinguish verbs from verbaltyp e adjectives C



Another p ossibility is to distinguish nouns and nominaltyp e adjectives by a feature

CONCLUSION

distinguishes inherently Casemarked elements ie adverbs including

bareNP adverbs bareadjective adverbs and adverbs in ly It is rel

evant only for FN categories Q distinguishes quanticational and

descriptive adjectives It is relevant only for FNAdj categories

The complete set of distinctions for the features F N and Adj is

the following

Adj Adj

N N N N

F VP N AQAdv

F IC DK Deg

It is not clear where P b elongs Perhaps languages dier as to whether

P is N or N I am thinking particularly of languages likeMayan where

Ps are very similar to nouns

It is not clear what feature distinguishes I from C and D from K but

presumably it is the same feature in b oth cases

Possibly there are FNAdj elements in other languages ie verbal

typ e adjectives It is not clear that there are FNAdj elements in any

language

To rep eat the central claim emb o died in the distribution of categories

is that there are two ma jor dichotomies functional vs thematic

elements and nominal vs verbal elements and that functional elements

o ccupy a uniform structural p osition in b oth nominal and verbal systems

The thrust of the presentwork is that the nominal system is not defective

but p ossesses a functional element D on a par with the functional elements

I and C of the verbal system

Aux whichwewould also use to distinguish verbs and auxiliaries I have not taken

that p osition here b ecause I have claimed that only prenominal adjectives pattern with auxiliaries

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Biblio graphy

Abney S Comp ms MIT

Abney S Some Topics Relevant to Sub categorization Generals

pap er MIT

Abney S Functional Elements and Licensing pap er presented to

GLOW Gerona Spain

Abney S in preparation A Semantics for GB ms MIT Cambridge

MA

Amritavalli R Expressing CrossCategorial Selectional Corresp on

dences An Alternative to the Xbar Syntax Approach Linguistic

Analysis

Anderson M Noun Phrase Structure Do ctoral dissertation Univer

sity of Connecticutt Storrs CT

Anderson M Prenominal Genitive NPs The Linguistic Review

Aoun J AGrammarofAnaphora Linguistic Inquiry Monograph

No MIT Press Cambridge MA

Aoun J D Sp ortiche On the Formal Theory of Government

The Linguistic Review

Aristotle The Poetics published with a translation by W Hamilton

Fyfe Lo eb Classical Library Harvard University Press Cambridge

MA

Arono M WordFormation in Generative Grammar Linguistic

Inquiry Monograph No MIT Press Cambridge MA

Bach E The noun phrase in E Bach RT Harms eds Univer

sals of Linguistic Theory Holt Rinehart and Winston New York

Baker M a The Mirror Principle and Morphological Explanation

Linguistic Inquiry

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Baker M b Incorporation A Theory of Grammatical Function Chang

ing Do ctoral dissertation MIT Cambridge MA

Baker M c Syntactic Axation and English Gerunds in Cobler

et al eds Proceedings of the West Coast ConferenceofFormal

Linguistics Stanford UniversityPalo Alto CA

Baker M K Johnson I Rob erts Explicit Passive Arguments

talk presented at MIT Cambridge MA

Barss A H Lasnik A Note on Anaphora and Double Ob jects

Linguistic Inquiry

Barwise J and R Co op er Generalized Quantiers and Natural

Language Linguistics and Philosophy

Belletti A Unaccusatives as Case Assigners Lexicon Pro ject Work

ing Pap ers Center for Cognitive Science MIT Cambridge MA

Belletti A L Rizzi PsychVerbs and theory ms MIT b oth

Scuole Normale Sup eriore di Pisa Belletti and Universite de Gen

eve Rizzi

Bolinger D Degree Words Mouton The Hague

Bowers JS a Adjectives and Adverbs in English Foundations of

Language

Bowers JS b Some Adjectival Nominalizations in English Lingua

Brame M The General Theory of Binding and Fusion Linguistic

Analysis

Brame M The HeadSelector Theory of Lexical Sp ecications and

the Nonexistence of Coarse Categories Linguistic Analysis

Bresnan J Syntax of the Comparative Clause Construction in En

glish Linguistic Inquiry

Chao W On El lipsis Do ctoral dissertation University of Mas

sachusetts Amherst MA

Chomsky N The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory published

The University of Chicago Press Chicago

Chomsky N Remarks on Nominalization in R Jacobs P Rosen

baum eds Readings in English Transformational GrammarGinn

Waltham MA

Chomsky N On WHMovement in P Culicover T Wasow A

Akma jian eds Formal Syntax Academic Press New York

CONCLUSION

Chomsky N Lectures on Government and BindingForis Publica

tions Dordrecht Holland

Chomsky N a Barriers Linguistic Inquiry Monograph No MIT

Press Cambridge MA

Chomsky N b Know ledge of Language Praeger Publications New

York

Davidson D Essays on Actions and Events Clarendon Press Ox

ford

Dayley A Tzutujil Grammar University of California Press Berkeley

and Los Angeles

Dixon RMW Where Have Al l the Adjectives Gone Mouton Am

sterdam

Emonds J Root and StructurePreserving Transformations Do ctoral

dissertation MIT Cambridge MA

Emonds J Derived Nominals Gerunds and Participles in Chaucers

English in B Kachrun ed Issues in Linguistics University of Illi

nois Press

Emonds J A Unied Theory of Syntactic CategoriesForis Dor

drecht Holland

Fabb N Syntactic Axation Do ctoral dissertation MIT Cam

bridge MA

Fahlman S a NETL A System for Representing and Using Real

World Know ledge MIT Press

Fahlman S b Representing and Using RealWorld Knowledge Ar

ticial Intel ligence An MIT PerspectiveVol pp

Fassi Fehri Some Complement Phenomena in Arabic Lexical Gram

mar the Complementizer Phrase Hyp othesis and the NonAccessibility

Condition ms University of Rabat

Fiengo R J Higginb otham Opacity in NP Linguistic Analysis

Fiva T NPInternal Chains in Norwegian Nordic Journal of Lin

guistics

Grimshaw J Nouns Arguments and Adjuncts ms Brandeis Uni

versityWaltham MA

Grub er J Studies in Lexical Relations Do ctoral dissertation MIT

Cambridge MA

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Gueron J Clause Union and the VerbParticle Construction in

English ms Universite de Paris VI I I

Haegeman L Passivization in Flemish Dialects ms University

of Geneva

Hale K class at LSA Summer Institute Albuquerque NM cited in

G Lamontagne L Travis The Case Filter and the ECP

ms McGill UniversityMontreal

Hale K LM Jeanne P Platero papago in P Culicover T

Wasow A Akma jian eds Formal Syntax Academic Press New

York

Hellan L The Headedness of NPs in Norwegian Chapter of P

Muysken H van Riemsijk eds Features and ProjectionsForis

Publications Dordrecht Holland

Higginb otham J Linguistic Relations ms MIT Cambridge MA

Higginb otham J Logical Form Binding and Nominals Linguistic

Inquiry

Higginb otham J On Semantics Linguistic Inquiry

Higginb otham J a Elucidation of Meaning ms MIT

Higginb otham J b A Systematization ms MIT

Higginb otham J R May Questions quantiers and crossing

The Linguistic Review

Horn G On the Nonsentential Nature of the PossIng Construc

tion Linguistic Analysis

Horro cks G M Stavrou Bounding Theory and Greek Syntax

Evidence for Whmovement in NP ms St Johns College Cam

bridge

Hudson RA Arguments for a Nontransformational Grammar The

University of Chicago Press Chicago

Hudson RA WordGrammar Basil Blackwell Oxford

Jackendo R Quantiers in English Foundations of Language

Jackendo R Xbar Syntax A Study of Phrase Structure Linguistic

Inquiry Monograph No MIT Press Cambridge MA

Jesp ersen O AModern English Grammar George Allen

Unwin London

CONCLUSION

Kayne R a Unambiguous Paths Chapter of Connectedness and

Binary BranchingForis Publications Dordrecht The Netherlands

Kayne RS b Principles of Particle Constructions Chapter of J

Gueron HG Ob enauer JY Pollo ck eds Levels of Syntactic

Representation IIForis Publications Dordrecht Holland

Kayne RS LAccord du Particip e Passe en Francais et en Italien

Modeles Linguistiques

Klein E to app ear Comparatives in A von Stechow D Wunderlich

eds Handbook of SemanticsAthenaeum Verlag

Kornlt J Case Marking Agreement and Empty Categories in

Turkish Do ctoral dissertation Harvard Cambridge MA

Koster J Why Sub ject Sentences Dont Exist in SJ Keyser

ed Recent Transformational Studies in European Languages MIT

Press Cambridge MA

Kuro da SY Whether you agree or not ms University of Cali

fornia at San Diego San Diego CA

Larson RK BareNP Adverbs Linguistic Inquiry

Larson RK a On the Double Ob ject Construction ms MIT

Cambridge MA

Larson RK b Missing Prep ositions and the Analysis of English

Free Relative Clauses Linguistic Inquiry

Lasnik H Random Thoughts on Implicit Arguments ms Uni

versity of Connecticutt Storrs CT

Lasnik H J Kupin A restrictive theory of transformational gram

mar Theoretical Linguistics

Lasnik H M Saito On the Nature of Prop er Government

Linguistic Inquiry

Leb eaux D The Interpretation of Derived Nominals CLS Part

Lees RB The Grammar of English Nominalizations Do ctoral dis

sertation MIT Cambridge MA

Levin B M Rappap ort The Formation of Adjectival Passives

Lexicon Pro ject Working Pap ers The Center for Cognitive Sci

ence MIT Cambridge MA

Lieb er R On the Organization of the Lexicon Do ctoral dissertation

MIT Cambridge MA

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Lieb er R Argument Linking and Comp ounds in English Linguis

tic Inquiry

Lob eck A Syntactic Constraints on VP El lipsis Do ctoral disserta

tion UniversityofWashington

Marantz A On the NatureofGrammatical Relations Linguistic

Inquiry Monograph No MIT Press Cambridge MA

Makino S Some Aspects of Japanese NominalizationsTokai Uni

versity Press Tokyo

Milner JC Les genitifs adnominaux en francais in Ordres et

raisons de langue Editions du Seuil Paris

Montague R Formal Philosophy SelectedPapers of Richard Mon

tague RH Thomason ed Yale University Press New Haven CT

Nap oli DJ Verb phrase deletion in English a basegenerated anal

ysis J Linguistics

Perlmutter D On the Article in English in M Bierwisch KE

Heidolph eds Progress in Linguistics Mouton The Hague

Pesetsky D Paths and Categories Do ctoral dissertation MIT Cam

bridge MA

Pesetsky D Morphology and Logical Form Linguistic Inquiry

Plann S The Two el innitive Constructions in Spanish Lin

guistic Analysis

Postal PM On SoCalled Pronouns in English in D Reib el

S Schane eds Modern Studies in English PrenticeHall

Englewo o d Clis NJ

Postal PM On Raising MIT Press Cambridge MA

Poutsma H The Innitive the Gerund and the Participles of the

English VerbP No ordho Groningen

Quirk R S Greenbaum G LeechJSvartvik AComprehensive

Grammar of the English Language Longman New York

Rappap ort M a On the Nature of Derived Nominals ms MIT

Cambridge MA

Rappap ort M b Derived Nominals and the Theory of Lexical Cat

egories ms MIT Cambridge MA

Reed I et al Yupik Eskimo GrammarUniversity of Alaska

CONCLUSION

Reinhart T Syntactic Domains for Semantic Rules in F Guen

thner SJ Schmidt eds Formal Semantics and Pragmatics for

Natural Languages Reidel Dordrecht Holland

Reuland E Governing ing Linguistic Inquiry

Reuland E A Feature System for the Set of Categorial Heads

ms Rijksuniversiteit Groningen

Ritter E Genitive NPs in Hebrew A Functor Analysis Generals

Pap er MIT Cambridge MA

Ritter E A Szab olcsi Lets Take the Thatt Eect Seriously

ms MIT

Ro ep er T Implicit Arguments and the Pro jection Principle ms

University of Massachusetts Amherst MA

Rosenbaum P The Grammar of English Predicate Complement Con

structions The MIT Press Cambridge MA

Ross J Constraints on Variables in Syntax Do ctoral dissertation

MIT Cambridge MA

Ross J Nouniness in O Fujimura ed Three Dimensions of Lin

guistic Theory TEC CompanyTokyo Japan

Rothstein S The Syntactic Forms of Predication Do ctoral disserta

tion MIT Cambridge MA

Schachter P A Nontransformational Account of GerundiveNomi

nals in English Linguistic Inquiry

Selkirk E On the Determiner Systems of Noun Phrase and Adjec

tive Phrase ms MIT Cambridge MA

Selkirk E Some Remarks on Noun Phrase Structure in P Culi

cover T Wasow A Akma jian eds Formal Syntax Academic

Press New York

Selkirk E The Syntax of Words Linguistic Inquiry Monograph No

MIT Press Cambridge MA

Siegel D Topics in English Morphology Do ctoral dissertation MIT

Cambridge MA

Smith C A class of complex mo diers in English Language

pp

Sp ortiche D Structural Invariance and Symmetry in SyntaxDoc

toral dissertation MIT Cambridge MA

Sproat R On Deriving the Lexicon do ctoral dissertation MIT

Cambridge MA

CHAPTER LEXICAL DETERMINERS

Sto ckwell R PSchachter B Partee The Major Syntactic Struc

tures of English Holt Rinehart and Winston

Stowell T Origins of Phrase Structure Do ctoral dissertation MIT

Cambridge MA

Stowell T Sub jects Across Categories The Linguistic Review

Szab olcsi A The Possessive Construction in Hungarian A Cong

urational Category in a NonCongurational Language Acta Lin

guisticaAcademiae Scientiarum Hungaricae

Szab olcsi A The p ossessor that ran away from home The Lin

guistic Review

Szab olcsi A Functional Categories in the Noun Phrase to app ear

in Kenesei ed Approaches to Hungarian Vol Szeged

Thompson S On Sub jectless Gerunds in English Foundations of

Language

Underhill R Turkish Grammar MIT Press Cambridge MA

Vendler Z Adjectives and Nominalizations Mouton The Hague

Vergnaud JR French Relative Clauses Do ctoral dissertation MIT

Cambridge MA

Wasow T T Ro ep er On the Sub ject of Gerunds Foundations

of Language

Wik B English Nominalizations in ingActaUniversitatis Upsalien

sis Studia Anglistica Upsaliensia Uppsala

Williams E Small Clauses in English in J Kimball ed Syntax

and SemanticsVol Academic Press NY

Williams E Predication Linguistic Inquiry

Williams E The NPCycle Linguistic Inquiry

Williams E PRO and Sub ject of NP Natural Language and Lin

guistic Theory

Winston P Articial Intel ligence AddisonWesley Reading MA

Young R W Morgan The Navaho Language Deseret Bo ok Com

pany