Talking to Skeptics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Talking to Skeptics TALKING TO SKEPTICS by Charles Goldhaber B.A. in Philosophy and Japanese Language & Culture, summa cum laude University of California, Berkeley, 2011 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2020 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Charles Goldhaber It was defended on October 29, 2020 and approved by John McDowell, PhD, Distinguished University Professor, Philosophy Stephen Engstrom, PhD, Professor, Philosophy James Shaw, PhD, Associate Professor, Philosophy Karl Schafer, PhD, Professor, Philosophy Dissertation Director: John McDowell, PhD, Distinguished University Professor, Philosophy ii Copyright c by Charles Goldhaber 2020 iii TALKING TO SKEPTICS Charles Goldhaber, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2020 Skeptics argue that we can know very little, threatening our claims to knowledge. Many philosophers now think there is no use in talking to skeptics|that nothing can change their minds, curing them of skepticism. These philosophers opt for mere prevention, aiming to convince only non-skeptics that skeptical arguments fail. I argue that a cure is needed, viable, and theoretically illuminating. First, I argue that the mere prevention of skepticism is likely to fail. To succeed, it would need to show why skeptical arguments appear compelling. Showing this either reveals that the arguments are compelling, demonstrating the need for cure, or reveals how they merely appear so, constituting a cure. Second, I show that we can change a skeptic's mind. I argue that influential arguments for skepticism about the external world all rely on a shared, tacit premise: that perception never guarantees that things are as we seem to perceive them to be. I then argue that arguments for this premise are question-begging. Showing the skeptic that her skepticism lacks foundation clears obstacles to her accepting, on ordinary grounds, a view on which perception can provide us with knowledge of how things are around us, thus curing her. Third, I argue that my cure helps us understand the nature, significance, and history of skepticism. For Hume, I explain, skepticism is a temperament, which leads to mad- ness when overly dominant, but only carefulness when balanced with other temperaments. Tracing skepticism to a groundless intuition helps motivate Hume's focus on temperaments, while Hume's conception of proper temperamental balance helps to diagnose and moderate skepticism. I then argue that Kant tries to cure a skeptical empiricist not by showing skepticism's incoherence, but by offering an alternative explanation of our knowledge. Kant's portrayal of skepticism as arising from despair of understanding human knowledge explains why the skeptic is apt to find his alternative appealing, and teaches a general lesson about curing iv skepticism: Offering the skeptic a way to make sense of our knowledge allows him to overcome the frustration from which his skepticism arises. Keywords: skepticism, knowledge, perception, temperament, Hume, Kant. v TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE ......................................... ix 1.0 CURE AND PREVENTION ..........................1 1.1 WHO SKEPTICS ARE.............................1 1.2 KINDS OF RESPONSES TO SKEPTICISM.................3 1.3 THE PREFERENCE FOR PREVENTION..................8 1.4 IGNORING THE SKEPTIC.......................... 11 1.5 A DILEMMA FOR MERE PREVENTION.................. 16 1.6 TRANSITION: HOPE FOR A CURE..................... 21 2.0 THE GROUNDLESSNESS OF SKEPTICISM ............... 24 2.1 PLAN FOR A CURE.............................. 24 2.2 A COMMON PREMISE IN SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS.......... 25 2.3 JUST AN INTUITION............................. 36 2.4 REACHING THE SKEPTIC.......................... 40 2.5 OBJECTIONS AND REPLIES......................... 43 2.6 CONCLUSION.................................. 46 2.7 TRANSITION: HISTORICAL PRECEDENT................. 52 3.0 THE HUMORS IN HUME'S SKEPTICISM ................ 56 3.1 AN OVERLOOKED QUESTION........................ 56 3.2 A CYCLE THROUGH THE HUMORS.................... 60 3.3 THE ANACHRONISM OBJECTION..................... 69 3.4 THE METHODOLOGY OBJECTION..................... 75 3.5 RECONCEIVING HUME'S SKEPTICISM.................. 80 3.6 CONCLUSION.................................. 88 3.7 TRANSITION: JUST A PALLIATIVE?.................... 91 4.0 KANT'S OFFER TO THE SKEPTICAL EMPIRICIST ......... 96 4.1 A NEW QUESTION............................... 96 vi 4.2 TRADITIONAL READINGS OF KANT ON HUME............. 101 4.3 KANT'S ATTITUDE TOWARDS SKEPTICAL EMPIRICISTS....... 111 4.4 THE EXPLANATORY READING OF THE DEDUCTION......... 116 4.5 THE EXPLANATION IN THE DEDUCTION................ 122 4.6 THE INSTABILITY OF SKEPTICAL EMPIRICISM............ 131 4.7 FURTHER OBSTACLES............................ 144 4.8 CONCLUSION.................................. 148 5.0 CONCLUSION TO THE DISSERTATION ................. 151 APPENDIX A. CHAPTER SUMMARIES .................... 158 APPENDIX B. NOTE ON CITATIONS OF HUME AND KANT ..... 160 BIBLIOGRAPHY .................................... 163 vii LIST OF FIGURES 1 The four humors................................... 62 2 Abbreviations for Hume and Kant's writings.................... 162 viii PREFACE This dissertation is a set of interconnected essays on the theme of skepticism. Common to each essay is the idea that we will understand the nature and proper treatment of skepticism better than many contemporary discussions do, if we consider the history, ambitions, moods, and feelings which give rise to skepticism. Throughout each essay, I will be treating skepticism as a kind of infirmity or illness. As an illness, its treatment is aided by looking beyond its symptoms and for its underlying causes. In viewing skepticism in this way, I do not mean to disparage or trivialize the phenomenon, those afflicted with it, or the thinking that it can inspire. On the contrary, I think we must take skepticism seriously. We must treat it with a sober respect in part because, like some diseases, it is a regular and natural part of human life, and can be brought about through human activities that are often or in other circumstances salutary. Viewing the illness in light of these origins can be one way of coming to see skepticism as capable of playing a positive role in human life, especially insofar as it can help usher in a kind of intellectual maturity. Nonetheless, skepticism's harmful side should not be overlooked, and the production of a cure for such an illness is a worthy humanitarian effort. One of the principal goals of this dissertation is to offer a cure for skepticism. I develop this cure in Chapter2. But another goal is to diagnose what I see as a deficiency in recent philosophical discussions of skepticism, which I believe tend to distort the nature of the phenomenon by abstracting it from human life. Most philosophical discussions of skepti- cism nowadays treat it as one of many possible, equally well-positioned views about human knowledge or justification. In particular, they take skepticism to be the view that we know nothing, or very little, of what we ordinarily take ourselves to know, or that we are justified in believing little to none of the things we believe. Like any other view in epistemology|say, fallibilism or contextualism|arguments are produced in its favor, and considered on their own merits, presumably from a hallowed position of philosophical neutrality. This sort of approach to skepticism may appear appropriate, insofar as philosophy itself can seem to require sober non-partisanship. Surely part of what makes philosophy attractive ix and worthwhile is that it can, in some circumstances, not only help us to understand the grounds of what we antecedently believe, but also change our minds and make us wiser as a result. To succeed with this, philosophy may indeed require us to suspend judgment about the topic of interest and patiently turn it on all sides before deciding what to think. But thinking that philosophy must always do this, or even that there can ever be a perfectly pure decision from the void, is, I think, a mistake. This way of thinking removes philosophy from its actual, humble origins in human concern and insight, and, in doing so, impoverishes the resources of philosophical dialectic. It can lead us to overlook the possibility of appealing to more than our interlocutor's explicit commitments. We might then miss the relevance of her antecedent aspirations, affective tendencies, and ability to dissociate from her current views sufficiently to entertain others and see where they lead. It may seem that it is skepticism in particular, rather than philosophy in general, which demands that we limit the resources used in debate with a skeptic to a very narrow set, insofar as skepticism casts doubt on so much of what we ordinarily take ourselves to know. But to think that this is so, I suggest, is to forget that skepticism is a condition that people can be afflicted by, and that philosophy can and ought to play a role in the treatment and moderation of such natural infirmities. In order to reclaim a more resource-rich dialectic, I propose to model philosophical treat- ment of skepticism on a conversation with a skeptic. In calling my dissertation \Talking to Skeptics," I do not mean that I will be using a dialogical form. Instead, I call it that to remind the reader that skepticism is something a person has, and
Recommended publications
  • CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy the Johns Hopkins University Citizen of U.K. Baltimore, MD 21218-2686 P
    CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy The Johns Hopkins University Citizen of U.K. Baltimore, MD 21218-2686 Permanent Resident of U.S. Phone: (410) 516-6863 Fax: (410) 516-6848 e-mail: <[email protected]> EDUCATION B.A. Oxford University, 1980, Literae Humaniores (Classics and Philosophy). First Class Honours, Final Examinations, 1980; First Class Honours, Honour Moderations in Greek & Latin Literature, 1978 Ph.D. University of California, Berkeley, 1986, Philosophy. Dissertation Title: “Moral Scepticism: Why Ask ‘Why Should I be Moral?’” CURRENT POSITION Professor of Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University; secondary appointment in Classics PREVIOUS POSITIONS Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Texas at Arlington, 1986-1991 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, Jan.-June 1991 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1991-1994 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1994-2000; secondary appointment in Classics, 1996-2000 Acting Executive Director, The American Philosophical Association, Jan. 2000-June 2001 PUBLICATIONS a) Books Sextus Empiricus, Against the Ethicists (Adversus Mathematicos XI): Introduction, Translation and Commentary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, paperback 2000). Pp. xxxiv + 302 Pyrrho, his Antecedents and his Legacy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000, paperback 2003). Pp. xi + 264 Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians (Adversus Mathematicos VII-VIII): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). Pp. xliv + 207 The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism (editor) (Cambridge University Press, 2010). Pp. xii + 380 (Books, continued) Sextus Empiricus, Against the Physicists (Adversus Mathematicos IX-X): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012). Pp. xxxiii + 178 Sextus Empiricus, Against those in the Disciplines (Adversus Mathematicos I-VI): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018).
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 137: Skepticism, Relativism, and Truth
    Philosophy 137: Skepticism, Relativism, and Truth Whitman College – Fall 2018 Mitch Clearfield [email protected] office: Olin 195 office hours: office phone: 527-5853 Mon. 2-4 & Fri. 1-2:30 Course Description In philosophy, and for many people in everyday life, a genuine “truth” is something that reflects the way things really are, objectively speaking. Skepticism either opposes the idea that there are such objective truths, or claims that we can never really have adequate access to them. Relativism claims that something can be true only within a particular individual’s or culture’s perspective, but not absolutely or universally. In this class, we will examine different forms of skepticism and relativism, and different responses from defenders of objective truth. We will briefly consider the views of the ancient Greek skeptics and the 16th century French philosopher René Descartes, but most of the readings in the course were written by recent and contemporary English-language philosophers. We will consider views that are skeptical or relativist about everything, as well as views that focus on more specific topics: • Science: Do our best scientific theories capture (or at least get closer and closer to capturing) the way the world really is? Does science make progress toward truth? • Language: Do different languages reflect or even impose fundamentally different ways of understanding the world? Can the speaker of one language fully understand the speaker of another language? • Culture: Do different cultures reflect or even impose fundamentally
    [Show full text]
  • Essays I Would Prefer Him to Keep Quiet
    Essays, Book I Michel de Montaigne 1580 Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type. —Montaigne kept adding to this work. Following most modern editions, the present version uses tags in the following way: [A]: material in the first edition (1580) or added soon thereafter, [B]: material added in the greatly enlarged second edition (1588), [C]: material added in the first posthumous edition (1595) following Montaigne’s notes in his own copy. The tags are omitted where they seem unimportant. The ones that are retained are kept very small to make them neglectable by readers who aren’t interested in those details. Sometimes, as on pages 34 and 54, they are crucial. —The footnotes are all editorial. —Contemporary spellings of French words are used in the glossary and in references in the text to the glossary. —In the original, all the quotations from Latin writers are given in Latin. First launched: 2017 Contents 1. We reach the same end by different means 2 2. Sadness 4 3. Our feelings reach out beyond us 5 Essays, Book I Michel de Montaigne 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Vocabulary, Grammar and Punctuation
    English Appendix 2: Vocabulary, grammar and punctuation Year 1 The following should be taught at year 1: Punctuation Separation of words with finger spaces. The use of capital letters, full stops, question marks and exclamation marks in sentences. Capital letter for proper nouns (names of people, places, days of the week). Capital letter for the personal pronoun I Grammar and Vocabulary The use of regular plural noun suffixes. e.g. adding s or es. (dog–dogs and wish– wishes ) Adding suffixes to words where there is no change to the spelling of the root word:e.g. root word–help becomes helping, helper, helped. Using and understanding how the prefix un changes the meaning of verbs and adjectives. e.g. kind– unkind, tie–untie. How words can make simple sentences. Join words and clauses with and. Grammatical terms that Letter children should know Capital letter Full stop word Singular and plural Sentence Punctuation Question mark Exclamation mark Link to SPaG progression Y1 Sentence structures Examples document Join words and clauses with Write 2 simple sentences joined with I can see the dog and the cat. and and because and and because. 1A sentences I can see the scruffy dog. One adjective before the noun Year 2 The following should be taught at year 2, ensuring that year 1 content is secure. Punctuation The use of capital letters, full stops, question marks and exclamation marks in sentences. The use of commas to separate items in a list The use of apostrophes for omission. e.g. did not – didn’t The use of apostrophe to show singular possession in nouns e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Empiricus and the Scientific Scepticism
    ENCEPHALOS 50, 62-74, 2013 SEXTUS EMPIRICUS AND THE SCIENTIFIC SCEPTI- CISM STAVROS J.BALOYANNIS* Summary philosophical books, which survived, but remained for long in obscurity, been rediscovered in the late Renaissance. Two Sextus Empiricus is the most eminent representative of these works on the title, “Adversus Mathematikus”, include of the ancient sceptisism, which is a Post-Classical, Hellenis- large number of strong arguments against the Logicians, the tic philosophy based on the criterion of life, the experience Physicists and the Ethicists. The third and most important of and the analysis of phenomena, aiming to provide a straight the books on the title “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” provides an out- and practical way of life, leading to interior peace and mental line of Pyrrhonian scepticism, incorporating at the same time tranquility, sharply opposed to a purely theoretical pursuit of his own philosophical doctrines. Sextus offers thoroughly a dogmatic philosophy. The term “sceptic” is a derivative of the general overview of scepticism, describing and explaining the noun, skepsis (σκέψις), which means thought, examination, meaning of the sceptical investigation, the value of suspen- inquiry, consideration, meditation and investigation. The scep- sion of judgment and the importance of the sceptical dialectics. tical school was connected for a long period of time with the Sextus insists that the skepticism does not accept or reject any Empirical school of physicians, who based the good medical impression and substantially does not affirm or deny anything. practice on the clinical experience rather than on the theoret- Sextus claims that appearances (φαινόμενα) are the practical ical erudition, dedicating themselves to observation, memory criteria of approaching to the truth and by the continuous inves- and continuous clinical practice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Positive Self-Reference
    The Theory of Positive Self-reference Bordum, Anders Document Version Final published version Publication date: 2002 License CC BY-NC-ND Citation for published version (APA): Bordum, A. (2002). The Theory of Positive Self-reference. Department of Management, Politics and Philosophy, CBS. MPP Working Paper No. 10/2002 Link to publication in CBS Research Portal General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us ([email protected]) providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 28. Sep. 2021 The Theory of Positive Self-Reference Anders Bordum WP 10/2002 May 2002 1 MPP Working Paper No. 10/2002 © May 2002 ISBN: 87-91181-13-5 ISSN: 1396-2817 Department of Management, Politics and Philosophy Copenhagen Business School Blaagaardsgade 23B DK-2200 Copenhagen N Denmark Phone: +45 38 15 36 30 Fax: +45 38 15 36 35 E-mail: [email protected] www.cbs.dk/departments/mpp 2 The Theory of Positive Self-Reference By Anders Bordum Anders Bordum, Ph.D Associate Professor Department of Management, Politics and Philosophy Copenhagen Business School Blaagaardsgade 23B DK-2200 Copenhagen Denmark Phone: +45 38 15 37 83 Email: [email protected] 3 The Theory of Positive Self-Reference............................................................................ 2 The Problem of Contradiction.........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Rainer Hirsch-Luipold, Reinhard Feldmeier und Heinz-Günther Nesselrath unter der Mitarbeit von Natalia Pedrique und Andrea Villani Band XXV Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary and Interpretative Essays by Katja Maria Vogt, Richard Bett, Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi, Christiana M. M. Olfert, Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley, and James Warren edited by Katja Maria Vogt Mohr Siebeck SAPERE is a Project of the Göttingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony. e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156430-7 ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio nal- bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http:// dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. www.mohr.de This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This ap- plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro- cessing in electronic systems. This book was supervised by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tübin- gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times.
    [Show full text]
  • Proquest Dissertations
    "I lost the bus: Can you give me a ride home?" Native and nonnative English speakers' speech act production and metapragmatic judgments: A study of apologies, complaints and requests Item Type text; Dissertation-Reproduction (electronic) Authors Ruhil, Anuradha, 1965- Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 23/09/2021 23:03:29 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/282738 INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfihn master. UMI fihns the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overiaps. Each original is also photographed in one exposure and is included in reduced form at the back of the book.
    [Show full text]
  • Doing Things with Concepts in Sextus Empiricus Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University
    Doing Things with Concepts in Sextus Empiricus Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University What concepts are is the subject of lively and continuing debate. Are they in our heads, and if so, what form do they take? Or are they abstract objects – Fregean senses, for example, or “the constituents of propositions”1 – with which we somehow interact in our speech and thought? Do they vary from person to person? And should we draw a definite distinction between the concept of X, understood as relatively unified and stable, and various different conceptions of X, which “are thought to be more ephemeral and idiosyncratic than concepts”2? These are some of the many questions in this area, the answers to which may affect, or be affected by, our most basic commitments in the philosophy of mind and language. Fortunately, we need not worry about any of these deep and difficult questions, because we are dealing with Sextus Empiricus, who, as a Pyrrhonian sceptic, does not adopt philosophical theories, whether about the nature of concepts or about anything else. But these contested matters are nonetheless worth mentioning, if only to indicate that the territory we are dealing with under the heading of “concepts” is somewhat indeterminate. For an author like Sextus who not only eschews theory, but also deliberately avoids what he considers over-precision in the use of language (PH 1.207, cf. 1.17, 1.191), this is perhaps only appropriate. There is in fact quite a lot in Sextus that can naturally be seen as addressing the topic of concepts. There are four or five relevant terms in his texts that either 1 Margolis and Laurence 2011, 1.3.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Different Origins of Symbols and Grammar
    On the Different Origins of Symbols and Grammar University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Language Evolution Morten H. Christiansen and Simon Kirby Print publication date: 2003 Print ISBN-13: 9780199244843 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: January 2010 DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199244843.001.0001 On the Different Origins of Symbols and Grammar Michael Tomasello DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199244843.003.0006 Abstract and Keywords This chapter emphasises the role of psychology in language evolution, but claims that it was the separate evolution of capacities for using symbols and grammar (that is, syntactic structure) that distinguishes human communication from the communication of other primates. It suggests that there was no specific biological adaptation for linguistic communication. Rather, there was an adaptation for a broader kind of complex social cognition that enabled human culture and, as a special case of that, human symbolic communication. A crucial part of this adaptation was an evolved ability to recognise other individuals as intentional agents whose attention and behaviour could be shared and manipulated. The capacity for grammar subsequently developed, and became refined through processes of grammaticalisation occurring across generations — but with no additional biological adaptations. In support of this perspective, psychological data from the study Page 1 of 21 PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015. All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy).
    [Show full text]
  • Defining the Elephant: a History of Psychopathy, 1891-1959
    Defining the Elephant: a History of Psychopathy, 1891-1959 Susanna Elizabeth Evelyn Shapland Department of History, Classics and Archaeology Birkbeck, University of London Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, February 2019 1 DECLARATION I confirm that all material presented in this thesis is my own work, except where otherwise indicated. Signed .............................................. 2 ABSTRACT Although ‘psychopath’ is a term which is still in use by psychiatrists, it has come to be used as a way of dismissing individuals as irredeemably ‘bad’, untreatable or unpleasant, both by professionals and the public. This attitude is supported by existing histories of psychopathy that are in fact simply histories of the criminal personality, and rely upon retrofitting the diagnosis to historical examples of criminal or problematic behaviour to support their claims of psychopathy’s universal and timeless nature. This thesis disrupts that narrative. By examining the ways in which the terms psychopath, psychopathy and psychopathic are used in historical context, and how this changed over time, it challenges the idea of psychopathy as a fixed and value-free term, and reveals that there were multiple, competing versions of psychopathy in a history rich with contested meanings and overlapping usage. In analysing discussions of how psychopaths were diagnosed, managed and treated, it shows that the history of psychopathy is marked by a fundamental lack of agreement over the parameters of this ‘wastebasket’ diagnosis, which time and again proved too useful to discard. 3 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My thanks go first and foremost to my supremely patient supervisor, Joanna Bourke. Her inexhaustible enthusiasm and thought-provoking and perceptive feedback have been inspirational.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E
    Philosophy Compass 6/4 (2011): 246–258, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00391.x Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E. Machuca* Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı´ficas y Te´cnicas Abstract Pyrrhonism was one of the two main ancient skeptical traditions. In this second paper of the three-part series devoted to ancient skepticism, I present and discuss some of the issues on Pyrrho- nian skepticism which have been the focus of much attention in the recent literature. The topics to be addressed concern the outlooks of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. In the first paper of this three-part series on ancient skepticism, I offered a general pre- sentation of the ancient skeptical traditions as well as an overview of recent translations and general studies. With this framework in place, the present paper deals with some vexed questions concerning the stances of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. For reasons of space, the discussion will be selective and it will not always be possible to go into detail about the issues tackled. 1. Pyrrho Most recent scholarship on Pyrrho of Elis (360–270 BC) continues to divide between two main interpretations of his outlook, which may be called ‘practical’ and ‘theoretical’. The first interpretation affirms that Pyrrho’s motivation was exclusively or mainly ethi- cal.1 This view finds support in some passages in Diogenes Laertius and particularly in Cicero, who does not refer to Pyrrho as a skeptic, but invariably portrays him as a moral- ist – as someone who considered virtue as the only good and who was admired for his lifestyle (Academica II 130; On Moral Ends III 11–2, IV 43, 49, 60; On Duties I 6).
    [Show full text]