I Desire, Knowledge, and the Origins of Self-Consciousness: A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

I Desire, Knowledge, and the Origins of Self-Consciousness: A Desire, Knowledge, and the Origins of Self-Consciousness: A Theological Account in Conversation with Augustine, Aquinas, and Freud By Daryl Ellis Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Vanderbilt University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Religion December, 2016 Nashville, Tennessee Approved: Date: ________________________________________________ ________________ Paul J. DeHart, Ph.D. ________________________________________________ ________________ Ellen T. Armour, Ph.D. ________________________________________________ ________________ J. Patout Burns, Ph.D. ________________________________________________ ________________ Bruce L. McCormack, Ph.D. ________________________________________________ ________________ Bruce Morrill, Ph.D. i Copyright © 2016 by Daryl Ellis All Rights Reserved ii To Courtney. Our life together is a foretaste of the joy that awaits when we see God face-to-face. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In undertaking a project as long and complex has this one has proven to be, I owe a debt of gratitude to numerous people who have supported me along the way. My advisor, Paul DeHart, has directed and encouraged me faithfully with the gift of his exacting insight and the generosity of his time. In the midst of what can often be a very confusing season to practice academic theology, his scholarly example of taking the question of truth seri- ously (as well as our God-created and grace-rehabilitated capacity for grasping it) will stay with me for the rest of my life. In the same vein, thanks to Patout Burns for introduc- ing me to Aquinas and modeling what it means to bear steadfast witness to the Christian faith with equal parts humor and earnestness; to Ellen Armour for her kindness as a con- versation partner and for enriching my interest in psychoanalysis by pointing me toward Kristeva; to Doug Meeks for constantly encouraging me to be a theologian in the service of the church; to Ted Smith for casting an inspired vision for guild-situated practical the- ology; and to Bruce McCormack for his gracious support and teaching me how to pair heart and mind as a theologian in confessing that Jesus is Lord. In addition, a number of institutions have furnished financial support along the way that provided enough concrete stability in my daily life to allow for the completion of my doctoral studies and dissertation. Thanks especially to Vanderbilt University’s Graduate School, the Program in Theology and Practice, and the Lilly Endowment. Also, thanks to members of the Presbyterian Church of the Master for several periods of study leave, in addition to their prayers and loving inquiries as to my progress. Lastly, I have been surrounded by colleagues, friends, and family members who have been a constant source of encouragement and blessing. Joel Erickson, Jared Bangs, iv and Jonathan Taylor have all offered indispensable feedback along the way. Similarly, two colleagues deserve special mention. First, this dissertation was born from a series of conversations I had with Sean Hayden. The constructive questions that ended up blos- soming in these pages emerged in large part because of the fruitfulness of his considera- ble insight and direct inquiries to me regarding the knottiest of anthropological matters. Without him, it is unlikely that self-consciousness would ever have appeared on my radar as a theological problem. Second, Chris Blumhofer has been a tireless source of support, inspiration, and fellowship. Not only did he provide excellent feedback on portions of this study, but he also made himself endlessly available as my library of last resort after I had moved away from Nashville. The generosity of that availability, and the holistic pos- ture of his friendship, buoyed me at several crucial junctures in the writing process. Above all, however, I owe the greatest debt to my wife, Courtney. This disserta- tion is the fruit that has slowly emerged from a series of daily sacrifices we have made together over the course of several years. Many of her particular sacrifices related to tak- ing on the familiar, but nonetheless priceless and exhausting, tasks of our family so that I could have the space to write. This included countless early mornings and Saturdays lov- ing our sons (first Lincoln and then, right near the end, newborn Wilson as well)—i.e. feeding them, reading books with them, packing snacks for them, convincing them that going to the playground or the pool really is a good idea (!), teaching them, and assuring them that Daddy actually is coming home very soon. Moreover, she also demonstrated extraordinary patience with me as the project ending up taking much longer than ex- pected. Not only did she endure these extensions with grace and gentleness, but she also found a deep well of love from which to also offer support and encouragement at some of v my lowest moments of being disheartened by my progress. During these years we also lived so much life together: we made two out-of-state moves, began serving in ministry on the same church staff, had two children, and experienced many heartaches and joys. When taken together, these daily sacrifices and experiences combine to make up one ex- tended act of laboring toward a common goal. In addition to her remarkable resilience and strength, perhaps the most memorable thing to me is that God has used these years to draw us closer to one another and to Christ. Whereas the stress of such a project very eas- ily could have driven us apart, instead it has functioned—to borrow a phrase from the po- et Donald Hall—as a “third thing” that unified our common bonds of love more securely and beautifully.1 May the completion of this “third thing” open up space for even more common labors of love, all of which converge upon Jesus as the ultimate “third thing” that binds us together: for “through him [may we] go straight toward him, through knowledge toward wisdom, without turning aside from one and the same Christ.”2 1 Donald Hall, “The Third Thing,” Poetry 185, no. 2 (2004): 113-21. 2 Augustine, trin. XIII.24. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Acknowledgements ............................................................................................................ iv Sources and Abbreviations ................................................................................................ ix Introduction The Nature and Origin of Self-Consciousness: Why Freud, Augustine, and Aquinas? ..... 1 I. Definitions and the Riddle of Self-Consciousness as a Primal Self-Relation ............. 4 II. From Kant to Schleiermacher: Four Approaches ..................................................... 10 III. The Origins of this Project: Two Conjectures and Finding a Midwife ................... 27 IV. Chapter Outline: Leveraging Aquinas’s Solution to Translate Freud .................... 39 V. Some Methodological and Terminological Notes ................................................... 45 Chapter 1. Desire, Knowledge and the Varieties of Intensive Unity: Augustine’s Dilemma in De Trinitate .................................................................................................................. 52 I. The Eternal Simplicity of the Triune God and the Exitus of Temporal Desire ......... 58 II. Ascending to the Trinitarian Imago Dei and the Crux of Augustine’s Dilemma .... 66 III. Summary and Conclusion ..................................................................................... 103 2. Aquinas’s Solution I: The Aristotelian Soul and the Verticality of Knowledge ........ 108 I. A Primer on Aristotelian Metaphysics: Causation and Passion/Action .................. 115 II. Aristotle and Aquinas on the Soul as the First Actuality of a Living Being .......... 124 III. The Apprehensive Powers and the Verticality of Knowledge .............................. 130 IV. With and Beyond Augustine Via Aristotle: Participation and The Triune Creator .................................................................................................................. 162 V. Conclusion: Summarizing and Outlining a Gap .................................................... 183 3. Aquinas’s Solution II: The Verticality of Desire ........................................................ 189 I. The Metaphysics of Appetite in General ................................................................. 195 II. Sense Appetite: The Passions of the Soul .............................................................. 208 III. Intellective Appetite: The Will ............................................................................. 227 IV. The Vertical Dynamism Between the Sensitive and Intellective Appetites ......... 248 V. Conclusion: Summarizing and Outlining a Gap .................................................... 260 4. The Ego and the Identifying Part of the Soul: Translating Freud Via Aquinas’s Solution ...................................................................................................................... 268 I. Freud’s Dilemma: The Ego’s Formation, Identification, and the Specter of Hypnosis .................................................................................................................. 274 II. The Identifying Part of the Soul: An Initial Step in Applying Aquinas’s Solution .................................................................................................................. 319 III. Conclusion: Summarizing and Looking Ahead .................................................... 358 vii 5. Identification,
Recommended publications
  • Catharsis and Salvation in the Mosaic of Casaranello (Italy, 6Th Century)
    American Journal of Art and Design 2021; 6(3): 84-94 http://www.sciencepublishinggroup.com/j/ajad doi: 10.11648/j.ajad.20210603.13 ISSN: 2578-7799 (Print); ISSN: 2578-7802 (Online) A Journey of the Soul: Catharsis and Salvation in the Mosaic of Casaranello (Italy, 6th Century) Francesco Danieli Gli Argonauti, Roman University Editions, Rome, Italy Email address: To cite this article: Francesco Danieli. A Journey of the Soul: Catharsis and Salvation in the Mosaic of Casaranello (Italy, 6th Century). American Journal of Art and Design . Vol. 6, No. 3, 2021, pp. 84-94. doi: 10.11648/j.ajad.20210603.13 Received : June 12, 2021; Accepted : July 19, 2021; Published : July 28, 2021 Abstract: The church of Santa Maria della Croce in Casaranello (Casarano, Italy, 6th century) is an important paleo- Byzantine testimony in Southern Italy. The building is well preserved and corresponds more or less to its original structure because in the late-medieval age the community of Casaranum decided to move the residential area up the hill overlooking the original hamlet. The German art historian Arthur Haseloff (1872-1955) visited the church in 1907, intrigued by a bibliographic indication by Wladimir De Gruneisen, and he found it in the miserable condition of stall for sheep and goats. When he entered the church, he immediately realised he was in front of one of the most important jewels of the paleochristian art: a treasure fallen into oblivion and whose value deserved to be highlighted. Haseloff summarily analysed the site of Casaranello, paying particular attention to the mosaic. This research promoted a new awareness towards Santa Maria della Croce and laid the basis for the restoration interventions carried out during the second half of the ‘900s.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Irvine UC Irvine Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC Irvine UC Irvine Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Text Machines: Mnemotechnical Infrastructure as Exappropriation Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3cj9797z Author McCoy, Jared Publication Date 2020 License https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ 4.0 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Text Machines: Mnemotechnical Infrastructure as Exappropriation DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in English by Jared McCoy Dissertation Committee: Professor Andrzej Warminski, Chair Professor Rajagopalan Radhakrishnan Professor Geoffrey Bowker 2020 © 2020 Jared McCoy Dedication TO MY PARENTS for their boundless love and patience …this requires a comprehensive reading of Heidegger that is hard, you know, to do quickly. Paul de Man ii Contents Contents ................................................................................................................................. iii Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................. v Curriculum Vitae ..................................................................................................................... vi Abstract of the Dissertation .................................................................................................... vii I. History of Inscription ...........................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • About: Plato an Entity of Type : Person, from Named Graph : Within Data Space : Dbpedia.Org
    About: Plato An Entity of Type : person, from Named Graph : http://dbpedia.org, within Data Space : dbpedia.org Plato (/ˈpleɪtoʊ/; Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, "broad"; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BCE) was a philosopher, as well as mathematician, in Classical Greece. He is considered an essential figure in the development of philosophy, especially the Western tradition, and he founded the Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the Western world. Along with Socrates and his most famous student, Aristotle, Plato laid the foundations of Western philosophy and science. Property Value dbo:abstract Plato (/ˈpleɪtoʊ/; Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, "broad"; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BCE) was a philosopher, as well as mathematician, in Classical Greece. He is considered an essential figure in the development of philosophy, especially the Western tradition, and he founded the Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the Western world. Along with Socrates and his most famous student, Aristotle, Plato laid the foundations of Western philosophy and science. Alfred North Whitehead once noted: "the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato."Plato's dialogues have been used to teach a range of subjects, including philosophy, logic, ethics, rhetoric, religion and mathematics. His lasting themes include Platonic love, the theory of forms, the five regimes, innate knowledge, among others. His theory of forms launched a unique perspective on abstract objects, and led to a school of thought called Platonism. Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.
    [Show full text]
  • Rohde's Theory of Relationship Between the Novel and Rhetoric
    2020-3673-AJHA-LIT 1 Rohde’s Theory of Relationship Between the Novel and 2 Rhetoric and the Problem of Evaluating the Entire Post- 3 Classical Greek Literature 4 5 The one hundred and fiftieth anniversary of the first publication of Rohde’s monograph 6 on the Greek novel is drawing near affording a welcome occasion for raising the big 7 question as to what remains of it today, all the more as the ancient novel, just due to his 8 classical work, has become a major area of research. The aforesaid monograph, 9 considered to be one of the greatest scientific achievements of the eighteenth century, 10 can be justifiably used as a litmus test for ascertaining how efficient methods hitherto 11 employed were or, in other words, whether we are entitled to speak of the continuous 12 progress in research or the opposite is true. Finally, the questions raised in the 13 monograph will turn out to be more important than the results obtained by the author, in 14 so far as the latter, based on his unfinished theses, proved to be very harmful to 15 evaluating both the Greek novel and the entire post-classical Greek literature. In this 16 paper we focus our attention on two major questions raised by the author such as 17 division of the third type of narration in the rhetorical manuals of the classical antiquity 18 and the nature of rhetoric, as expressed in the writings of the major exponents of the 19 Second Sophistic so as to be in a position to point to the way out of aporia, with the 20 preliminary remark that we shall not be able to get the full picture of the Greek novel 21 until the two remaining big questions posed by the author, such as the role played by 22 both Tyche and women in the Greek novel, are fully answered.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in Front of Religion
    ISSN 2239-978X Journal of Educational and Social Research Vol. 7 No.1 ISSN 2240-0524 January 2017 Research Article © 2017 Dorian Sevo. This is an open access article licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Philosophy in Front of Religion Dorian Sevo Doi:10.5901/jesr.2017.v7n1p127 Abstract From Plato to Aristotle, from Augustine to Aquinas from Pascal to Freud and Heidegger the world and philosophical thought has continually interpreted the human nature, the source of morality and religion, specifically what we call (metaphysics). Man of antiquity, the medieval, modern and contemporary has his attitude towards the sacred. But what is happening with the man of our age, what relation does it have nowadays with the sacred, what is his attitude and what are the reasons for this relationship with the sacred. All the above are part of this scientific research paper. To give readers an overview of attitudes of philosophical thought of different times in front of the sacred, what are its meanings at different times and how is the attitude toward the sacred today. Descriptive analysis of the philosophical and religious issues. 1. Introduction 1.1 Ancients in front of afterlife Philosophy and Religion have had and will always have connection with each other. Philosophy is as metaphysical as Religion or Faith as we might otherwise know it. Since antiquity we see a connection of religion and philosophy. Orphic religion in antiquity did the separation of the body to the soul, typical of the Christian faith, but also of the Islam, which are monotheistic religions.
    [Show full text]
  • Dieter Henrich's Turn
    The Problem of Subjectivity: Dieter Henrich’s Turn 189 The Problem of Subjectivity: Dieter Henrich’s Turn Gerhard Preyer The German philosopher Dieter Henrich has worked on the problem of subjectivity since the 1950s.1 In his lecture at the “Kolleg Friedrich Nietzsche der Stiftung Weimarer Klassik” (2003) he has reformulated the problem of subjectivity in the context of a revisionary approach. This is worth emphasiz- ing, since Henrich’s analysis is focused on the limits of the position of subjec- tivity in the world. He calls his turn a revisionary metaphysics because he sees subjectivity not as self-grounded but as part of an All-Einheit (all-unity), thus evoking a motive of Plato’s philosophy.2 In the present article, I will first deal with Henrich’s turn to the question of subjectivity. Secondly, I re-interpret his analysis of conscious self-reference (subjectivity) which starts from the condition of primary self-consciousness as immediate consciousness. Henrich also claims to give an answer to the mind-body problem in the context of the much changed questions of philosophy of mind since the 1950s. Thirdly, I consider Henrich’s view of the body (Leib) as a position in the world which goes along with subjectivity. Fourthly, this leads me to his discussion of the principle of consequence and of free choice as well as to the interplay between subjectiv- ity and practical self-reference considered as self-determination (Selbstbestim- mung) and self-relationship (Selbstverhältnisse).3 Studying the philosophical work of Henrich again I read it, in the current philosophical context, as a contribution to an existenzial phenomenology, given from the subject’s point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • PRELIMINARY SYLLABUS Metaphysics And
    Hartford Seminary 77 Sherman Street, Hartford, CT 06105-2260 PRELIMINARY SYLLABUS Metaphysics and the Quest(ion) of God After Kant (TH-626 – Fall Semester 2016) Instructor: Prof. Dr. Fábio Henrique de Abreu Visiting Professor of Philosophical Theology and Philosophy of Religion Email: [email protected] COURSE DESCRIPTION The starting point for modern philosophy in general and the philosophy of religion in particular belongs to Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). It is well recognized in the secondary literature that Kant’s “Copernican Revolution” has placed traditional (pre-critical) metaphysics and, by extension, the philosophical problem of religion – including his critique of the metaphysical doctrine of God – under such pervasive criticism that religion is now threatened up to the point of becoming nothing more than an illusion. The best example of the powerful and influent character of the Kantian criticism of religion is, perhaps, Ludwig A. Feuerbach’s (1804-1872) understanding of religion as a human projection. One is no longer able to speak of God by means either of the authority of the Scriptures or through an appeal to any kind of supernatural source. The reality of God, as such, is now at stake. This course aims firstly at investigating, historically, the fundamental nature of Kant’s criticism both of religion and of the idea of God. Secondly, it will investigate some selected writings by the young Georg W. F. Hegel (1770-1831) and Friedrich D. E. Schleiermacher (1768-1834) as critical responses to Kant’s transcendental philosophical standpoint that have led to a consequent repositioning of the Kantian problematic on religion and the idea of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Fichte's Position
    Fichte’s Position: Self-Awareness and the Space of Reasons Paul Franks I: Introduction Of all the famous figures in the history of philosophy, Johann Gottlieb Fichte may perhaps have the worst reputation. Others have been accused of equivocations, inconsistencies, non sequiturs and other blunders. But Fichte’s view has the distinction that it has regularly been described as verging upon insanity, sometimes even as attaining it. Here, for example, is Bertrand Russell: “Kant’s immediate successor, Fichte, abandoned ‘things in themselves’ and carried subjectivism to a point which seems almost to involve a kind of insanity. He holds that the Ego is the only ultimate reality, and that it exists because it posits itself; the non-Ego, which has a subordinate reality, also exists only because the Ego posits it. The Ego as a metaphysical concept easily became confused with the empirical Fichte . .”i Later, I will cite Jean Paul, a contemporary of Fichte’s, who also associates Fichteanism with a literally crazy subjectivism. Now I want to note that a view of Fichte surprisingly like Russell’s -- and indeed a view of the development of modern philosophy somewhat similar to Russell’s -- can also be found on what we Englishmen quaintly call the continent. Thus Heidegger, like Russell, sees the development of philosophy since Descartes as the ascent of subjectivism, and, again like Russell, Heidegger regards Fichte’s philosophy as a high-point of a regrettable journey.ii For all their differences, both Anglo-American and continental traditions of twentieth century philosophy have shared a common enemy: subjectivism.iii By subjectivism, I think it is fair to say, both traditions have meant the extension of the Cartesian view of the mind to the whole of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Johann Gottfried Herder on Memory Laura Follesa Friedrich Schiller University of Jena
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CommonKnowledge Essays in Philosophy ISSN 1526-0569 | Essays in Philosophy is published by the Pacific University Libraries Volume 19, Issue 2 (2018) Learning and Vision: Johann Gottfried Herder on Memory Laura Follesa Friedrich Schiller University of Jena Abstract A consistent thread throughout Johann Gottfried Herder’s thought is his interest in human knowledge and in its origins. Although he never formulated a systematic theory of knowledge, elements of one are disseminated in his writings, from the early manuscript Plato sagte (1766–68) to one of his last works, the periodical Adrastea (1801–3). Herder assigned a very special function to memory and to the related idea of a recollection of “images,” as they play a pivotal role in the formation of personal identity. He provided an original description of the Platonic theory of recollection, trying to merge ancient and modern meta- physical views and to interpret them from a less metaphysical and more psychological point of view. I then analyze Herder’s notion of memory via another research line, which is basically founded upon the analogy between the childhood of an individual and the infancy of the human race. Finally, I explore Herder’s view that memory and imagination, as “forces” of the soul, can have negative effects on an individual when they are not equally balanced. Essays Philos (2018)19:2 | DOI: 10.7710/1526-0569.1610 Correspondence: [email protected] © 2018 Follesa. This open access article is distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License (https:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/) Essays in Philosophy Volume 19, Issue 2 1.
    [Show full text]
  • FU/BEST Program
    FU/BEST Program Name: Dr. Detlef von Daniels Email address: [email protected] Course title: The Promise of German Philosophy: Between Kant and Hegel Course number: FU-BEST 9a Language of instruction: English Contact hours: 45 ECTS-Credits: 6 U.S. semester credits: 3 Course description Philosophy has constituted a central element in the development of modern German culture. In the late eighteenth century, German philosophy participated in the broader European Enlightenment culture, which has in turn been connected to the development of modern empirical science. Under the impression of the historical changes brought about by the French Revolution and by the ‘Industrial Revolution’ in Great Britain, a special constellation of German philosophy emerged at the end of the eighteenth century, which has deeply left its mark on subsequent philosophical thinking far beyond Germany. In the course, we follow the emergence and full deployment of German philosophy from its beginnings in Kant’s theoretical and moral philosophy to Hegel’s grand but fragile synthesis. We will also discuss the critique by the Young Hegelians as well as by the late Schelling, trying to understand the richness as well as the limitations of this tradition of German philosophy. The course is based upon contemporary attempts at rethinking a global philosophical perspective. Therefore, the contextual reading of key texts is related to contemporary feminist and postcolonial discussions. Course work/expectations Midterm exam: 20% Term-Paper: 25% Final Exam: 20% Attendance and participation: 25% (including weekly reading responses) Independent Project: 10% Student profile Second-semester sophomore or above Prerequisites Prior knowledge of philosophy is not required, however, an eagerness to engage with densely written texts is indispensable.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Transcendental Deduction
    Kant’s Transcendental Deduction Professors James Conant & Robert Pippin Spring 2010 *** Syllabus *** Description of the Seminar This seminar will be devoted to a close reading and discussion of Kant’s First Critique, focusing on the Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding. We will also explore carefully explore a handful of proposals for how to interpret the First Critique and especially the Transcendental Deduction, including especially those put forward by Allison, Strawson, and Strawson. We will end the course with a close look at Wilfrid Sellars’s and John McDowell’s respective interpretations of Kant, with special attention to how each of their own philosophies of perception inherit, modify, and explore Kant’s criticisms of traditional empiricism, and how each of them it rework a number of Kantian themes – most notably Kant’s conception of intuition and his account of the relation between intuitions and concepts. The aim of the course is both to use certain central texts of recent Kant commentary and contemporary analytic Kantian philosophy to illuminate some the central aspirations of Kant’s theoretical philosophy and to use certain central Kantian texts in which those aspirations were first pursued to illuminate some recent developments in epistemology and the philosophy of mind. Instructors James Conant Robert Pippin Office: Stuart 208 Office: Foster 307 Office Phone: 773 702 6146 Office Phone: 773 702 5453 e-mail: [email protected] e-mail: [email protected] 1 Texts All of the following textbooks have been ordered through the Seminary Co-op and are all required texts for the course: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Problems and Challenges in Gadamer's Hermeneutics
    Between Enlightenment and Romanticism: Some Problems and Challenges in Gadamer’s Hermeneutics KRISTIN GJESDAL* for post-analytical philosophers such as Richard Rorty and John McDowell, Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Truth and Method (1960) has played an important role in their battles against Cartesian epistemology.1 In this context, it is little known that when Gadamer started working on Truth and Method in the early 1930s, he did not want only to criticize the framework of modern epistemology. Rather, the initial intention of his work was to “demonstrate that art can convey truth.”2 In Gadamer’s view, such a demonstration could not be of a merely systematic na- ture, but also had to engage with the historical development of aesthetics; it had to overcome the way in which Kant and the romantics had come to deny art any significance as knowledge. Since the publication of Truth and Method, Gadamer’s discussion of art and aesthetics—his critique of Kant, the romantics, and the general philosophical paradigm that he terms ‘aesthetic consciousness’—has received only scant atten- tion.3 By contrast, the second and third parts of the work—addressing, respectively, 1For Rorty’s reading of Gadamer, see Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 357–95; and “Der Vorlesungsgast,” in Begegnungen mit Hans-Georg Gadamer, ed. Günter Figal, trans. Joachim Schulte (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2000), 87–92. For McDowell’s application of Gadamerian insights and concepts, see John McDowell, Mind and Nature (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1996), xi–xxiv and 108–26; and “Gadamer, Davidson, and the Ground of Understanding,” in Gadamer’s Century: Essays in Honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer [Gadamer’s Century], ed.
    [Show full text]