'Ars Lnfirma' Aspects of 'Auto-Poiesis' in Heidegger and Stoic Doctrine An

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

'Ars Lnfirma' Aspects of 'Auto-Poiesis' in Heidegger and Stoic Doctrine An 'Ars lnfirma' Aspects of 'auto-poiesis' in Heidegger and Stoic doctrine An investigation into the incertitude in art Michal Klega Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Of the University of London in Fine Art Department of Visual Arts Goldsmiths College University of London 2008 Content Abstract 4 Introduction 5 Chapter I Art and a 'Way of Life' 13 1. What is Socrates' Way of Life? 23 2. Agon an Reality 28 3. Art as a 'Way of Life' 31 4. The Possibility of 'Making Art' 33 5. ' Awareness' (prosoche) 37 6. 'Way of Life' and the 'Sway of Being' 38 Chapter II Heidegger's Authenticity and Work 43 1. The Constitution ofa 'Self' in 'Being and Time' 47 a. Being and Dasein 48 b. Existence 53 c. Anxiety 57 d. Turning away from Beings 59 e. 'Care-structure' 61 f. Authenticity ofDasein and 'Being-towards-Death' 65 g. 'Willingness-to-have-Consciousness' 67 h. Being-guilty' 69 i. 'Resolve' as Care 70 j. 'Care' and 'Oikeiosis' 71 k. Self and Guilt 74 1. Fate and History 76 m. Conclusion 77 2. 'Poiesis' and 'Challenging-forth' 78 a. The Origin of the Work of Art 82 b. Poiesis and Mastery 96 c. Poiesis and Science 102 d. Art and the Artist 105 e. Art and the "Unumgangliche" III f. Conclusion 116 2 Chapter III Antiquity and the 'Way of Life' 122 1. The Concept of'agon' 124 2. The Concept of 'logos' 128 3. Socrates' Care of the self 138 4. Stoic Doctrine 141 a. Oikeiosis as Familiarity 146 b. Categories 147 c. Fate and Detennination 148 d. Pathe 151 e. The Unity of the Soul 154 f. Exercises 157 g. The Virtuous Choice 159 h. The Therapeutic Aspect of 'logos' 163 i. Virtue as Wisdom 166 j. Virtue and Conversion 169 5. Conversion 171 Chapter IV Heidegger and the Stoics 176 1. Conversion and the Self 178 2. The "Ungeheure" and the Self 180 3. Consideration, Decision and Volition 182 4. 'Agon', 'Polemos', and 'Logos' 187 5. Conversion and Enthusiasm 190 6. Arete and Poiesis 197 Conclusion 201 Abbreviations 207 Bibliography 208 3 Abstract This research investigates a possible agency for 'making art'. It focuses on the convergence of 'life' and 'art' by comparing two conceptions of self-understanding: the Heideggerian 'Dasein', and the Stoic quest for the 'virtuous act'. These serve as a paradigm for the possible integration of the 'self of the artist and the 'work' as an 'ethics' of enduring in 'incertitude'. The first aspect of the convergence of 'life' and 'work' is the separation of the 'in­ strumental' and the 'virtuous'. I refer to Huizinga's research into the concept of the 'agon' and the concept of 'conversion' as elaborated on by Pierre Hadot The second aspect deals with the Stoic therapeutic concept of philosophy, which leads to the third aspect which is the 'comportment' within which questioning is guided by the disposition of 'discretio', a tact towards the aporia of 'knowledge'. Giorgio Colli points to the words of the 'oracle' as the symbol of language, because it discloses and withdraws (truth) at the same time. The concept of 'logos' he develops I relate to Heidegger's 'letting-be' (Gelassenheit) as the originary comportment to beings in the movement of concealment and unconcealment as the site of 'truth'. I argue that the necessary conditions for 'art' originate in the 'agon' as ordeal and ac­ tion as well as in the psychagogical methodology of 'awareness' (prosoche) which underpins the possibility to interrogate the particular mode of constituted conscious­ ness as it expresses itself in 'comportment', and the concept of 'phronesis, which moderates disclosure and withdrawal, concealment and unconcealment I argue that this mode is itself a 'poiesis', which has as its temporal 'telos' its own existence as the origin of art itself 4 Introduction This thesis was written within the remits of a combined theory and practice based course, and emphasises therefore aspects of interest rooted in my own practice_ These are not related to the particular forms of the work I produce, but to the inter­ nal modality which drives such activity in general and accords with my experience_ The barriers between art and life have been blurred for some time now but there is still a 'desire' for the 'creative' artist as a 'personality' _To narrow this vast subject to a more manageable size, I have used Martin Heidegger's interpretation of Greek on­ tology in Being and Time as a starting point and compared it with the Greek under­ standing of the self and its constitution and formation_ Heidegger's 'retrieval' (Wied­ erholung) of Greek ontological thought and the rejection of Platonic teleology as 'metaphysics' appears in relation to the Presocratics as a reconfiguration of the ar­ chaic 'agon' - as a 'judgment by ordeal': the telos is the fate as logos_ Virtue is a dis­ closure of the possibility of disclosure itself and therefore an 'ethos', a comportment I investigate certain modes of speaking about the possibility of making art, as they are presented in Greek psychagogy or 'paideia', where the' self' is revealed in its ethical dimension as a product of 'consideration' and a form of 'aletheia' _The first access to such an approach became, in the progress of my investigation, the writings of Martin Heidegger, while the Greek idea of a 'care ofthe self' related these in­ sights to the everyday experiences of human actions and exercises_ The 'way oflife' is central to human beings only_ Life is always 'artistic' in this sense, and the Greeks understood their life to be such a 'work of art' _This is therefore a thesis guided by the particular interest of an artist to understand the strange presuppositions of 'crea­ tive' forces, which he follows but does not control and which are not a mere 'subjec­ tive' fancy, but an ontological inquiry into one's own 'being'_ 'Being' is always ar­ tistic and not in our controL The thesis is generally about the concepts of the appearance of a self within its eve­ ryday structures and its possibility and parameters_ In my own experience, making art is first about one's 'self', how it is fitted into its environment and its sensitivity in questioning incongruencies and contradictions within such an environment The state of mind which enables proper questioning has to achieve both, the loss of the com- 5 fort of what is taken for granted as much as unfolding what is around rather than ar­ bitrarily proposing 'new beginnings'. However, it is also the exercise of the mind (not only of the artist) which I am most interested in and which is expressed by ques­ tioning the Greek and especially Stoic practices which are expressly designed to withdraw from a myopic concentration on the things that we take for granted and be­ gin to question: not the things but a 'self' which we always already have become in our dealings with beings without consideration about the possibility and the modes of such dealings. To have an idea is 'not' to have the certitude of knowledge. Art can never be the 'terra firma' of knowledge. There are ideas, they are neither mine nor are they yours. The artist has an idea. They come into a mind, they are not eternal, they are bound to a particular time. What is the 'Being' of such ideas and the mind apprehending them? The first chapter opens up the question of how a 'way of life' and 'art' are connected in general. The concepts within which this discourse takes place are drawn from the Greek experience, which still dominates our understanding. The development from the Greek 'agon', 'logos' and the Socratic expression of 'arete' and 'agathon' as a transcendent principle devaluing 'worldly' goods are the basic elements of this re­ search. From there, the question of production (poiesis) arises as the main question of how 'existence' becomes a creation and how agency is attributed by the Stoics, and, alternatively, in Heidegger's Being and Time. Heidegger's Dasein is 'authentic' when it understands itself as the 'possibility' for the site in which beings find their truth. In becoming 'authentic' Dasein turns away from its 'objects' towards its own Being. Pierre Hadot is one of the few commentators on ancient philosophy who points out forcefully that philosophy was a 'way oflife' and not 'science' or 'metaphysics'. Moulding a virtuous character means to live the 'eudamonic' life. To do this, the 'self' has to understand itself, and its own constituted character. By way of self­ 'decomposition' it has to undo the discourse of mere survival (instrumentality), which tied it to passions and attachments. This procedure is what is called 'askesis' or 'exercise' and ultimately leads to a 'con-version' of the foundations on which the previous understanding was based. 6 Heidegger's path tries to revert the reflective strategy of the Stoics by placing em­ phasis on Dasein's always underlying immediate (un-self-conscious) intuition of be­ ings and a reassertion ofthe 'attunement' (Gestimmtheit) as the originary aspect of 'receiving-perceiving' of phenomena as they 'present themselves'. Artistic practice, in terms of 'poiesis', is important for Heidegger as the agency that fonns a collective 'way oflife'. This 'poiesis' is 'inspired' in the sense that it is not the self or individ­ ual artist but his 'listening' or being the medium of a historic movement This 'poie­ sis' takes place in a space antecedent to the constitution of a 'self', which today de­ tennines 'Being' as technology and metaphysics. Coming back to the Greek experience of 'self-improvement' as self-constitution, the concepts of 'poiesis' and the archaic 'agon' supply the notion of transcending the sphere of mere' survival'.
Recommended publications
  • Herakleitos (121.6Kb)
    The Reign of the Whirlwind 122 Chapter 7 Herakleitos ----------- 1. Life and book We have very little reliable information about the life of Herakleitos son of Bloson, of Ephesos. It is clear from the biographical accounts that survive, that the Alexandrian scholars could find little, even though they were not fussy about reliability. They made up anecdotes to fit some of the more striking sayings of this paradox-loving writer; and as a result, “Herakleitos the Dark” became even more obscure. We have to guess, first, at his dates. He knows something about Pythagoras and Xenophanes; and Parmenides seems to know something about him. We can hazard the conjecture that his book was written by 500 BCE (when Xenophanes had still the last quarter of his long life to live, and Pythagoras was in his last years). This would make 545 BCE a reasonable guess for his birth date. He probably died before 480.i Herakleitos belonged to the ancient royal clan of Ephesos. He is said to have deposited his book in the great temple of Artemis for which his native city was famous (22 A 1).ii We can fairly suppose that it was in his eyes the worthy trophy of a greater victory than any triumph in arms. Whether he was actually melancholic (“the weeping philosopher” as he came to be called)iii we cannot say. He was certainly both an angry man, and an intellectual aristocrat. There are some The Reign of the Whirlwind 123 “sayings” of his that were not in the book. In one plausible story, he “upbraids the Ephesians .
    [Show full text]
  • Senecan Tragedy and Virgil's Aeneid: Repetition and Reversal
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 10-2014 Senecan Tragedy and Virgil's Aeneid: Repetition and Reversal Timothy Hanford Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/427 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] SENECAN TRAGEDY AND VIRGIL’S AENEID: REPETITION AND REVERSAL by TIMOTHY HANFORD A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Classics in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2014 ©2014 TIMOTHY HANFORD All Rights Reserved ii This dissertation has been read and accepted by the Graduate Faculty in Classics in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Ronnie Ancona ________________ _______________________________ Date Chair of Examining Committee Dee L. Clayman ________________ _______________________________ Date Executive Officer James Ker Joel Lidov Craig Williams Supervisory Committee THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract SENECAN TRAGEDY AND VIRGIL’S AENEID: REPETITION AND REVERSAL by Timothy Hanford Advisor: Professor Ronnie Ancona This dissertation explores the relationship between Senecan tragedy and Virgil’s Aeneid, both on close linguistic as well as larger thematic levels. Senecan tragic characters and choruses often echo the language of Virgil’s epic in provocative ways; these constitute a contrastive reworking of the original Virgilian contents and context, one that has not to date been fully considered by scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucan's Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulf
    Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2014 Reading Committee: Catherine Connors, Chair Alain Gowing Stephen Hinds Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics © Copyright 2014 Laura Zientek University of Washington Abstract Lucan’s Natural Questions: Landscape and Geography in the Bellum Civile Laura Zientek Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Professor Catherine Connors Department of Classics This dissertation is an analysis of the role of landscape and the natural world in Lucan’s Bellum Civile. I investigate digressions and excurses on mountains, rivers, and certain myths associated aetiologically with the land, and demonstrate how Stoic physics and cosmology – in particular the concepts of cosmic (dis)order, collapse, and conflagration – play a role in the way Lucan writes about the landscape in the context of a civil war poem. Building on previous analyses of the Bellum Civile that provide background on its literary context (Ahl, 1976), on Lucan’s poetic technique (Masters, 1992), and on landscape in Roman literature (Spencer, 2010), I approach Lucan’s depiction of the natural world by focusing on the mutual effect of humanity and landscape on each other. Thus, hardships posed by the land against characters like Caesar and Cato, gloomy and threatening atmospheres, and dangerous or unusual weather phenomena all have places in my study. I also explore how Lucan’s landscapes engage with the tropes of the locus amoenus or horridus (Schiesaro, 2006) and elements of the sublime (Day, 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Kaikkivaltias Jumala Ja Hyveellinen Maailmankaikkeus Kleemens Roomalaisen Ensimmäinen Kirje Stoalaisessa Kontekstissa
    Kaikkivaltias Jumala ja hyveellinen maailmankaikkeus Kleemens Roomalaisen ensimmäinen kirje stoalaisessa kontekstissa Tuomas J. Salo Dogmatiikan pro gradu -tutkielma Huhtikuu 2015 HELSINGIN YLIOPISTO HELSINGFORS UNIVERSITET Tiedekunta/Osasto Fakultet/Sektion Laitos Institution Teologinen tiedekunta Systemaattisen teologian laitos TekijäFörfattare Tuomas Juhani Salo Työn nimi Arbetets titel Kaikkivaltias Jumala ja hyveellinen maailmankaikkeus : Kleemens Roomalaisen ensimmäinen kirje stoalaisessa kontekstissa. Oppiaine Läroämne Dogmatiikka Työn laji Arbetets art Aika Datum Sivumäärä Sidoantal Pro gradu -tutkielma 1.4.2015 90 Tiivistelmä Referat Tämän tutkielman tavoite on kartoittaa ja analysoida Kleemens Roomalaisen ensimmäisen kirjeen (todennäköisesti 90-luvulla jKr.) ja samassa historiallisessa kontekstissa vallalla olleen stoalaisen ajattelun välisiä yhteneväisyyksiä ja eroavaisuuksia. Metodi on systemaattinen analyysi. Lähde on Kleemens Roomalaisen ensimmäinen kirje. Taustaluvussa tutustutaan stoalaisen filosofisen koulukunnan historiaan sen alkuvaiheista Ateenassa aina sen kultakauteen Rooman imperiumin populaarifilosofiana. Samoin tutustutaan Rooman ja Korintin seurakuntien historialliseen tilanteeseen kirjeen lähettämisen aikoihin. Etiikkaa käsittelevässä pääluvussa ”Kleemensin” eettistä ajattelua suhteessa stoalaisen filosofian eettiseen momenttiin. Hyveteorian kannalta huomataan, että kummassakin järjestelmässä ihmisen hyveellistä toimintaa ohjaa jokin sisäinen tiedollis-asenteellinen elementti. Kleemensillä se on vanhurskaus,
    [Show full text]
  • Apocalypses and the Sage. Different Endings of the World in Seneca
    ARTÍCULOS Gerión. Revista de Historia Antigua ISSN: 0213-0181 http://dx.doi.org/10.5209/GERI.63869 Apocalypses and the Sage. Different Endings of the World in Seneca Francesca Romana Berno1 Recibido: 9 de abril 2018 / Aceptado: 29 de octubre de 2018 Abstract. This paper deals with apocalypse, intended as a revelation or prediction related to the end of the world, in Seneca’s prose work. The descriptions and readings of this event appear to be quite different from each other. My analysis will follow two main directions. Firstly, I will show the human side of the question, focussing on the condition of the sage facing the universal ruin in the context of the macroscopic narrative structure of most passages, and on the differences between the Epicurean and the Stoic view on this point. Secondly, I will turn to the descriptions of the end of the world which we can find in the Naturales Quaestiones. I will argue that Seneca’s choice of flood or conflagration as representations for the apocalypse are not haphazard, but may be motivated by a subtle political narrative, and thus linked to the Stoic struggle for taking part in the governing of the state. In particular, the end of book three represents a flood which probably alludes toTiber’s floods. Keywords: Seneca; Final flood;ekpyrosis ; End of the world; Fire of Rome; Tiber’s flood. [esp] El sabio y los apocalipsis. Diferentes fines del mundo en Séneca Resumen. Este artículo trata del apocalipsis, entendido como una revelación o predicción relacionada con el fin del mundo, en las obras en prosa de Séneca.
    [Show full text]
  • Dissertação Apresentada Por ANDERSON ALEXANDRE RODRIGUES Ao Programa
    UEM UNIVERSIDADE ESTADUAL DE MARINGÁ CENTRO DE CIÊNCIAS HUMANAS, LETRAS E ARTES PROGRAMA DE PÓS-GRADUAÇÃO EM EDUCAÇÃO ÁREA DE CONCENTRAÇÃO: EDUCAÇÃO ANDERSO N ALEXANDRE RODRIGUES RODRIGUES ALEXANDRE N O CARÁTER PEDAGÓGICO DA FILOSOFIA SENEQUIANA ANDERSON ALEXANDRE RODRIGUES MARINGÁ 2020 2020 UNIVERSIDADE ESTADUAL DE MARINGÁ CENTRO DE CIÊNCIAS HUMANAS, LETRAS E ARTES PROGRAMA DE PÓS-GRADUAÇÃO EM EDUCAÇÃO ÁREA DE CONCENTRAÇÃO: EDUCAÇÃO Dissertação apresentada por ANDERSON ALEXANDRE RODRIGUES ao Programa de Pós-Graduação em Educação da Universidade Estadual de Maringá, como um dos requisitos para a obtenção do título de Mestre em Educação. Área de Concentração: EDUCAÇÃO. Orientador: Prof. Dr.: JOSÉ JOAQUIM PEREIRA MELO. MARINGÁ 2020 Dados Internacionais de Catalogação-na-Publicação (CIP) (Biblioteca Central - UEM, Maringá - PR, Brasil) Rodrigues, Anderson Alexandre R696c O caráter pedagógico da filosofia Senequiana / Anderson Alexandre Rodrigues. -- Maringá, PR, 2020. 93 f.: il. color., figs., tabs. Orientador: Prof. Dr. José Joaquim Pereira Melo. Dissertação (Mestrado) - Universidade Estadual de Maringá, Centro de Ciências Humanas, Letras e Artes, Departamento de Fundamentos da Educação, Programa de Pós- Graduação em Educação, 2020. 1. Educação - Filosofia. 2. Sêneca, Lúcio Aneu, ca. 4 a.C - 65 d.C - Proposta educativa. 3. Educação - História. 4. Sêneca, Lúcio Aneu, ca. 4 a.C - 65 d.C - Estudo da filosofia. I. Melo , José Joaquim Pereira , orient. II. Universidade Estadual de Maringá. Centro de Ciências Humanas, Letras e Artes. Departamento de FundamentosCDD da 23.ed. 370.9 Educação. Programa de Pós-Graduação em Educação. III. Título. Rosana de Souza Costa de Oliveira - 9/1366 ANDERSON ALEXANDRE RODRIGUES O CARÁTER PEDAGÓGICO DA FILOSOFIA SENEQUIANA BANCA EXAMINADORA Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucan's Pharsalia: the Stoic Cosmos As a Mirror
    Lucan’s Pharsalia: The Stoic Cosmos as a Mirror At the center of Lucan’s Pharsalia is an extended allegory that binds a Rome hurtling toward Civil War to a cosmos careening toward the Stoic ekpyrosis (conflagration). Recently, scholars have worked to elucidate the oft-noticed contradiction in Lucan’s depiction of the Stoic cosmos, namely that his cosmos is both Stoic and not Stoic (Lapidge 1979, Sklenar 1999). Attempts to pigeon-hole the Pharsalia into one of these categories lead to myopic or incomplete readings of the text. In his article concerning this contradiction, Paul Roche (quoting D. Feeney) notes, ‘In literary criticism you can often go a long way by saying, if someone brings up a problem, “Yes, that’s the point’” (Roche 2005). This paper, drawing from recent studies of Stoic physical theory, will further elucidate the contradiction found in Lucan’s text and will offer ways of understanding this contradiction and its essential rhetorical role in the epic. The contradiction involves the relationship between Stoic physics and Stoic ethics, a topic much debated in recent years. The orthodox theory holds that knowledge of Stoic cosmology is necessary for living a virtuous life. Most scholars agree that on reason (among others) that knowledge of Stoic cosmology was desirable was because it provided the Stoic with a providential view of the cosmos (Inwood 2009). This argument for the benefit of the cosmic viewpoint was often employed by Stoic philosophers to account for “the apparent counterintuitive thesis that pain and death are not evils” (Boeri 2009). Seneca, Lucan’s uncle, writes as much in his Consolatio ad Marciam.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Unformed Substance and Old Academic Ontology
    Stoic Unformed Substance and Old Academic Ontology Martin Skipper University College London 2009 PhD. 1 Stoic Unformed Substance and Old Academic Ontology I, Martin Skipper, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 Stoic Unformed Substance and Old Academic Ontology Abstract: This thesis examines the influences on the Stoics‟ development of their material principle. The thesis argues that the reasons for the Stoics‟ conceiving of a material principle as they did actually have their origins in metaphysical speculation rather than physics. While the natural philosophy of the Ionians, as interpreted by Aristotle and his followers, no doubt furnished the intellectual background for a persisting material substrate of all sensible change, it is in fact the concerns of Plato and his early followers with the non-sensible that exert the strongest influence on the Stoics. The thesis examines the concepts of space and matter in the Timaeus ultimately rejecting this work of physics as central to the development of Stoic thought on matter. Rather it is the metaphysical doctrines of Plato and his successors, and the use they make of an incorporeal matter, that exerted the greatest influence on the Stoics and their material principle. The interpretation of Platonic metaphysics argued for in the thesis, based on the Unwritten Doctrines and the Old Academy‟s teachings, challenges the majority opinion of the English speaking community; and as a result offers a novel understanding of the relationship of Stoicism to Platonic metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca on Platonic Apatheia
    © Museum Tusculanum Press :: University of Copenhagen :: www.mtp.dk :: [email protected] SENECA ON PLATONIC APATHEIA By Michael Fournier Summary: In his Ad Marciam, Seneca makes use of the technique of prosopopeia in order to address Marcia in the guise of the philosopher Areus, Nature, and her father Cordus, who is now deified and speaking from the perspective of providence. These addresses form a series of exhortations which are involved in the project of consolation and give a philosophical structure to a text oft maligned as incoherent. Scholars generally consider Seneca’s Ad Marciam to be a flawed example of Stoic consolation. My own view is that Seneca’s presentation of a variety of consolatory strategies is not evidence of his carelessness and inconsistency, but part of the progression which the work commends to Marcia and to the reader. The progression leads the bereaved from the human perspective, to the standpoint of Nature, and concludes with the divine perspective. This progression becomes clear when the three prosopopeiae, which are generally ignored or regarded by commentators such as Manning1 or Favez2 as mere rhetorical flourishes, are interpreted as representatives of the three levels of consolatory wisdom. The result is that the work concludes, not with a Stoic apatheia that is opposed to the moderation proffered at the outset, but with a distinction between worldly virtue and divine virtue. This distinction an- ticipates Plotinus’ delineation between the moderation appropriate to civic virtue and the apatheia of the purified virtues in Nous which are above the passions. Seneca’s Ad Marciam is also widely regarded as a work which subordinates or abandons philosophical coherence in favor of rhetorical and generic con- 1 C.E.
    [Show full text]
  • Horror in Seneca's Thyestes and Lovecraft's
    Buchanan 1 Marshall Buchanan Prof. Nelson-Hawkins Latin 5014 December 14, 2012 Horror in Seneca’s Thyestes and Lovecraft’s “The Call of Cthulhu” There are no grounds for establishing a direct literary tradition between the twentieth-century American writer of horror—H.P. Lovecraft—and the Stoic philosopher of Julio-Claudian Rome—L. Annaeus Seneca. Lovecraft himself writes only passingly of Seneca in his survey of Roman writers to praise his eminence in Latin letters of the Silver Age (“Literature of Rome” 29), and, in his brief appraisal of classical writers of the ‘weird,’ notes only specific incidents in the works of Pliny the Younger, Petronius, Apuleius, and Phlegon of Tralles, making no mention of the sanguinary dramas of Seneca (“Supernatural” 85). Yet, as these instances manifest, Lovecraft was clearly aware of and broadly acquainted with classical literature and culture and acknowledged it as the basis of the contemporary Western culture with which he fervently identified. (It is worth noting, too, that the foremost scholar of Lovecraft’s life and works, S. T. Joshi, is a graduate from the Department of Classics at Brown University [Joshi, “S.T.Joshi”].) Moreover, as a professed conservative, Lovecraft’s conscious incorporation of traditional motifs and aesthetic values into his own work is a strong basis for a mutually illuminating comparison of Lovecraft and Seneca. What makes this mutual illumination more compelling than simply a too general commonality of tradition is that, despite the major differences in their ostensible world views, both men in practice appealed to a similar aesthetic of cosmic horror, and furthermore used similar devices in developing that aesthetic.
    [Show full text]
  • View Community College
    INFORMATION TO USERS This reproduction was made from a copy of a document sent to us for microfilming. While the most advanced technology has been used to photograph and reproduce this document, the quality of the reproduction is heavily dependent upon the quality of the material submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help clarify markings or notations which may appear on this reproduction. 1. The sign or “target” for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is “Missing Page(s)”. If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting through an image and duplicating adjacent pages to assure complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a round black mark, it is an indication of either blurred copy because of movement during exposure, duplicate copy, or copyrighted materials that should not have been filmed. For blurred pages, a good image of the page can be found in the adjacent frame. If copyrighted materials were deleted, a target note will appear listing the pages in the adjacent frame. 3. When a map, drawing or chart, etc., is part of the material being photographed, a definite method of “sectioning” the material has been followed. It is customary to begin filming at the upper left hand comer of a large sheet and to continue from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. If necessary, sectioning is continued again—beginning below the first row and continuing on until complete.
    [Show full text]
  • Pneuma in Early Stoicism Robert Heller Royal
    PNEUMA IN EARLY STOICISM ROBERT HELLER ROYAL HOLLOWAY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON PhD 1 Declaration of Authorship I ………………………………… hereby declare that this thesis and the work presented in it is entirely my own. Where I have consulted the work of others, this is always clearly stated. Signed: ______________________ Date: ___________ 2 Abstract: The thesis proceeds on the supposition that there is an underlying theoretical unity between the three parts of philosophy and that the principle of coherence presupposes an element of continuity from one Stoic head to another. As such, whilst a fully- fledged theory of pneuma can only be attributed to Chrysippus, the third head of the school, the character of the theory is seen to be determined from much earlier with Zeno, who is the cause for the emergence of a pneuma with such unique characteristics in Chrysippus. Although the thesis does not pretend to be a comprehensive study of the concept of pneuma in Stoic thought, in order to trace the key characteristics of the Chrysippean concept in the earliest stages of the school and to reconstruct an outline of the underlying theory, I chart the evidence describing the mechanical processes involved in the pneuma’s variations in tension, its contraction and expansion, its growth and nourishment and the relation between the hegemonikon and the soul. These themes are discussed in chapters which are related to specific theories of the Stoics like cosmogony and cognitive process. The nature of the methodological approach means that I often use evidence from seemingly disparate parts of the Stoic system in order to better understand the processes involved and I also consider evidence from the doxographical records and extant commentaries which is largely ignored in the modern literature or is absent from von Arnim’s collection.
    [Show full text]