Of Stoic Cosmology SI 7.50

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Of Stoic Cosmology SI 7.50 I • The Origins of Stoic Cosmology SI 7.50 THE ORIGINS OF STOIC COSMOLOGY David E. Hahm Though there never was in antiquity a single, all-pervasive ideology or school of philosophy, for half a millennium beginning about 300 B.C., the Stoic outlook, as it apprehended both the physical and ethical universes, captured a sufficiently large number of adherents to be considered the ancient counterpart of the currently popular scientific world view. This world view of the Stoics appealed to all classes and attracted slaves and laborers as well as kings and emperors. Its ideas and tenets infiltrated and shaped all branches of art and learning —poetry, drama, religion, theology, science, medicine, law. and govern­ ment — and its concepts influenced and in­ formed the later doctrines of Christianity, Gnosticism, Neo-Pythagoreanism, and Neo­ platonism. Despite its undoubted historical importance, however, the question of Stoicism's origin has usually been passed over with glib generaliza­ tions; and there has remained, until the ap­ pearance of Professor Hahm's book, a crucial need to undertake a systematic study of all the evidence in order to determine conclusively from whom the ideas of the Stoics were de­ rived, what sorts of ideas they appropriated, and how they used this borrowed material to create a new and enduring popular philosophy. Professor Hahm performs this service for one of the major areas of Stoic philosophy. On the basis of a new and more careful recon­ struction of the cosmological theories of Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus, the three heads of the Stoic school in the third century B.C., Hahm demonstrates that Stoic cosmology grew directly out of the contemporary philosophical and scientific debates and was, in fact, a unique, original synthesis of the latest Greek theories of cosmology and biology. (Continued on hack flap) THE ORIGINS OF STOIC COSMOLOGY David E. Hahm The Origins of Stoic Cosmology OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY PRESS Copyright © 1977 by the Ohio State University Press All rights reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Hahm, David E. The origins of Stoic cosmology. Includes indexes. 1. Stoics. 2. Cosmology, Ancient. I. Title. B528.H33 113 76-20712 ISBN 0-8142-0253-5 TO FRIEDRICH SOLMSEN Contents Preface IX Abbreviations xi Introduction xiii ι Corporealism 3 II Principles 29 II Cosmogony 57 IV Cosmology 91 V Cosmobiology 136 VI The Cosmic Cycle 185 VII : Epilogue: The Definition of Nature and the Origins of Stoic Cosmology 200 Appendixes I. Influences on Stoicism According to the Biographical Tradition 219 II. The Contents of Book One of Chrysippus's Physics 238 III. Cleanthes' Cosmogony 240 IV. Accounts of the Stoic Proofs for the Immobility and Coherence of the Cosmos 249 V. Chrysippus's Statement on the Alleged Imperishability of the Cosmos 260 VI. Cleanthes' Proof for the Intelligence of the Cosmos 267 Indexes 275 Preface Although I can never adequately express my gratitude to all who aided me in writing this book, I would like to acknowledge at least my most outstanding personal debts. My foremost obligation is to my teacher and friend, Friedrich Solmsen, to whom this book is gratefully dedi­ cated. It was he who through his writings and personal discussions awakened in me a zeal for Greek philosophy in general and an interest in Stoic physics in particular. In writing the thesis from which this book evolved and in reshaping it for publication, I was guided by his encouragement and his generous and painstaking criticism. I would also like to thank those who enabled me to devote a full year to reshaping this work, namely, the National Endowment for the Humanities, which awarded me a summer fellowship, and the Center for Hellenic Studies in Washington, D.C. together with its director Bernard M. W. Knox, which provided me a year of leisure in an idyllic mouseion. I am also grateful to Charles L. Babcock, Herbert M. Howe, Robert J. Lenardon, Mark P. Morford, Paul Plass, Wesley D. Smith, and several anonymous referees for ideas, advice, criticism, and encouragement along the way, to Vicki Nau for typing the manu­ script, to the Ohio State University College of Humanities for a grant- in-aid to defray the cost of typing the manuscript, and to Sarah T. Millett of the Ohio State University Press for many refinements in the text. Finally my deepest debt is to my wife, Donna, not only for eliminat­ ing countless errors, suggesting many improvements, and proof­ reading the entire manuscript, but above all for her patience, under­ standing, and unfailing support, without which this book would never have been written. The manuscript of this book was completed a few years ago. Since then many important publications have appeared of which I have been x Preface unable to take account. I particularly regret that I have been unable to make use of L. Bloos, Probleme der stoischen Physik, Hamburger Studien zur Philosophic 4 (Hamburg, 1973); A. Graeser, Zenon von Kition: Positionen und Probleme (Berlin, 1975); M. Lapidge, "Αρχαί and (ττουχέϊα: A Problem in Stoic Cosmology," Phronesis 18 (1973): 240-78; J. Longrigg, "Elementary Physics in the Lyceum and Stoa" his 66 (1975): 211-29; and K. von Fritz, "Zenon von Kition," RE, 2d ser. 10A (Munich, 1972): 83-121. David E. Hahm The Ohio State University Columbus, Ohio February, 1976 Abbreviations Abbreviations of the names of ancient authors and works follow the systems used in The Oxford Classical Dictionary (Oxford, 1949; 2d ed., 1970) and H. G. Liddell, R. Scott, and H. S. Jones, eds., A Greek-English Lexikon9 (Oxford, 1940). Citations are normally by book and chapter or paragraph, or by standard page number and line. Where pages and lines of a specific edition, or where fragments are cited, I have added the editor's name. All translations are my own. In addition, I have used the following abbreviations for common jour­ nals, collections of sources, and an index: AbhMainz Abhandlungen der Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur in Mainz AC L' Antiquite Classique AGP Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie AJP American Journal of Philology BICS Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies of the Uni­ versity of London Bonitz H. Bonitz, Index Aristotelicus (Berlin, 1870; 2d ed., Graz, 1955) CQ Classical Quarterly DG H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci (Berlin, 1879) DK H. Diels, and W. Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker11 (Berlin, 1964) GGA Gottingische Gelehrte Anzeiger JHI Journal of the History of Ideas JHS Journal of Hellenic Studies Xll Abbreviations ΜΝΑ W Mededelingen der koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Afdeeling Letterkunde MusHelv Museum Helveticum NGG Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaft zu Gb'ttingen PhilosRev Philosophical Review RE A. Pauly, G. Wissowa, et al., Real-Encyclopadie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft RPhL Revue Philosophique de Louvain SIFC Studi Italiani di Filologia Classica SVF J. von Arnim, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (Leipzig, 1903-05; indices by M. Adler, Leipzig, 1924) The fragments of Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus are normally cited by volume and fragment number unless pages (with line numbers) are expressly mentioned. The fragments of the minor early Stoics are cited by volume, name, and fragment number. Names are abbreviated as follows: Ant. = Antipater of Tarsus; Apollod.=Apol­ lodorus of Seleuceia; Arch. = Archedemus of Tarsus; Diog. = Diogenes of Babylon. ΤΑΡΑ Transactions of the American Philological Association Introduction For half a millennium Stoicism was very likely the most widely ac­ cepted world view in the Western world. Although there was, of course, never a single all-pervasive world view in antiquity, yet from the third century B.C. to the second century A.D. more people in the Mediterranean world seem to have held a more or less Stoic conception of the world than any other. The Peripatos had its following among a few intellectuals; Platonism was dormant while skepticism ruled in the Academy; and even if Epicureanism had a slightly larger following, it, too, was limited to a small coterie of ardent believers with a somewhat larger group of sympathizers, particularly among the Roman aristo­ crats. The Stoic world view, however, appealed to all classes, attracting slaves and laborers as well as kings and emperors. Its ideas infiltrated religion and science, medicine and theology, poetry and drama, law and government. Even when it had to yield to other world views, it left its mark on Christianity, Gnosticism, Neo-Pythagoreanism, and Neo- Platonism.1 For a variety of reasons the Stoic outlook, both physical and ethical, captivated a large number of people in the ancient world, probably many more than we shall ever realize;2 and, in fact, in view of its pervasiveness, it may not be much of an exaggeration to say that the Stoic physical world view was the ancient counterpart of our cur­ rent, popular, scientific world view. In spite of the historical importance of Stoic physics, the question of its origins is usually passed over with glib generalizations or incom­ pletely tested hypotheses. The ancient intellectual historians, who sought simple family trees, probably traced Stoicism back to Socrates by way of an alleged Cynic school.3 Another tradition made Stoicism an heir of the Platonic school.4 Modern discussions, particularly the earlier ones and the handbooks, are fond of making Stoic physics xiv Introduction essentially a revival of Heraclitus, on the grounds that several Stoics wrote books about Heraclitus, and that there
Recommended publications
  • Chrysippus's Dog As a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition
    Chrysippus’s Dog as a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition Michael Rescorla Abstract: I critique an ancient argument for the possibility of non-linguistic deductive inference. The argument, attributed to Chrysippus, describes a dog whose behavior supposedly reflects disjunctive syllogistic reasoning. Drawing on contemporary robotics, I urge that we can equally well explain the dog’s behavior by citing probabilistic reasoning over cognitive maps. I then critique various experimentally-based arguments from scientific psychology that echo Chrysippus’s anecdotal presentation. §1. Language and thought Do non-linguistic creatures think? Debate over this question tends to calcify into two extreme doctrines. The first, espoused by Descartes, regards language as necessary for cognition. Modern proponents include Brandom (1994, pp. 145-157), Davidson (1984, pp. 155-170), McDowell (1996), and Sellars (1963, pp. 177-189). Cartesians may grant that ascribing cognitive activity to non-linguistic creatures is instrumentally useful, but they regard such ascriptions as strictly speaking false. The second extreme doctrine, espoused by Gassendi, Hume, and Locke, maintains that linguistic and non-linguistic cognition are fundamentally the same. Modern proponents include Fodor (2003), Peacocke (1997), Stalnaker (1984), and many others. Proponents may grant that non- linguistic creatures entertain a narrower range of thoughts than us, but they deny any principled difference in kind.1 2 An intermediate position holds that non-linguistic creatures display cognitive activity of a fundamentally different kind than human thought. Hobbes and Leibniz favored this intermediate position. Modern advocates include Bermudez (2003), Carruthers (2002, 2004), Dummett (1993, pp. 147-149), Malcolm (1972), and Putnam (1992, pp. 28-30).
    [Show full text]
  • Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge
    Western Kentucky University TopSCHOLAR® Honors College Capstone Experience/Thesis Honors College at WKU Projects Fall 2007 Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy William Turner Western Kentucky University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/stu_hon_theses Part of the Other Philosophy Commons, Other Physics Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Turner, William, "Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy" (2007). Honors College Capstone Experience/Thesis Projects. Paper 111. http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/stu_hon_theses/111 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by TopSCHOLAR®. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors College Capstone Experience/ Thesis Projects by an authorized administrator of TopSCHOLAR®. For more information, please contact [email protected]. P │ S─Z─T │ P Zeno of Elea: Where Space, Time, Physics, and Philosophy Converge An Everyman’s Introduction to an Unsung Hero of Philosophy Will Turner Western Kentucky University Abstract Zeno of Elea, despite being among the most important of the Pre-Socratic philosophers, is frequently overlooked by philosophers and scientists alike in modern times. Zeno of Elea’s arguments on have not only been an impetus for the most important scientific and mathematical theories in human history, his arguments still serve as a basis for modern problems and theoretical speculations. This is a study of his arguments on motion, the purpose they have served in the history of science, and modern applications of Zeno of Elea’s arguments on motion.
    [Show full text]
  • Herakleitos (121.6Kb)
    The Reign of the Whirlwind 122 Chapter 7 Herakleitos ----------- 1. Life and book We have very little reliable information about the life of Herakleitos son of Bloson, of Ephesos. It is clear from the biographical accounts that survive, that the Alexandrian scholars could find little, even though they were not fussy about reliability. They made up anecdotes to fit some of the more striking sayings of this paradox-loving writer; and as a result, “Herakleitos the Dark” became even more obscure. We have to guess, first, at his dates. He knows something about Pythagoras and Xenophanes; and Parmenides seems to know something about him. We can hazard the conjecture that his book was written by 500 BCE (when Xenophanes had still the last quarter of his long life to live, and Pythagoras was in his last years). This would make 545 BCE a reasonable guess for his birth date. He probably died before 480.i Herakleitos belonged to the ancient royal clan of Ephesos. He is said to have deposited his book in the great temple of Artemis for which his native city was famous (22 A 1).ii We can fairly suppose that it was in his eyes the worthy trophy of a greater victory than any triumph in arms. Whether he was actually melancholic (“the weeping philosopher” as he came to be called)iii we cannot say. He was certainly both an angry man, and an intellectual aristocrat. There are some The Reign of the Whirlwind 123 “sayings” of his that were not in the book. In one plausible story, he “upbraids the Ephesians .
    [Show full text]
  • 2015 – Issue 2 (Summer)
    2015Summer Winter 2015Issue IAAA Artist Gallery—Pluto Pluto and Charon—acrylic on round canvas, Simon Kregar Overlooking Nitrogen Ice Glaciers on Pluto—digital, Ron Miller 2 From the Editor Welcome to another edition of the Pulsar. There are so many new discoveries, new leaps in technology in space exploration, and so many of you are doing incredible things with your art! I am sure there many of you who are creating beautiful things out there who have not shared with the IAAA and I want to invite you to please send in your happenings. This issue highlights artists who have been with the IAAA from the start, are working in textiles (not a traditional medium for space art, but incredible work) and creating calendars in an unusual format. I have received a few articles and announcements a little too late for publication in this issue, but be assured, they will be in the next one. Enjoy, and until next time, Ad Astra! Erika McGinnis, Pulsar Editor, [email protected] Table of Contents Gallery showcase . P. 2, 16—19 Kudos . .p. 4 Welcome New Members . P.5 Featured Artist: Roger Ferragallo . P. 7-8 From Space Art to Space Art Quilting By Robin Hart . .p. 9—12 An Evening With Alexei Leonov By Nick Stevens . .p. 13 The Heritage of Astronomical Art in Arizona By Michelle Rouch . .p. 14-15 Gallery Showcase . .p. 16—19 Board of Trustees . .p. 19 Letter From the President . P.20 Cover art: The Brain: A Cosmic Imperative, No 1 -2014- Roger Ferragallo Art Science Collaborations, Inc ASCI, October 11, 2014 - March 29, 2015, at the New York Hall of Science 23"h x 34"w, Lightjet 430 print, I remain awe-struck by the brain-mind which is a monumental work-in-process driven by a sublime cosmic imperative and complexity that knows no bounds.
    [Show full text]
  • Who Was Protagoras? • Born in Abdêra, an Ionian Pólis in Thrace
    Recovering the wisdom of Protagoras from a reinterpretation of the Prometheia trilogy Prometheus (c.1933) by Paul Manship (1885-1966) By: Marty Sulek, Ph.D. Indiana University Lilly Family School of Philanthropy For: Workshop In Multidisciplinary Philanthropic Studies February 10, 2015 Composed for inclusion in a Festschrift in honour of Dr. Laurence Lampert, a Canadian philosopher and leading scholar in the field of Nietzsche studies, and a professor emeritus of Philosophy at IUPUI. Adult Content Warning • Nudity • Sex • Violence • And other inappropriate Prometheus Chained by Vulcan (1623) themes… by Dirck van Baburen (1595-1624) Nietzsche on Protagoras & the Sophists “The Greek culture of the Sophists had developed out of all the Greek instincts; it belongs to the culture of the Periclean age as necessarily as Plato does not: it has its predecessors in Heraclitus, in Democritus, in the scientific types of the old philosophy; it finds expression in, e.g., the high culture of Thucydides. And – it has ultimately shown itself to be right: every advance in epistemological and moral knowledge has reinstated the Sophists – Our contemporary way of thinking is to a great extent Heraclitean, Democritean, and Protagorean: it suffices to say it is Protagorean, because Protagoras represented a synthesis of Heraclitus and Democritus.” Nietzsche, The Will to Power, 2.428 Reappraisals of the authorship & dating of the Prometheia trilogy • Traditionally thought to have been composed by Aeschylus (c.525-c.456 BCE). • More recent scholarship has demonstrated the play to have been written by a later, lesser author sometime in the 430s. • This new dating raises many questions as to what contemporary events the trilogy may be referring.
    [Show full text]
  • As in Milan Kundera's the Unbearable Lightness of Being
    Journal of Xi'an University of Architecture & Technology ISSN No : 1006-7930 Postmodernism and the Concept of Kitsch- As in Milan Kundera’s The Unbearable Lightness of Being Dr.Shanthichitra Associate Professor & Head, Dept. of English, College of Science and Humanities SRMIST, Chennai, India Abstract: The concept of Kitsch is one of the difficult concepts which has been so easily handles by Milan Kundera in his incredible work of art – The Unbearable Lightness of Being. Culturally accepted words and situations vs. the words which are labeled as grotesque points out that peculiar point which deviates the ordinary to sublimity. This paper studies that ordinary which is ignored in culture through Milan Kundera’s The Unbearable Lightness of Being. Keywords: Kitsch, Postmodernism, Phenomenology, Milan Kundera, Ideologies and Culture. When I came across the concept of Taipei modern Toilet diner, I was reminded of Milan Kundera’s Kitsch…This Modern Toilet diner is one of chain of themed eateries in Taiwan appealing to largely the youngsters of the city. This diner has greater relevance to the modern culture, culture in which youngsters call each other by bad words out of love…they have overcome all the grotesques!? Are they above all the human hurts?! Or is it an effort to deviate from kitsch?! Milan Kundera in his The Unbearable Lightness of Being talks about the concept of Kitsch. Kitsch is a German word that’s been adopted by a number of other languages, including English. It refers primarily to art that is overly sentimental or melodramatic, and so refers to aesthetics. What’s interesting is the way Kundera uses the concept in his novel, not to talk about art, but to talk about political ideology and about life.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Two Democritus and the Different Limits to Divisibility
    CHAPTER TWO DEMOCRITUS AND THE DIFFERENT LIMITS TO DIVISIBILITY § 0. Introduction In the previous chapter I tried to give an extensive analysis of the reasoning in and behind the first arguments in the history of philosophy in which problems of continuity and infinite divisibility emerged. The impact of these arguments must have been enormous. Designed to show that rationally speaking one was better off with an Eleatic universe without plurality and without motion, Zeno’s paradoxes were a challenge to everyone who wanted to salvage at least those two basic features of the world of common sense. On the other hand, sceptics, for whatever reason weary of common sense, could employ Zeno-style arguments to keep up the pressure. The most notable representative of the latter group is Gorgias, who in his book On not-being or On nature referred to ‘Zeno’s argument’, presumably in a demonstration that what is without body and does not have parts, is not. It is possible that this followed an earlier argument of his that whatever is one, must be without body.1 We recognize here what Aristotle calls Zeno’s principle, that what does not have bulk or size, is not. Also in the following we meet familiar Zenonian themes: Further, if it moves and shifts [as] one, what is, is divided, not being continuous, and there [it is] not something. Hence, if it moves everywhere, it is divided everywhere. But if that is the case, then everywhere it is not. For it is there deprived of being, he says, where it is divided, instead of ‘void’ using ‘being divided’.2 Gorgias is talking here about the situation that there is motion within what is.
    [Show full text]
  • A Phenomenological Investigation of Lighting in Built Environments
    Think About Thinking About Light: A Phenomenological Investigation of Lighting in Built Environments A Major Paper submitted to the Faculty of Environmental Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master in Environmental Studies, York University, Ontario, Canada. Taylor Stone 210601706 July 26, 2011 Student Signature: _____________________________________ Supervisor Signature: __________________________________ (Peter Timmerman) Stone i Table of Contents Abstract ii Foreword iii Acknowledgements iv 1. Introduction: In Search of Light 1 Times Square at Night… Light as a Topic of Inquiry… Note on Paper Structure 2. Questioning Architecture: Ecological Design as a Qualitative Field of Inquiry 8 Environmentalism and Architecture… This is Not About Architecture 3. Phenomenology: Theoretical Framework 15 In Search of the Experiential Basis of Experiences… Architectural Phenomenology… Ecophenomenology… Questions of Scale 4. Finding the Light: Experiential and Interpretive Understandings 25 Seeing the Light… Some Thoughts on Light as Metaphor… Metaphors Buried but Not Forgotten… Seeing the Light, Almost 5. Dundas Square: Big City Lights 46 The City at Night… Light and Space, and Darkness… A Cosmos Unto Itself 6. The Terrence Donnelly Centre for Cellular and Biomolecular Research: A World Without Windows 63 A World of Glass… Allan Gardens… Inside Out, Outside In 7. St. Gabriel’s Passionist Parish: In Light of Religious Experience 81 Light, Materialization, Colour… The Light of God in the Dark Ages… A New Religious Experience… Cathedral Church of St. James 8. Conclusion: Reflections 105 Summary and Concluding Remarks… Looking Back… Looking Forward… Coda: Still Searching Appendix 112 1) Research Method 2) Building Credits Works Cited 119 Stone ii Abstract This Major Paper is a phenomenological investigation of lighting in built environments.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristoxenus Elements of Rhythm: Text, Translation, and Commentary with a Translation and Commentary on Poxy 2687
    © 2009 Christopher C. Marchetti ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ARISTOXENUS ELEMENTS OF RHYTHM: TEXT, TRANSLATION, AND COMMENTARY WITH A TRANSLATION AND COMMENTARY ON POXY 2687 by CHRISTOPHER C. MARCHETTI A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Classics written under the direction of Prof. Thomas Figueira and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey May, 2009 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Aristoxenus’ Elements of Rhythm: Text, Translation, and Commentary with a Translation and Commentary on POxy 2687 By Christopher C. Marchetti Dissertation Director: Prof. Thomas Figueira Aristoxenus of Tarentum makes productive use of Aristotelian concepts and methods in developing his theory of musical rhythm in his treatise Elements of Rhythm. He applies the Aristotelian distinction between form and material and the concept of hypothetical necessity to provide an explanation for why musical rhythm is manifested in the syllables of song, the notes of melody, and the steps of dance. He applies the method of formulating differentiae, as described in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals, to codify the formal properties of rhythm. Aristoxenus’ description of the rhythmic foot presents several interpretive challenges. Our text is fragmentary, and we lack Aristoxenus’ definitions of several key terms. This study seeks to establish the meanings of these terms on the basis of a close examination of the structure of Aristoxenus’ argument. Parallel passages in Aristides Quintilianus’ On Music are considered in detail for ii their consistency or lack thereof with Aristoxenian usage.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Basic Metaphysical Argument Against Hedonism and Aristotle's Presentation of It at Eudemian Ethics 6.11
    Plato's Basic Metaphysical Argument against Hedonism David Wolfsdorf and Aristotle's Presentation of It at Eudemian Ethics 6.11 1. Introduction At Eudemian Ethics 6.11 (= Nicomachean Ethics 7.11) Aristotle introduces several views that others hold regarding pleasure's value. In particular I draw your attention to the following one. Aristotle writes that some believe that: A. No pleasure is a good thing, either in itself or incidentally. οὐδεµία ἡδονὴ εἶναι ἀγαθόν, οὔτε καθ᾽ αὑτὸ οὔτε κατὰ συµβεβηκός. (1152b8-9) Aristotle proceeds to give several reasons for this position. One is that: R. Every pleasure is a perceived genesis toward a nature, but no genesis is of the same kind as its ends, for example no building of a house is of the same kind as a house. (1152b13-15) πᾶσα ἡδονὴ γένεσίς ἐστιν εἰς φύσιν αἰσθητή, οὐδεµία δὲ γένεσις συγγενὴς τοῖς τέλεσιν, οἷον οὐδεµία οἰκοδόµησις οἰκίᾳ. Who are the believers of A and R that Aristotle is reporting? I suggest that the evidence leads us back to Plato's Philebus. There a view very similar to R is developed, and a view very similar to A is argued to depend on it. That the views Aristotle here reports can be traced back to Plato does not confirm that Plato himself held them. An argument is always necessary when inferring from a thesis stated or advanced in some Platonic text to a thesis maintained by Plato himself. But— setting that problem aside— I also said that A and R are "very similar to," I did not say that they were identical to the views expressed in Plato's Philebus.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophie Antique , Comptes Rendus Mathilde Brémond, Lectures De Mélissos
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Mathilde BRÉMOND, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos Citation for published version: Harriman, B 2019, 'Mathilde BRÉMOND, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos', Philosophie Antique. <https://journals.openedition.org/philosant/1944> Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Philosophie Antique General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 Philosophie antique Problèmes, Renaissances, Usages Comptes rendus Mathilde BRÉMOND, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos Berlin/Boston, Walter De Gruyter, 2019 (Studia Praesocratica), 595 p., ISBN : 978-3-11-054288-2. Benjamin Harriman Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/1944 ISSN: 2648-2789 Publisher Presses universitaires du Septentrion Brought to you by Ecole Normale Supérieure Paris This text was automatically generated on 10 May 2019. Mathilde Brémond, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation..
    [Show full text]
  • Lives Stoics
    LIVES of the STOICS The Art of Living from Zeno to Marcus Aurelius RYAN HOLIDAY and STEPHEN HANSELMAN Authors of The Daily Stoic PROFILE BOOKS Lives of the Stoics prelims.indd 5 05/08/2020 13:06 Lives_9780525541875_all_5p_r1.indd v 28/07/20 2:18 PM First published in Great Britain in 2020 by Profile Books Ltd 29 Cloth Fair London EC1A 7JQ www.profilebooks.com First published in the United States of America in 2020 by Portfolio/Penguin, an imprint of Penguin Random House LLC Copyright © Ryan Holiday and Stephen Hanselman, 2020 Illustrations by Rebecca DeFeld. Used with permission. Book design by Daniel Lagin 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2 Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A. The moral right of the authors has been asserted. All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise), without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and the publisher of this book. A CIP catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN 978 1 78816 260 9 eISBN 978 1 78283 550 9 Audiobook 978 1 78283 776 3 Lives of the Stoics prelims.indd 6 05/08/2020 15:05 CONTENTS Introduction ix Zeno the Prophet 1 Cleanthes the Apostle 13 Aristo the Challenger 27 Chrysippus the Fighter 39 Zeno the Maintainer 51 Diogenes the Diplomat 55 Antipater the Ethicist 65 Panaetius the Connector 75 Publius
    [Show full text]