Adriano Picoli Florianópolis 2018

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Adriano Picoli Florianópolis 2018 Adriano Picoli LINGUAGEM UNIVERSAL E UNIVERSALIDADE DA LÍNGUA: DOIS MODOS DE DAR-SE DE SENTIDO Tese submetida ao Programa de Pós- graduação em Filosofia da Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina como requisito parcial para obtenção do grau de Doutor em Filosofia. Área de Concentração: Ontologia. Linha de Pesquisa: Ontologia e Método. Orientador: Prof. Celso Reni Braida, Dr. Florianópolis 2018 Dedicatória Dedico este trabalho a uma das poucas pessoas que desde a primeira conversa nunca deixou de acreditar em meus esforços; estando presente nos momentos de desmate do terreno, de preparação do solo, do plantio, de cuidados na fase de crescimento, poda, amadurecimento e colheita, e, mesmo assim, sempre me possibilitou a liberdade de escolha do caminho a ser seguido, às vezes deixando-me atômico com a numerosa quantidade de vias, ao meu orientador: Celso Reni Braida. AGRADECIMENTOS Agradeço à CAPES e aos seus servidores pela concessão de recursos públicos na forma de 43 meses de bolsa de doutorado, sem a qual esta investigação não teria sido executada. A todos os servidores e professores do Departamento de Filosofia e da UFSC que de uma forma ou de outra colaboraram para a viabilização desta oportunidade de financiamento, em particular, à Ângela, à Irma e à Jacinta pela sempre gentil atenção à resolução das questões burocráticas. Aos membros da banca de qualificação e de defesa: Prof. Dr. Roberto Wu e Prof. Dr. Nazareno Eduardo de Almeida, os quais com suas observações e críticas possibilitaram-me a realização de muitos cortes, ganho de clareza, correções e reforços a minha interpretação. Ao Prof. Dr. Evandro Oliveira de Brito por ter aceitado participar da banca de defesa e pelas questões e sugestões. Ao Prof. Dr. Cláudio Reichert do Nascimento e à Profa. Dra. Claudia Pellegrini Drucker por terem aceitado as suplências da banca. Aos meus pais pela essencial contribuição financeira nos períodos difíceis da graduação e enquanto eu estava sem bolsa no início do doutorado. Ao meu orientador Celso R. Braida por ter-me guiado por mais esta etapa da vida acadêmica. É impossível, poderia ser dito, que através de uma conceitografia se possa fazer progredir a ciência, pois a invenção da primeira já pressupõe a realização desta última. Com a língua também se dá a mesma dificuldade aparente. Com efeito, supõe-se que ela tenha tornado possível o desenvolvimento da razão; mas como poderia o homem ter criado a língua sem a razão? Para descobrir as leis da natureza há que se utilizar instrumentos físicos; mas estes apenas podem ser produzidos mediante uma tecnologia avançada que, por sua vez, se apóia sobre o conhecimento das leis da natureza. Em todos esses casos o círculo se resolve da mesma maneira: um progresso em física resulta num progresso em tecnologia, e esta torna possível a construção de novos instrumentos mediante os quais a física por sua vez progride. A aplicação ao nosso caso é evidente.1 Mas a teoria da filosofia é ela própria um problema para a filosofia; e não apenas um possível problema, mas um problema inevitável, um que mais cedo ou mais tarde ela será obrigada a levantar.2 1 FREGE, LFL, p. 65. FBB, p. 75. “Unmöglich, sagt man, kann durch eine Begriffsschrift die Wissenschaft gefördert werden; denn die Erfindung der ersteren setzt die Vollendung der letzteren schon voraus. Ganz dieselbe Scheinschwierigkeit erhebt sich schon bei der Sprache. Diese sol die Entwicklung der Vernunft möglich gemacht haben; aber wie konnte der Mensch die Sprache schaffen ohne Vernunft? Zur Erforschung der Naturgesetze dienen die physikalischen Apparate; diese können nur durch eine fortgeschrittene Technik hervorgebracht werden, welche wieder auf der Kenntnis der Naturgesetze fußt. Der Kreis löst sich in allen Fällen auf dieselbe Weise. Ein Fortschritt in der Physik hat einen solchen in der Technik zur Folge, und dieser macht es möglich, neue Apparate zu bauen, mittels deren wieder die Physik gefördert wird. Die Anwendung auf unseren Fall ergibt sich von selbst.” 2 COLLINGWOOD, R. G. An Essay On Philosophical Method, p. 2. Tradução minha. “But the theory of philosophy is itself a problem for philosophy; and not only a possible problem, but an inevitable problem, one which sooner or later it is bound to raise.” RESUMO O ponto de partida desta investigação filosófica é a insatisfação gerada pela unificação de língua e linguagem de fórmulas através do uso do conceito de linguagem como medium universal por Jaakko Hintikka (a partir de “Frege’s hidden semantics”, de 1979) e por Martin Kusch (Linguagem como cálculo versus linguagem como meio universal, de 1989) para subsumir as distintas concepções filosóficas de linguagens desenvolvidas tanto por Frege (Conceitografia, de 1879) quanto por Gadamer (Verdade e Método, de 1960) sob a alegação principal da inefabilidade da semântica, esta pensada como impossibilidade de uma semântica completa. Analisamos os respectivos conceitos de linguagens defendidos nessas concepções, o da linguagem de fórmulas como linguagem universal a partir de Frege, e o da língua como medium universal da experiência hermenêutica a partir de Gadamer, explicitando como cada uma dessas perspectivas dá conta da expressabilidade de sentido. Constatamos que, para essas concepções de linguagens, o conceito de linguagem como medium universal torna-se vago para abarcá-las como um mesmo tipo, pois em ambas se separa nitidamente língua e linguagens lógicas. Em cada uma delas se busca a expressabilidade de sentido via modos distintos, na gadameriana concebendo a língua como condição indispensável do próprio plano humano, característica que se sustentaria na constante produtividade e inabarcabilidade da língua, o que a torna semanticamente inefável em seu todo, mas não parcialmente; e na concepção fregeana tanto a língua quanto a linguagem de fórmulas são concebidas como instrumentos limitados, a última apenas se caracteriza como um meio incrementável, aqui a inefabilidade da semântica se dá quando entendemos o conceito de inefabilidade da semântica como impossibilidade da autorreferência das fórmulas e também quando a compreendemos como inefabilidade conteudística devido ao caráter inexpressável em palavras de uma língua ou de outra linguagem instrumental de parte dos conteúdos com os quais lida o lógico. Como uma alternativa à submissão realizada por J. Hintikka e por Kusch, indicamos que caso quisermos encontrar um ponto de contato entre estas concepções filosóficas de linguagens temos que perceber que ambas operam com o mesmo conceito de fundo, o de sentido, e sob o pressuposto de sua expressabilidade intersubjetiva. Por mais que o viés metafísico de linguagem universal seja rechaçado por Gadamer, vimos através de Frege que uma linguagem universal como um construto humano na verdade é, em certo sentido, complementar às línguas, à proporção que uma linguagem de fórmulas apenas pode ser introduzida direta ou indiretamente a partir de uma língua, sendo aquela criada para corrigir as lacunas e limites desta para a expressão de pensamentos. Tanto as concepções fregeanas de língua e linguagem de fórmulas quanto a gadameriana de língua se sustentam na tese de que ser compreendido é ser expressável por via de uma linguagem, sendo a expressabilidade de sentido a condição mínima de uma linguagem, chegamos assim na defesa de um conceito minimal de linguagem como modo de dar-se de sentido, de doação de sentido. Palavras-chave: Língua. Linguagem. Universalidade. Expressabilidade. Sentido. ABSTRACT The point of departure for this philosophical inquiry is the dissatisfaction generated by the unification of tongue and language of formulas through the use of the concept of language as universal medium by Jaakko Hintikka (from “Frege’s hidden semantics”, of 1979) and Martin Kusch (Language as calculus vs. language as universal medium, of 1989) to subsume the different philosophical conceptions of languages developed by both Frege (Begriffsschrift, 1879) and by Gadamer (Truth and Method, 1960) under the main claim of the ineffability of semantics, this thought as the impossibility of a complete semantics. We analyze the respective concepts of languages defended in these conceptions, the language of formulas as universal language from Frege, and that of tongue as universal medium of the hermeneutic experience from Gadamer, explaining how each of these perspectives gives account of the expressibility of meaning. We find that for these conceptions of languages the concept of language as universal medium becomes vague to encompass them as one and the same type, since tongue and logical languages are clearly separated in both. In each one of them the expressibility of meaning is sought through different modes, in the Gadamerian tongue being conceived as an indispensable condition of the human plane itself, a characteristic that would be sustained in the constant productivity and inabarcability of the tongue, which makes it semantically ineffable in its entirety, but not partially; and in the Fregean conception both the tongue and the language of formulas are conceived as limited instruments, the latter is only characterized as an incremental means, here the ineffability of semantics occurs when we understand the concept of ineffability of semantics as impossibility of self-reference of formulas and also when we understand it as content ineffability due to the inexpressible character in words of a tongue or other instrumental language of part of the contents with which the logician deals. As an alternative to the submission by J. Hintikka and Kusch, we indicate that if we want to find a point of contact between these philosophical conceptions of languages we have to realize that both operate with the same background concept, meaning, and under the assumption of its intersubjective expressibility. As much as the metaphysical bias of universal language is rejected by Gadamer, we have seen through Frege that a universal language as a human construct in truth is in a sense complementary to tongues, to the extent that a language of formulas can only be introduced directly or indirectly from a tongue, the one created to correct the gaps and limits of this for the expression of thoughts.
Recommended publications
  • The Practical Origins of Ideas
    OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 19/1/2021, SPi The Practical Origins of Ideas Genealogy as Conceptual Reverse-Engineering MATTHIEU QUELOZ 1 OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 19/1/2021, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Matthieu Queloz 2021 The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2021 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. The pre-press of this publication was supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2020951579 ISBN 978–0–19–886870–5 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198868705.001.0001 Printed and bound in the UK by TJ Books Limited Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychological Knowledge
    Psychological Knowledge ‘Martin Kusch’s important philosophical contribution is to demonstrate the implicit individualism running through the entire literature on folk-psychology. By exposing and challenging this, he has radically changed the terms of the debate. To understand Kusch’s thesis that psychological concepts are social institutions is to understand that there must be a Gestalt switch in the entire field of philosophical psychology. To combine such a significant philosophical contribution with a brilliant, in-depth historical case-study is an achievement indeed.’ David Bloor, University of Edinburgh ‘Psychological Knowledge is an extremely fine work. In both approach and subject matter, it is related to Martin Kusch’s earlier terrific book, Psychologism, and is a very worthy successor.’ James Robert Brown, University of Toronto ‘Martin Kusch makes a compelling case that the practices of both “academic” and “folk” psychology are best approached as social institutions. In so doing he provides us with a viable transdisciplinary approach to science studies which speaks authoritatively to philosophers, historians, sociologists, and psychologists of science alike. Psychological Knowledge is an important book.’ Paul Stenner, Bath University ‘Psychological Knowledge is a masterly and timely work. It makes accessible the results of meticulous and wide-ranging scholarship. This book is beautifully clear and well organised, complete with summaries and easily memorable labels—suitable for pedagogical purposes as well as essential reading for the research community.’ Elizabeth Valentine, University of London Martin Kusch is Lecturer in the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge. He is also the author of Psychologism, Foucault’s Strata and Fields and Language as Calculus vs.
    [Show full text]
  • 269 JHBS—WILEY RIGHT BATCH Short Stand Long Reviewed By
    JHBS—WILEY RIGHT BATCH Top of RH BOOK REVIEWS 269 Base of RH Vol. 1: Historiographical perspectives; vol. 2: Methodological perspectives and applications. Amsterdam and Top of text Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Base of text Koerner, E. F. K. (1972). Bibliographia Saussureana 1870–1970: An annotated, classified bibliography on the background, development, and actual relevance of Ferdinand de Saussure’s general theory of language. Me- tuchen NJ: Scarecrow Press. Koerner, E. F. K. (1973). Ferdinand de Saussure: Origin and development of his linguistic thought in Western studies of language. A contribution to the history and theory of linguistics. Braunschweig: Friedrich Vieweg & Sohn. Koerner, E. F. K. (1995). Professing linguistic historiography. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Koerner, E. F. K. (Ed.). (1991). First person singular II: Autobiographies by North American scholars in the language sciences. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Skinner, B. F. (1976). Particulars of my life. New York: Knopf. Skinner, B. F. (1979). The shaping of a behaviorist: Part two of an autobiography. New York: Knopf. Skinner, B. F. (1983). A matter of consequences: Part three of an autobiography. New York: Knopf. Swiggers, P. (Ed.). (1999). E. F. K. Koerner: A biobibliography. Leuven: Peeters. Reviewed by JOHN E.E. JOSEPH, professor of applied linguistics, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh EH8 9LL, UK. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 36(3), 269–270 Summer 2000 ᭧ 2000 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Martin Kusch. Psychological Knowledge: A Social History and Philosophy. London and New York: Routledge, 1999. 413 pp. $99.99 ISBN 0-415-19253-6.
    [Show full text]
  • Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka
    Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka 1953 Books (a) Distributive Normal Forms in the Calculus of Predicates, Acta Philosophica Fennica 6, (1953), 71 pp. By distributing quantifiers deeper and deeper into the formulas of a finite first- order language, with or without identity, at the same time as truth-functions are transformed into a propositional normal form, we obtain a simple normal form for such formulas. This refutes the conjecture of Hilbert and Bernays that “a simply characterizable normal form is not obtainable in this way in general.” The basic properties of these distributive normal forms are established, including a set of suf- ficient conditions of inconsistency. Papers (a) “A New Approach to Sentential Logic”, Societas Scientiarum Fennica, Com- mentationes Physico-Mathematicae 17, no. 3, (1953), 13 pp. 1954 Papers (a) “An Application of Logic to Algebra”, Mathematica Scandinavia 2, (1954), 243–246. 1955 Books (a) Two Papers on Symbolic Logic, Acta Philosophica Fennica 8, (1955), 115 pp. (Includes “Form and Content in Quantification Theory”, 11–55, and “Reductions in the Theory of Types”, 57–115.) First paper: For a finite first-order language, the concept of a model set (m.s.) of formulas is defined by means of certain simple closure and compatibility conditions. Intuitively, a m.s. is a partial description of a possible world. A set of formulas is accordingly consistent if it can be embedded in some m.s. A simple proof procedure is obtained by considering rules for an attempt to embed the negation of a sentence © Springer International Publishing AG 2018 557 H. van Ditmarsch and G.
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl and the Development of Semantics Philosophia Scientiæ, Tome 2, No 4 (1997), P
    PHILOSOPHIA SCIENTIÆ JAN WOLENSKI Husserl and the development of semantics Philosophia Scientiæ, tome 2, no 4 (1997), p. 151-158 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=PHSC_1997__2_4_151_0> © Éditions Kimé, 1997, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Philosophia Scientiæ » (http://poincare.univ-nancy2.fr/PhilosophiaScientiae/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www. numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou im- pression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la pré- sente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ Husserl and the Development of Semantics Jan Wolenski Institute ofPhilosophy Jagiellonian University - Krakow - Potarid Philosophia Scientiae* 2 (4), 1997, 151-158 Jan Wolenski Abstract This paper investigates the rôle of Edmund Husserl in the development of formai or model-theoretic semantics through glasses of the distinction of language as calculus vs. language as universal médium, introduced by Jaakko Hintikka and Martin Kusch. In particular, the paper raises the question of possible Husserl's influence on the conception of language accepted in Polish philosophy, in particular by Lesniewski and Tarski. Résumé. Cet article examine le rôle d'Edmund Husserl dans le développement de la sémantique formelle ou de la sémantique fondée sur la théorie des modèles à travers la distinction, introduite par Jaakko Hintikka et Martin Kusch, du langage comme calcul et du langage comme moyen d'expression universel. L'article soulève en particulier la question d'une influence possible de Husserl sur la conception du langage partagée par la philosophie polonaise, notamment par Lesniewski et Tarski.
    [Show full text]
  • Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka
    ANNOTATED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF JAAKKO HINTIKKA 1953 Books (a) Distributive Normal Forms in the Calculus of Predicates, Acta Philosophica Fennica 6, (1953), 71pp. By distributing quantifiers deeper and deeper into the formulas of a finite first-order language, with or without identity, at the same time as truth-functions are transformed into a propositional normal form, we obtain a simple normal form for such formulas. This refutes the conjecture of Hilbert and Bernays that “a simply characterizable normal form is not obtainable in this way in general.” The basic properties of these distributive normal forms are established, including a set of sufficient conditions of inconsistency. Papers (a) “A New Approach to Sentential Logic”, Societas Scientiarum Fennica, Commentationes Physico-Mathematicae 17, no. 3, (1953), 13pp. 1954 Papers (a) “An Application of Logic to Algebra”, Mathematica Scandinavia 2, (1954), 243-246. 1955 Books (a) Two Papers on Symbolic Logic, Acta Philosophica Fennica 8, (1955), 115pp. (Includes “Form and Content in Quantification Theory”, 11-55, and “Reductions in the Theory of Types”, 57-115.) First paper: For a finite first-order language, the concept of a model set (m.s.) of formulas is defined by means of certain simple closure and compatibility conditions. Intuitively, a m.s. is a partial description of a possible world. A set of formulas is accordingly consistent if it can be embedded in some m.s.. A simple proof procedure is obtained by considering rules for an attempt to embed the negation of a sentence S in a m.s.. If such an attempt fails in all directions, a proof is obtained for S.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychologism: a Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge/Martin Kusch
    PSYCHOLOGISM For most of this century, Western philosophy has been resolutely antinaturalist, and until recently the sharp distinction between the empirical sciences and philosophy seemed almost self-evident: the questions of why they should be separate, and of how they came to be separate, were never asked. These questions are at the heart of Martin Kusch’s groundbreaking study. Antinaturalism rose to dominance in the debate on psychologism among German academic philosophers at the turn of the century. Psychologism, according to received opinion, was decisively refuted by Frege and Husserl. Kusch therefore examines their arguments and, crucially, relates them to the context that shaped that debate and gave those arguments their persuasive force. Drawing on perspectives pioneered by the sociology of scientific knowledge, he reconstructs the dynamics of the psychologism debate; he uncovers its causes and weighs the factors that determined its outcome. What emerges is the fascinating picture of a struggle, between ‘pure’ philosophy and the newly emerging experimental psychology, for academic status, social influence and institutional power. The triumph of antinaturalism, far from being the only logical conclusion, was dependent on historical contingency. Introducing forms of analysis new to the history of philosophy, Psychologism will make fascinating reading for lecturers and students of philosophy, psychology, sociology and cognitive science; it will also stimulate renewed debate on the prospects of antinaturalism at the close of this century. Martin Kusch is Lecturer at the Science Studies Unit of the University of Edinburgh. He is the author of Language as Calculus vs. Language as Universal Medium (1989), and Foucault’s Strata and Fields (1991).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Genealogy of Relativism and Absolutism Martin Kusch, University
    1 The Genealogy of Relativism and Absolutism Martin Kusch, University of Vienna & Robin McKenna, University of Vienna1 Abstract This paper applies Edward Craig’s and Bernard Williams’ ‘genealogical’ method to the debate between relativism and its opponents in epistemology and in the philosophy of language. We explain how the central function of knowledge attributions -- to ‘flag good informants’ -- explains the intuitions behind five different positions (two forms of relativism, absolutism, contextualism, and invariantism). We also investigate the question whether genealogy is neutral in the controversy over relativism. We conclude that it is not: genealogy is most naturally taken to favour an anti-realism about epistemic norms. And anti-realism threatens absolutism. Keywords Edward Craig; Bernard Williams; Paul Boghossian; epistemic relativism; semantic relativism; epistemic antirealism; invariantism; contextualism Introduction In this paper we bring together two strands of epistemological theorizing that have lived separate lives: the controversy around epistemic relativism (e.g. Boghossian 2006) and the debate over ‘the genealogy of knowledge’. The latter refers to a method first suggested in Edward Craig’s Knowledge and the State of Nature (1990), and then further developed in Bernard Williams’ Truth and Truthfulness (2002) and Steven Reynolds’ Knowledge as Acceptable Testimony (2017). There are different ways to interpret the genealogical method. On our reading (Kusch and McKenna, forthcoming), genealogy comes into its own when used to explain intuitions underlying different epistemological theories. The explanation in question is functional: the explanans are ubiquitous human needs; and the primary explananda are social practices and institutions of gathering and sharing information about the natural and social world.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Penultimate Draft Martin Kusch Disagreement, Certainties
    1 Penultimate Draft Martin Kusch Disagreement, Certainties, Relativism Department of Philosophy University of Vienna Universitätsstrasse 7 1090 Vienna Austria Email: [email protected] Phone: 0043 4277 46422 Compliance with Ethical Standards Work on this study was funded by ERC Advanced Grant Project “The Emergence of Relativism: Historical, Philosophical and Sociological Issues” (#339382). There is no conflict of interest of any kind. The article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by the author. 2 1. Introduction In this paper I want to widen the dialogue between the epistemology of peer disagreement and so-called hinge epistemology, that is, the epistemology informed by Wittgenstein’s last notebooks, later edited as On Certainty (Wittgenstein 1969). In doing so I continue a line of research started more than thirty years ago in Robert J. Fogelin’s little classic “The Logic of Deep Disagreement” (1985).1 I shall address the following questions: What are (Wittgensteinian) certainties? Can we rationally count someone a peer who denies one of our certainties? Can there be reasonable, mutually recognized, peer disagreements over a certainty? And finally, faced with a peer disagreement over a certainty (= c-disagreement), should I be “steadfast” (Kelly 2005), “conciliationist” (Christensen 2007), “justificationist” (Lackey 2008), or “relativist” (Hazlett 2014)? In answer to these questions, I shall try to make plausible, in a preliminary and tentative fashion, the following theses: (i) Not all certainties are groundless; many of them are beliefs; and they do not have a common essence. (ii) The analysis of different forms of peer disagreement calls for different renderings of the category of peer: ordinary peer, distant peer, scientific peer, and stance-dependent peer.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's on Certainty and Relativism Martin Kusch
    This is the penultimate draft of a paper published in Analytic and Continental Philosophy (ed. By Rinofner-Kreidl), Berlin Boston, Walter de Gruyter, 29-46. Wittgenstein’s On Certainty and Relativism Martin Kusch Introduction One important strand in the contemporary debate over epistemological relativism focuses on the question whether, and to what extent, Wittgenstein in On Certainty (1969) leaned towards this position. This paper is a contribution to this strand. My discussion has four parts. I shall begin by outlining my interpretation of Wittgensteinian certainties. Subsequently I shall briefly introduce some central arguments for and against attributing epistemic relativism to On Certainty. This will be followed by a sketch of the cluster of ideas that – on my analysis – define important versions of the doctrine in question. And finally I shall give my own interpretation of On Certainty in relation to epistemic relativism. On Certainty – A Brief Reminder On Certainty describes as its central interest “cases in which I rightly say I cannot be making a mistake …” And the passage continues: “I can enumerate various typical cases, but not give any common characteristic.” (§674) In this section I shall offer a classification of these “various typical cases”. On my count these cases fall into five epistemic categories. These categories differ in how certainties relate to evidence, justification and knowledge. Category I consists of beliefs for which we have evidence that is both overwhelming and (at least in good part) dialectically mute. There are eight types of such cases: (I.1) Perceptual/proprioceptive beliefs about one’s own body (e.g. “… here is a hand.” §1) (I.2) Perceptual beliefs about close familiar medium-size objects (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Feyerabend Edited by Karim Bschir , Jamie Shaw Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-47199-2 — Interpreting Feyerabend Edited by Karim Bschir , Jamie Shaw Frontmatter More Information INTERPRETING FEYERABEND This collection of new essays interprets and critically evaluates the philosophy of Paul Feyerabend. It offers innovative historical scholar- ship on Feyerabend’s take on topics such as realism, empiricism, mimesis, voluntarism, pluralism, materialism, and the mind-body problem, as well as certain debates in the philosophy of physics. It also considers the ways in which Feyerabend’s thought can contribute to contemporary debates in science and public policy, including questions about the nature of scientific methodology, the role of science in society, citizen science, scientism, and the role of expertise in public policy. The volume will provide readers with a comprehen- sive overview of the topics that Feyerabend engaged with throughout his career, showing both the breadth and the depth of his thought. karim bschir is a Lecturer at the University of St Gallen, Switzerland. His research focuses on topics in the general philosophy of science and the history of philosophy of science. He has written on the relationship of Feyerabend’s pluralism to Popper’s critical rationalism. jamie shaw is Postdoctoral Fellow at the Institute for History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, University of Toronto. His primary research interests revolve around the implications of Feyerabend’s pluralism for science funding policy. © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-47199-2 — Interpreting Feyerabend Edited by Karim Bschir , Jamie Shaw Frontmatter More Information INTERPRETING FEYERABEND Critical Essays edited by KARIM BSCHIR University of St.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Participation in the Making of Science Policy
    Public Participation in the Making of Science Policy Darrin Durant York University This paper argues that, because Science and Technology Studies (STS) lost contact with political philosophy, its defense of public participation in policy- making involving technical claims is normatively unsatisfactory. Current penchants for political under-laboring and normative individualism are critiqued, and the connections between STS and theorists of deliberative de- mocracy are explored. A conservative normativity is proposed, and STS posi- tions on public participation are discussed in relation to current questions about individual and group rights in a liberal democracy. The result is ave- nues to normatively defend public participation, by analogy with identity politics and Habermas, while also theorizing its limits. Introduction Lately, one can distinguish two strands within Science and Technology Studies (STS): theorists who understand science as an agent of culture and tend to discipline public challenges to experts, and theorists who insist on greater public participation and thus criticize expert autonomy. Harry Collins and Robert Evans (2002, 2003, and 2007) represent the former strand. They contend that STS ought to address how far public participa- tion should extend rather than just the grounds for its legitimacy. Knowing why (and when) expert advice should be especially valued re- quires, for Collins and Evans, a normative theory of expertise. Sheila Jasanoff (2003a, 2003b) and Brian Wynne (2003, 2007) represent the lat- ter strand. They contend that public participation ensures that issues are not framed too narrowly, that institutions behave properly, that expertise is held to cultural standards, and that tacit assumptions are aired and thereby debated.
    [Show full text]