Kai Nielsen Ethics Without Religion

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kai Nielsen Ethics Without Religion When these points are conceded, theologians are in a position KAI NIELSEN to press home a powerful apologetic point. When we become keenly aware, they argue, of the true nature of such ETHICS WITHOUT RELIGION conventionalism and when we become aware that there is no overarching purpose that men were destined to fulfill, the (Ohio University Review 6, 1964, 48-51, 57-62.) myriad purposes, the aims and goals humans create for themselves, will be seen not to be enough. When we realize There certainly are fundamental difficulties and perhaps even that life does not have a meaning—that is, a significance— elements of incoherence in Christian ethics, but what can a which is there to be found, but that we human beings must by secular moralist offer in its stead? Religious morality—and our deliberate decisions give it whatever meaning it has, we Christian morality in particular—may have its difficulties, but will (as Sartre so well understood) undergo estrangement and secular morality, religious apologists argue, has still greater despair. We will drain our cup to its last bitter drop and feel our difficulties. It leads they claim, to ethical scepticism, nihilism, alienation to the full. Perhaps there are human purposes, or, at best, to a pure conventionalism. Such apologists could purposes to be found in life, and we can and do have them even point out that if we look at morality with the cold eye of an in a Godless world, but without God there can be no one anthropologist we will—assuming we are clear-headed—find overarching purpose, no one basic scheme of human existence, morality to be nothing more than the often conflicting mores of in virtue of which we could find a meaning for our grubby the various tribes spread around the globe. If we eschew the lives. It is this overall sense of meaning that man so ardently kind of insight that religion can give us, we will have no strives for, but it is not to be found in a purely secular Archimedean point in accordance with which we can decide worldview. You secularists, a new Pascal might argue, must how it is that we ought to live and die. If we look at ethics from realize, if you really want to be clear-headed, that no purely such a purely secular point of view, we will discover that it is human purposes are ultimately worth striving for. What you constituted by tribal conventions, conventions which we are humanists can give us by way of a scheme of human existence free to reject if we are sufficiently free from ethnocentrism. We will always be a poor second-best and not what the human can continue to act in accordance with them or we can reject heart most ardently longs for. them and adopt a different set of conventions; but whether we The considerations for and against an ethics not rooted in a act in accordance with the old conventions or forge “new religion are complex and involuted; a fruitful discussion of tablets,” we are still acting in accordance with certain them is difficult, for in considering the matter our passions, our conventions. Relative to them certain acts are right or wrong, anxieties, our (if you will) ultimate concerns are involved, and reasonable or unreasonable, but we cannot justify these they tend to blur our vision, enfeeble our understanding, of fundamental moral conventions themselves or the ways of life what exactly is at stake. But we must not forget that what is at which they partially codify. stake here is just what kind of ultimate commitments or obligations a man could have without evading any issue, 1 without self-deception or without delusion. I shall be concerned it for the great majority of our words. Yet there is no greater to display and assess, to make plain but also to weigh, some of loss here. Modern philosophical analysis has taught us that the most crucial considerations for and against a purely secular such an essentially Platonic conception of definition is ethic. While I shall in an objective fashion try to make clear unrealistic and unnecessary.1 I may not be able to define what the central issues are, I shall also give voice to my “chair” in the way that I can define “bachelor,” but I reflective convictions on this matter. I shall try to make evident understand the meaning of “chair” perfectly well. In normal my reasons for believing that we do not need God or any circumstances, at least, I know what to sit on when someone religious conception to support our moral convictions. I shall tells me to take a chair. I may not be able to define “pain,” but I do this, as I think one should in philosophy, by making know what it is like to be in pain, and sometimes I can know apparent the dialectic of the problem (by bringing to the fore when others are in pain. Similarly, though I cannot define the conflicting and evolving considerations for and against) and “happiness” in the same way that I can define “bachelor,” I by arguing for what I take to be their proper resolution. know what it is like to be happy, and I sometimes can judge I am aware that Crisis Theologians would claim that I with considerable reliability whether others are happy or sad, am being naive, but I do not see why purposes of purely human “Happiness” is a slippery word, but it is not so slippery that we devising are not ultimately worth striving for. There is much are justified in saying that nobody knows what happiness is. that we humans prize and would continue to prize even in a A man could be said to have lived a happy life if he had Godless world. Many things would remain to give our lives found lasting sources of satisfaction in his life and if he had meaning and point even after “the death of God.” been able to find certain goals worthwhile and to achieve at Take a simple example. All of us want to be happy. least some of them. He could indeed have suffered some pain But in certain bitter or sceptical moods we question what and anxiety, but his life must, for the most part, have been free happiness is or we despairingly ask ourselves whether anyone from pain, estrangement, and despair, and must, on balance, can really be happy. Is this, however, a sober, sane view of the have been a life which he has liked and found worthwhile. But situation? I do not think that it is, indeed we cannot adequately surely we have no good grounds for saying that no one define “happiness” in the way that we can “bachelor,” but achieves such a balance or that no one is ever happy even for a neither can we in that way define “chair,” “wind,” “pain,” and time. We all have some idea of what would make us happy and the vast majority of words in everyday discourse. For words of what would make us unhappy; many people, at least, can like “bachelor,” “triangle,” or “father” we can specify a remain happy even after “the death of God.” At any rate, we consistent set of properties that all the things and only the need not strike Pascalian attitudes, for even in a purely secular things denoted by these words have, but we cannot do this for world there are permanent sources of human happiness for “happiness,” “chair,” “pain,” and the like. In fact, we cannot do anyone to avail himself of. 1 This is convincingly argued in Michael Scriven’s essay “Definitions, Maxwell, eds., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, III Explanations, and Theories,” in Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven and Grover (Minneapolis, 1958), pp. 99-195. 2 What are they? What are these relatively permanent without God. And poetry, music, and art retain their beauty and sources of human happiness that we all want or need? What is enrich our lives even in the complete absence of God or the it which, if we have it, will give us the basis for a life that could gods. properly be said to be happy? We all desire to be free from pain We want and need art, music, and the dance. We find and want. Even masochists do not seek pain for its own sake; pleasure in travel and conversation and in a rich variety of they endure pain because this is the only psychologically experiences. The sources of human enjoyment are obviously acceptable way of achieving something else (usually sexual too numerous to detail. But all of them are achievable in a satisfaction) that is so gratifying to them that they will put up Godless universe. If some can be ours, we can attain a with the pain to achieve it. We all want a life in which reasonable measure of happiness. Only a Steppenwolfish sometimes we can enjoy ourselves, in which we can attain our personality beguiled by impossible expectations and warped by fair share of some of the simple pleasures that we all desire. irrational guilts and fears can fail to find happiness in the They are not everything in life, but they are important, and our realization of such ends. But to be free of impossible lives would be impoverished without them. expectations people must clearly recognize that there is no “one We also need security and emotional peace. We need big thing” or, for that matter, “small thing” which would make and want a life in which we will not be constantly threatened them permanently happy; almost anything permanently and with physical or emotional harassment.
Recommended publications
  • The Establishment Clause, Secondary Religious Effects, and Humanistic Education
    The Establishment Clause, Secondary Religious Effects, and Humanistic Education The Supreme Court decisions proscribing prayer' and Bible reading2 in public schools provoked considerable public debate. That debate has con- tinued,3 fueled in part by fear that the removal of those religious practices from public schools would hinder the moral development of school chil- dren.4 A number of different, avowedly nonreligious, moral education pro- grams5 that purport to encourage and channel the moral development of the individual child have emerged in the wake of the prayer and Bible- reading decisions.6 Although diverse in method, all of these programs, un- like more traditional forms of moral training,7 reflect the influence of an educational philosophy known as Humanistic Education. The Humanistic Education movement, originally concerned primarily with counteracting the dehumanizing character of technocratic modern ed- ucation,' has evolved into a comprehensive social and moral philosophy' 1. Engel v. Vitale, 370 U.S. 421 (1962). 2. Abington School Dist. v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203 (1963). 3. See N.Y. Times, Apr. 20, 1980, § 12, at 3, col. 1 (many groups still fighting to put prayer back in public schools; between 10% and 30% of public schools still refuse to comply with prayer decisions). 4. See, e.g., N.Y. Times, Jan. 24, 1980, § 2, at 10, col. 5 (some proponents of prayer believe that "crime, vandalism, and drugs are all results of ruling prayer from the schools"); cf D. BOLES, THE BIBLE, RELIGION, AND THE PUBLIC SCHOOLS 245-48 (1961) (proponents of Bible reading believe that its absence from public schools will lead to decline in moral standards).
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond the Principles of Bioethics: Facing the Consequences of Fundamental Moral Disagreement
    DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1677-2954.2012v11n1p13 BEYOND THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOETHICS: FACING THE CONSEQUENCES OF FUNDAMENTAL MORAL DISAGREEMENT H. TRISTRAM ENGELHARDT (Rice Universtiy / USA) ABSTRACT Given intractable secular moral pluralism, the force and significance of the four principles (autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice) of Tom Beauchamp and James Childress must be critically re-considered. This essay examines the history of the articulation of these four principles of bioethics, showing why initially there was an illusion of a common morality that led many to hold that the principles could give guidance across cultures. But there is no one sense of the content or the theoretical justification of these principles. In addition, a wide range of secular moral and bioethical choices has been demoralized into lifestyle choices; the force of the secular moral point of view has also been deflated, thus compounding moral pluralism. It is the political generation of the principles that provides a common morality in the sense of an established morality. The principles are best understood as embedded not in a common morality, sensu stricto, but in that morality that is established at law and public policy in a particular polity. Although moral pluralism is substantive and intractable at the level of moral content, in a particular polity a particular morality and a particular bioethics can be established, regarding which health care ethics consultants can be experts. Public morality and bioethics are at their roots a political reality. Keywords: Bioethics. Pluralism. Moral disagreement. Ethical particularism. RESUMO Dado o pluralismo moral secular intratável, a força e o significado dos quatro princípios (autonomia, beneficência, não maleficência e justiça) de Tom Beauchamp e James Childress precisam ser reconsiderados criticamente.
    [Show full text]
  • Saharan Africa: the Igbo Paradigm
    Journal of International Education and Leadership Volume 5 Issue 1 Spring 2015 http://www.jielusa.org/ ISSN: 2161-7252 The Re-Birth of African Moral Traditions as Key to the Development of Sub- Saharan Africa: The Igbo Paradigm Chika J. B. Gabriel Okpalike Nnamdi Azikiwe University This work is set against the backdrop of the Sub-Saharan African environment observed to be morally degenerative. It judges that the level of decadence in the continent that could even amount to depravity could be blamed upon the disconnect between the present-day African and a moral tradition that has been swept under the carpet through history; this tradition being grounded upon a world view. World-view lies at the basis of the interpretation and operation of the world. It is the foundation of culture, religion, philosophy, morality and so forth; an attempt of humans to impose an order in which the human society works.1 Most times when the African world-view is discussed, the Africa often thought of and represented is the Africa as before in which it is very likely to see religion and community feature as two basic characters of Africa from which morality can be sifted. In his popular work Things Fall Apart, Chinua Achebe had above all things shown that this old Africa has been replaced by a new breed and things cannot be the same again. In the first instance, the former African communalism in which the community was the primary beneficiary of individual wealth has been wrestled down by capitalism in which the individual is defined by the extent in which he accumulates surplus value.
    [Show full text]
  • "Good Without God": Happiness and Pleasure Among the Humanists
    Matthew Engelke "Good without God": happiness and pleasure among the humanists Article (Published version) (Refereed) Original citation: Engelke, Matthew (2015) "Good without God": happiness and pleasure among the humanists. HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory, 5 (3). pp. 69-91. ISSN 2049-1115 DOI: 10.14318/hau5.3.005 Reuse of this item is permitted through licensing under the Creative Commons: © 2015 The Author CC BY 4.0 This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/65522/ Available in LSE Research Online: February 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. 2015 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5 (3): 69–91 SPECIAL ISSUE “Good without God” Happiness and pleasure among the humanists Matthew Engelke, London School of Economics and Political Science In this article, I explore conceptions of happiness and pleasure among secular humanists in Britain. Based on fieldwork among members of the British Humanist Association, and its associated local groups, I argue that happiness for the humanists is both the promise and demand of enlightenment, of an appeal to reason over and against what they see as the irrationality of religion. For them, happiness and pleasure are subjective experiences, but they are also indices of philosophical and ethical commitments.
    [Show full text]
  • A VARIETY of MORAL SOURCES in a SECULAR AGE – Damian Barnat –
    Diametros 54 (2017): 161–173 doi: 10.13153/diam.54.2017.1138 A VARIETY OF MORAL SOURCES IN A SECULAR AGE – Damian Barnat – Abstract. The aim of my paper is to assess in a critical way the views presented by Graeme Smith in his book A Short History of Secularism (2008) as well as in his paper Talking to Ourselves: An Inves- tigation into the Christian Ethics Inherent in Secularism (2017). According to Smith, secular Western societies are underpinned by Christian ethics. An example of a moral norm that – in Smith’s opin- ion – derives from medieval Christianity and shapes the moral condition of the members of con- temporary societies, is the concern about the poor. My criticism of Smith’s thesis is based on the distinction between moral norms and the ways of justifying them. Referring to this distinction, my objective is to show that certain norms which appear to be the same cannot be treated as identical due to the significant differences in their justification. Keywords: Charles Taylor, secularism, ethics, religion, modernity, Enlightenment. Introduction The aim of my paper is to assess in a critical way the views presented by Graeme Smith in his book A Short History of Secularism (2008),1 as well as in his paper Talking to Ourselves: An Investigation into the Christian Ethics Inherent in Secu- larism (2017).2 According to Smith, secular Western societies are underpinned by Christian ethics. An example of a moral norm that – in Smith’s opinion – derives from medieval Christianity and shapes the moral condition of the members of con- temporary societies, is the concern about the poor.
    [Show full text]
  • New Atheism and the Scientistic Turn in the Atheism Movement MASSIMO PIGLIUCCI
    bs_bs_banner MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY Midwest Studies In Philosophy, XXXVII (2013) New Atheism and the Scientistic Turn in the Atheism Movement MASSIMO PIGLIUCCI I The so-called “New Atheism” is a relatively well-defined, very recent, still unfold- ing cultural phenomenon with import for public understanding of both science and philosophy.Arguably, the opening salvo of the New Atheists was The End of Faith by Sam Harris, published in 2004, followed in rapid succession by a number of other titles penned by Harris himself, Richard Dawkins, Daniel Dennett, Victor Stenger, and Christopher Hitchens.1 After this initial burst, which was triggered (according to Harris himself) by the terrorist attacks on September 11, 2001, a number of other authors have been associated with the New Atheism, even though their contributions sometimes were in the form of newspapers and magazine articles or blog posts, perhaps most prominent among them evolutionary biologists and bloggers Jerry Coyne and P.Z. Myers. Still others have published and continue to publish books on atheism, some of which have had reasonable success, probably because of the interest generated by the first wave. This second wave, however, often includes authors that explicitly 1. Sam Harris, The End of Faith: Religion, Terror, and the Future of Reason (New York: W.W. Norton, 2004); Sam Harris, Letter to a Christian Nation (New York: Vintage, 2006); Richard Dawkins, The God Delusion (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2006); Daniel C. Dennett, Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (New York: Viking Press, 2006); Victor J. Stenger, God:The Failed Hypothesis: How Science Shows That God Does Not Exist (Amherst, NY: Prometheus, 2007); Christopher Hitchens, God Is Not Great: How Religion Poisons Everything (New York: Twelve Books, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Man Is Condemned to Be Free by Jean-Paul Sartre from the Lecture, “Existentialism Is a Humanism” (1946) Translated by Philip Mairet (1948)
    Man is Condemned to Be Free by Jean-Paul Sartre from the lecture, “Existentialism is a Humanism” (1946) translated by Philip Mairet (1948) Existence Precedes Essence … we can begin by saying that existentialism, in our sense of the word, is a doctrine that does render human life possible; a doctrine, also, which affirms that every truth and every action imply both an environment and a human subjectivity. … [A]t bottom, what is alarming in the doctrine that I am about to try to explain to you is – is it not? – that it confronts man with a possibility of choice. To verify this, let us review the whole question upon the strictly philosophic level. What, then, is this that we call existentialism? … The question is only complicated because there are two kinds of existentialists. There are, on the one hand, the Christians, amongst whom I shall name Jaspers and Gabriel Marcel, both professed Catholics; and on the other the existential atheists, amongst whom we must place Heidegger as well as the French existentialists and myself. What they have in common is simply the fact that they believe that existence comes before essence – or, if you will, that we must begin from the subjective. What exactly do we mean by that? If one considers an article of manufacture as, for example, a book or a paper- knife – one sees that it has been made by an artisan who had a conception of it; and he has paid attention, equally, to the conception of a paper-knife and to the pre-existent technique of production which is a part of that conception and is, at bottom, a formula.
    [Show full text]
  • Atheism, Agnosticism, and Nonbelief
    ATHEISM, AGNOSTICISM, AND NONBELIEF: A QUALITATIVE AND QUANTITATIVE STUDY OF TYPE AND NARRATIVE By Christopher Frank Silver Ralph W Hood Jr Jim Tucker Professor Professor (Co-Chair) (Co-Chair) Valerie C. Rutledge David Rausch Professor Assistant Professor (Committee Member) (Committee Member) Anthony J. Lease A. Jerald Ainsworth Dean of the College of Health, Education Dean of the Graduate School and Professional Studies ATHEISM, AGNOSTICISM, AND NONBELIEF: A QUALITATIVE AND QUANTITATIVE STUDY OF TYPE AND NARRATIVE By Christopher Frank Silver A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the University of Tennessee at Chattanooga in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Education The University of Tennessee at Chattanooga Chattanooga, Tennessee August 2013 ii Copyright © 2013 By Christopher Frank Silver All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT Extensive research has been conducted in exploration of the American religious landscape, however recently has social science research started to explore Nonbelief in any detail. Research on Nonbelief has been limited as most research focuses on the popularity of the religious “nones” or the complexities of alternative faith expressions such as spirituality. Research has been limited in exploring the complexity of Nonbelief or how non-believers would identify themselves. Most research assumes nonbelievers are a monolithic group with no variation such as Atheism or Agnosticism. Through two studies, one qualitative and one quantitative, this study explored identity of Nonbelief. Study one (the qualitative study) discovered that individuals have shared definitional agreement but use different words to describe the different types of Nonbelief. Moreover, social tension and life narrative play a role in shaping one’s ontological worldview.
    [Show full text]
  • A Two-Dimensional Model of Utilitarian Psychology
    Psychological Review © 2017 American Psychological Association 2017, Vol. 0, No. 999, 000 0033-295X/17/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/rev0000093 Beyond Sacrificial Harm: A Two-Dimensional Model of Utilitarian Psychology Guy Kahane, Jim A. C. Everett, Brian D. Earp, Lucius Caviola, Nadira S. Faber, Molly J. Crockett, and Julian Savulescu University of Oxford Recent research has relied on trolley-type sacrificial moral dilemmas to study utilitarian versus nonutili- tarian modes of moral decision-making. This research has generated important insights into people’s attitudes toward instrumental harm—that is, the sacrifice of an individual to save a greater number. But this approach also has serious limitations. Most notably, it ignores the positive, altruistic core of utilitarianism, which is characterized by impartial concern for the well-being of everyone, whether near or far. Here, we develop, refine, and validate a new scale—the Oxford Utilitarianism Scale—to dissociate individual differences in the ‘negative’ (permissive attitude toward instrumental harm) and ‘positive’ (impartial concern for the greater good) dimensions of utilitarian thinking as manifested in the general population. We show that these are two independent dimensions of proto-utilitarian tendencies in the lay population, each exhibiting a distinct psychological profile. Empathic concern, identification with the whole of humanity, and concern for future generations were positively associated with impartial beneficence but negatively associated with instrumental harm; and although instrumental harm was associated with subclinical psychopathy, impartial beneficence was associated with higher religiosity. Importantly, although these two dimensions were independent in the lay population, they were closely associated in a sample of moral philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Does Morality Require Religious Foundations?
    Does Morality Require Religious Foundations? It is often claimed, particularly in polemical debates, that morality makes no sense without a religious foundation. In this short piece, I will set out an argument on the other side. The issues which I will be discussing have been considered with great erudition by many scholars. Here, I can only write much more briefly. These space limitations will, however, have two consequences. First, I will have to be rather cruder and may come over as more polemical than I would if more space were available, and I will often state my views without stopping to note that and why many distinguished scholars would disagree. Second, I cannot here address many important issues which readers will spot really require an answer. (Here, as with all my work, I’d welcome criticisms, objections and requests for clarification.) 1. Introduction: the very idea of religion as the basis of morality Are there dangers in a purely pragmatic and unreflective approach to issues of politics and public policy, which does not step back also to consider deeper moral questions? Second, if we say yes to this first question – as I would wish to – does morality stand in need of religious foundations? Here I will argue that it doesn’t. Let me start by being somewhat provocative. For I want to suggest that religion1 as such does not help at all with issues to do with morality (although religious traditions obviously incorporate many important moral ideas, and religious people display considerable self-sacrifice for moral causes). There are various reasons for this.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 104, Business Ethics, Queens College, Spring 2007
    Philosophy 104, Business Ethics, Queens College, Spring 2007 Russell Marcus, Instructor email: [email protected] website: http://www.thatmarcusfamily.org/philosophy/Business_Ethics/BEHome.htm Lecture Notes, March 2 I. Some final considerations in favor of secular morality over religious morality Nielsen argues that religious morality requires accepting a dogma, that we know God’s will, whereas secular morality is supported by good reasons. There are other reasons that we should study morality without considering religion. 1. Many people act morally without religious motivation. There seems to be no need to consider religion, since atheists can be moral. An objection: we might internalize the real (religious) motivation for our ethical behavior. Consider that we do not fear a traffic accident when we drive. We have learned to follow certain rules. But our basic motivation for driving safely is fear of an accident. Similarly, the existence of ethical atheists may only show that they have internalized the religious lessons. It would be difficult to show that ethical atheists have internalized religion. Still, the existence of ethical atheists does not seem decisive in favor of secular morality. 2. Religious morality embroils us in the intractable problem of selecting a correct religion. There are many religions, and we do not know which one is right. They may conflict. But we do not need to know the answer to be moral. There are problems of revelation and interpretation. Is the Bible God’s word, or an historical account of God’s actions? Our answers to these questions project a prior understanding of morality. 3. Religious morality may make God’s will morally arbitrary.
    [Show full text]
  • The Secular Transformation of Pride and Humility in the Moral Philophy of David Hume
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects The ecS ular Transformation of Pride and Humility in the Moral Philosophy of David Hume Kirstin April Carlson McPherson Marquette University Recommended Citation McPherson, Kirstin April Carlson, "The eS cular Transformation of Pride and Humility in the Moral Philosophy of David Hume" (2016). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 625. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/625 THE SECULAR TRANSFORMATION OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY IN THE MORAL PHILOPHY OF DAVID HUME by Kirstin Carlson McPherson, B.A., M.A. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin May 2016 ABSTRACT: THE SECULAR TRANSFORMATION OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY IN THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF DAVID HUME Kirstin Carlson McPherson, B.A., M.A. Marquette University, 2016 In this dissertation I examine Hume’s secular re-definition and re-evaluation of the traditional Christian understanding of pride and humility as part of his project to establish a fully secular account of ethics and to undermine what he thought to be the harmful aspects of religious morality. Christians traditionally have seen humility, understood as receptivity to God, to be crucial for individual and social flourishing, and pride as the root of individual and social disorder. By contrast, Hume, who conceives of pride and humility immanently in terms of our self-appraisals, sees pride as a key virtue that serves as the ultimate source of moral motivation and deems humility a ‘monkish virtue’ (i.e., a vice). Hume, moreover, sees religious appeals to a transcendent moral source to be a threat to individual flourishing in that they encourage the formation of what he calls ‘artificial lives’ (of which the monkish virtues are an expression) as well as a threat to social concord, insofar as they foster unnecessary religious factions, intolerance, and theologically sanctioned violence.
    [Show full text]