The Religion of Inductivism As a Living Force

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Religion of Inductivism As a Living Force Part II The Religion of Inductivism as a Living Force For the several employments and of fi ces of our fellows, we have 12 that sail into foreign countries … three that collect the experiments which are in all books … three who collect the experiments of all mechanical arts … three that try new experiments … three that draw the experiments … into titles and tables … three that bend themselves, looking into the experiments of their fellows, and cast about how to draw from them things of use … three that … direct new experiments. … three that raise the former discoveries by experiments into greater observations, axioms and aphorisms. … For our ordinance and rites, … we place … the more rare and excellent inventions … we place the statues of all principal inventors … some of brass; some of marble … some of cedar … some of silver; some of gold. We have certain hymns and services … and forms of prayers … (Bacon, The New Atlantis ) The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways. The point, however, is to change it. (Karl Marx, fi nal Thesis on Feuerbach) Epistemology without contact with science becomes an empty scheme. Science without epistemology is — insofar as it is thinkable at all — primitive and muddled. (Albert Einstein, “Reply”, 1949 , 683–4) This second part of this study is devoted to the more-or-less single-handed implemen- tation by Robert Boyle of the vision of amateur observers contributing to the rise of a new science that Bacon had initiated. It is therefore much devoted to the role of ideol- ogy in the rise of inductivism as a social movement and on the differences between the views on scienti fi c method of Bacon and of Boyle, perhaps even between their world- views. For this some attention to some terminological detail is necessary. Let me offer the major ones here with an apology to the reader. Following these let me offer a gen- eral view of the current literature on Boyle and contrast it with my view on him. These will hopefully facilitate the reading of the more detailed story that involves methodol- ogy and social history of science and bits and pieces from quite a few disciplines. 126 Part II The Religion of Inductivism as a Living Force Quasi-Terminological Notes “The Inductive Style” “Style” as referring to manner as opposed to matter, to the way of presenting things, is used here in a wide sense; “scienti fi c style” denotes here the dry and prosaic style typical to modern scienti fi c writings as well as modes of presentation like that of scienti fi c dialogues or of power points. My interest is in the style of scienti fi c papers proper, especially of inductivist ones, as developed in the Age of Reason. The inductive style is of intentional recording of experiences reminiscent of early Renaissance travel narratives: the inductive style is personal yet formal. A paper in the learned press in this style opens with a description of some experimental appa- ratus if its discussion refers to it and proceeds with a description of some experi- ments, perhaps adding some reports of other observations, and then concludes with a description of the result of the experiment and ends abruptly, without a word of comment or explanation as to the relevance of the facts it describes. Alternatively, it was reluctantly permitted to add to such a scienti fi c paper a short vague preamble and a few lines at the end that present a conjecture or some theoretical conclusion. Most important, the inductive style excludes controversy and allows reference to a theory that a paper refutes only in allusion. Nowadays papers that conform to this style or mode of presentation are rare 1 ; it was very popular in the eighteenth cen- tury. The only freedom granted to a writer during the time in which this style was compulsory was to add a few lines in the conclusion. If the paper lacks these addi- tions, then some previous knowledge of its background is necessary for the under- standing of its import. If the paper includes such additions in its conclusion, the proper way to read it is to start at the end, in order to get a hint at what is the con- cern of the paper. 2 The inductive style is an invention — of Bacon and Boyle, instituted in 1661, soon to become traditional. In the mid-nineteenth century, under the in fl uence of Michael Faraday, the historical or dialectic or critical style reappeared. It requires discussions of problem and of criticism of extant solutions to it. Some academics still forbid it as it boosts controversy. It does. Some academics fi nd controversy otiose. In some periodicals the inductive style is compulsory to these days. 3 1 The best-known example of the use of the inductive style in the twentieth century is in the con- cluding words of the fi rst ( 1953 ) path-breaking paper of Francis Crick and James Watson on nucleic acids: “It has not escaped our notice that the speci fi c pairing we have postulated immedi- ately suggests a possible copying mechanism for the genetic material.” For, this sentence alludes to a speculation, and the classical permission is to use these only very sparingly. 2 Let me report that biologist friends of mine habitually and unawares began reading a paper from the end. 3 Popper narrated that he challenged his friend John Eccles to submit to a leading periodical a paper in the critical style. It was returned with the demand to rewrite it. A few editors have returned papers of mine expressing disdain at my licentious attitude to speculations. Part II The Religion of Inductivism as a Living Force 127 “Speculation” and “Hypothesis” Bacon, Boyle and Faraday, used “hypothesis” and “speculation” as synonyms. I use these words as they do when I quote or discuss their views. Otherwise, I prefer to distinguish between them: a hypothesis is empirically testable and a speculation is not. Thus, for example, in my terminology Boyle’s atomism is speculative, while that of Dalton is hypothetical. I use the words “theory” or “conjecture” to designate both hypotheses and speculations. The ways these near-synonyms are used vary and change. This is unproblematic as long as any distinction between them is clear to readers. “Hypothesis” and “Fact” Following the older tradition, I often use the word “fact” to designate statement of fact. The difference between a fact and a statement is of paramount importance in logic and in some philosophical discourses. Not here. Since I discuss here inductiv- ism, I usually use here the word “fact” to designate statement of fact universalized, at times called “general fact” in comments on classical science and “low level gen- eralization” in comments on contemporary methodology. A general fact then is not any observed event but its supposed generalization. There is some subtlety involved here that somehow led to many useless philosophical debates. My advice to the interested in the logical analysis of these subtle matters is to consult Karl Popper’s Logic of scienti fi c Discovery ( 1935 , 1959) §§14, 22, and 30. On the Recent Literature When I wrote my dissertation (over half a century ago) the literature on Robert Boyle was scant. It soon began to grow in earnest; it is already monumental. It includes the tremendously learned surveys by R. E. W. Maddison in series of papers and books, the correspondence of Henry Oldenburg that Alfred Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall have edited (Oldenburg et al. 1969 ) and that of Robert Boyle that Michael Hunter, Antonio Clericuzio and Lawrence M. Principe have edited (Boyle et al. 2001 ) , as well as the collected works of Boyle that Michael Hunter and Edward Davis have edited (Boyle et al. 1999 , 2000), not to mention the many books and many more essays that Michael Hunter and others have published since, that contain much fascinating information. Current literature discusses Boyle’s religious and metaphysical writings that receive much too little attention in the present study. I praise this literature for its integration of his theology in his philosophy, especially its attention to his efforts to harmonize and even unite science and faith. For my purpose suf fi ce it, 128 Part II The Religion of Inductivism as a Living Force however, to note some generalities. Boyle advocated a view that he ascribed to Philo Judeus: research is the worship that be fi ts natural religion. Here he echoed popular sentiment: both Bellarmino and Galileo found it in Psalm 19. 4 To this Boyle added that revelation is inessential for religion: it is the merciful gift from the Lord to sinners, his giving them a second chance. In his Things above Reason he expressed his unwavering rationalism, saying, it is unthinkable that the Good Lord would make unreasonable demands. He also said, belief is not open to manipulation: I cannot control it. He dissented from Descartes, however, ascrib- ing to the soul moral sentiment (the expression is his) in addition to thinking. Natural religion belongs to thinking and revealed religion to the moral sentiment, as the Bible is a text in morality, not in reason. Hence, the expression of good will is in charity and in religious activities; science must be in the hands of (wealthy) amateurs. Hunter is today the leading Boyle scholar. To the little extent that he shows inter- est in the social history of science, he tends to follow Steven Shapin (1994 ) whose philosophy differs greatly from the one offered in this text (Agassi 1997 ) . As to Hunter’s view of Boyle’s methodology, Rose-Mary Sargent says of it adroitly (Sargent 2003 , 52): Without argument … Hunter presents Boyle as having advocated an unproblematic and thoroughgoing empiricism that re fl ected an ‘aversion’ to reason.
Recommended publications
  • 1 Phil. 4400 Notes #1: the Problem of Induction I. Basic Concepts
    Phil. 4400 Notes #1: The problem of induction I. Basic concepts: The problem of induction: • Philosophical problem concerning the justification of induction. • Due to David Hume (1748). Induction: A form of reasoning in which a) the premises say something about a certain group of objects (typically, observed objects) b) the conclusion generalizes from the premises: says the same thing about a wider class of objects, or about further objects of the same kind (typically, the unobserved objects of the same kind). • Examples: All observed ravens so far have been The sun has risen every day for the last 300 black. years. So (probably) all ravens are black. So (probably) the sun will rise tomorrow. Non-demonstrative (non-deductive) reasoning: • Reasoning that is not deductive. • A form of reasoning in which the premises are supposed to render the conclusion more probable (but not to entail the conclusion). Cogent vs. Valid & Confirm vs. Entail : ‘Cogent’ arguments have premises that confirm (render probable) their conclusions. ‘Valid’ arguments have premises that entail their conclusions. The importance of induction: • All scientific knowledge, and almost all knowledge depends on induction. • The problem had a great influence on Popper and other philosophers of science. Inductive skepticism: Philosophical thesis that induction provides no justification for ( no reason to believe) its conclusions. II. An argument for inductive skepticism 1. There are (at most) 3 kinds of knowledge/justified belief: a. Observations b. A priori knowledge c. Conclusions based on induction 2. All inductive reasoning presupposes the “Inductive Principle” (a.k.a. the “uniformity principle”): “The course of nature is uniform”, “The future will resemble the past”, “Unobserved objects will probably be similar to observed objects” 3.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI230 Philosophy of Science
    Department of Philosophy Level 2 Module PHI230 Philosophy of Science LECTURER: George Botterill Office Hours Wed 12-1, Fri 1-2; external tel: (0114)2220580; email: [email protected] Lectures: Monday 2-3 in Hicks Building LT6 Friday 11-12 in Hicks Building LT5 Seminars: See MOLE unit to join: Monday 4-5 Jessop Building 215, Friday 12-1 Jessop Building 215 GENERAL OUTLINE This course will deal with major issues in the philosophy of science, with particular emphasis on the rationality of theory-change, explanation, the status of scientific laws, observation, and the structure of scientific theories. Most of the course will be devoted to the methodology of natural science, though we may also discuss some issues in the philosophy of the social sciences. Most of the issues presented revolve around two major debates in the philosophy of science: (1) the dispute between Kuhn and Popper about theory change (2) disagreements between positivist (or instrumentalist) and realist conceptions of science. Modern philosophy of science has become closely linked with the history of science. The course will reflect this by considering how well major developments in the history of science fit proposed methodological rules about how science ought to proceed. The Copernican Revolution in astronomy will be used as a case-study. 1 AIMS AND OBJECTIVES The main aims of this module are: • to introduce students to the debate about theory-change in science, deriving from the work of Popper, Kuhn, Feyerabend and Lakatos • to help students acquire an understanding of some important problems in the philosophy of science (concerning the topics of: explanation, observation, scientific realism, and the nature of laws) • to encourage students to enter into serious engagement with some of the major problems in the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Induction, Deduction, and the Scientific Method
    INDUCTION, DEDUCTION, AND THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF THE PRACTICE OF SCIENCE IRVING ROTHCHILD Emeritus Professor of Reproductive Biology Case Western Reserve University School of Medicine Cleveland, Ohio © 2006 by the Society for the Study of Reproduction, Inc. CONTENTS ABSTRACT 1 INTRODUCTION 1 INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 2 Etymology 2 Definitions 2 Induction 2 Deduction 3 THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD 3 BEING A SCIENTIST 4 Making Observations 4 Point of View 5 Asking the Right Question 6 Theorizing 6 The theory (or finding) that questions authority 7 Defending the controversial theory or finding 8 Eurekas 8 Experimentation 9 The failed experiment 9 Publishing 10 Statistics 10 Recognition 10 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS 10 REFERENCES 11 © 2006 by the Society for the Study of Reproduction, Inc. © 2006 by the Society for the Study of Reproduction, Inc. INDUCTION, DEDUCTION, AND THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF THE PRACTICE OF SCIENCE IRVING ROTHCHILD* Emeritus Professor of Reproductive Biology Case Western Reserve University School of Medicine Cleveland, Ohio ABSTRACT: Science is a never-ending, always changing process through which we learn to know the material nature of the universe. Science does not deal with nonmaterial entities such as gods, for there is no way their existence can be either proved or disproved. No single, identifiable method applies to all branches of science; the only method, in fact, is whatever the scientist can use to find the solution to a problem. This includes induction, a form of logic that identifies similarities within a group of particulars, and deduction, a form of logic that identifies a particular by its resemblance to a set of accepted facts.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation. James Wayne Lemke Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1978 Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation. James Wayne Lemke Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Lemke, James Wayne, "Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation." (1978). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 3249. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/3249 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 79031*4 LEMKE» JAMES WAYNE POLITICAL THEORY AND THE PROBLEM OF EXPLANATION. THE LOUISIANA STATE UNIVERSITY AND AGRICULTURAL AND MECHANICAL COL., P H .D ., 1978 University Microfilms International 3o o n , z e e s r o a d , a n n a r b o r , m i 4eioe 0 1978 JAMES WAYNE LEMKE ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by James Wayne Lerrike B.A., Southeastern Louisiana University, 1969 August, 1978 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The writing of this dissertation, to say nothing of its completion, has been an enjoyable and rewarding enterprise. My good feelings about this experience are in large measure the result of the support and assistance of a number of people.
    [Show full text]
  • Science Without Inductivism ( Karl Popper’S View )
    Science without inductivism ( Karl Popper’s view ) Ningombam Bupenda Meitei (St.Stephen’s College), Department of Philosophy, University of Delhi Abstract The paper aims to expound on the issue of science being different from non science or pre- science in the form of the scientific methodology used. Popper’s method of falsifiability ensures the aim of science to be successful. The aim of science which also needs a critical attitude, can enable scientific progress by rejecting inductivism as its scientific methodology. Popper’s view on what the aim of science is and why and how inductivism fails in the case of science, along with examples from history of science besides its impact on philosophical foundations of science, has been stressed in the paper. Introduction Science and its significance grew rapidly due to Einstein’s theory of relativity and its difference from the nature of the works of Freud and Adler which made Popper to expound on the notion of allegedly scientific psychoanalysis of Freud and the revolutionary work on relativity of Einstein which was also experimentally proved by Eddington in 1919 showing the deflection of light by solid massive gravitational bodies. The debate of what science is and what non science could be, the notion of what science should do or can do or precisely ,the aim of science have made the 20th century a breeding moment of thoughts for philosophical foundations of science ,thereby influencing the development of philosophy of science. Popper who is also influenced by Hume’s skepticism on inductivism has made his notion of being scientific very strong in terms of being falsifiability through repeated tests.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Styles of Thought in Science: Examples Applied to the History Of
    ;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;;; and give theories of vera causa wide berth, for good Some Styles of reason. They are leery of any attempt to extrapolate causes from observations, conÞning themselves to Thought in Science: laws and the extraordinarily rare causal theory. The 1859 publication of DarwinÕs On the Origin Examples Applied of the Species is a watershed event, in the neutrally geographic sense of that wordÑrecognized regardless to the History of of how you feel about it. Subsequently, scientists established functionalism, based on the adaptation Evolution of critters to their niches via natural selection, as the dominant paradigm in evolutionary biology for virtually all of the 20th century and still going strong by Erik Rau into the 21st. Functionalism explains diversity among species of critters through adaptation to either the In the vastly cluttered secondhand shop of tasks those critters perform or the environment philosophical ideas, there is a large but somewhat they live in or both. Though he wasnÕt the Þrst to empty cardboard box labeled ÔSCIENCE.Õ A few terms do so, Darwin clearly propounded the supremacy rattle around inside, some of which look very similar of adaptation over conservation of structure in to each other. When these terms are unpacked and natural selection: ÔHence every detail of structure in tried out on a few actual theories, however, we begin every living creature (making some little allowance to see how they might work. What follows is a short for the direct action of physical conditions) may discussion of some often-used but little-identiÞed be viewed, either as having been of special use to epistemological terms in the philosophy of science, some ancestral form, or as being now of special use and their roles illustrated through part of the history to the descendants of that form,Õ (Darwin 200) and of evolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Central Issues in Popper's Theory of Science
    FOUR CENTRAL ISSUES IN POPPER’S THEORY OF SCIENCE By CARLOS E. GARCIA-DUQUE A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA 2002 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would not have been able to finish this project without the help and support of many persons and institutions. To begin with, 1 wish to express my deepest gratitude to Dr. Chuang Liu, chair of my doctoral committee for his continuous support and enthusiastic encouragement since the time when this dissertation was nothing more than a inchoate idea. 1 enjoyed our long discussions and benefited greatly from his advice and insightful suggestions. 1 am also very grateful to the other members of my committee, who all made significant contributions to the final product. 1 wish to thank Dr. Kirk Ludwig with whom 1 have had extensive discussions about several specific problems that 1 addressed in my dissertation. His valuable suggestions made my arguments more compelling and helped me to improve substantially Chapter 5. Dr. Robert D’Amico has posed deep questions that led me to refine and better structure my views. My conversa- tions with Dr. Robert A. Hatch about specific episodes in the history of science and their relationship with my topic were inspirational and prompted me to develop new ideas. I completed my doctoral studies with the endorsement of the Fulbright Program and the support of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Florida. 1 also want to thank the Universidad de Caldas and the Universidad de Manizales for granting me a leave of absence long enough to successfully finish this academic program.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Science, Experimental Science, and the Scientific Method
    Historical science, experimental science, and the scientific method Carol E. Cleland Department of Philosophy and Center for Astrobiology, University of Colorado, Boulder, Colorado 80309, USA ABSTRACT Many scientists believe that there is a uniform, interdisciplinary method for the prac- tice of good science. The paradigmatic examples, however, are drawn from classical ex- perimental science. Insofar as historical hypotheses cannot be tested in controlled labo- ratory settings, historical research is sometimes said to be inferior to experimental research. Using examples from diverse historical disciplines, this paper demonstrates that such claims are misguided. First, the reputed superiority of experimental research is based upon accounts of scientific methodology (Baconian inductivism or falsificationism) that are deeply flawed, both logically and as accounts of the actual practices of scientists. Second, although there are fundamental differences in methodology between experimental scien- tists and historical scientists, they are keyed to a pervasive feature of nature, a time asymmetry of causation. As a consequence, the claim that historical science is methodo- logically inferior to experimental science cannot be sustained. Keywords: methodology, induction, history, experimental investigations. INTRODUCTION This paper explains why historical science is not inferior to ex- Experimental methods are commonly held up as the paradigm for perimental science when it comes to testing hypotheses. First, objec- testing hypotheses: the scientific method, widely disseminated in intro- tions such as Gee’s are based upon common misconceptions about ductory science texts, is modeled upon them. But not all scientific experimental practice and scientific methodology in general. Second, hypotheses can be tested in the laboratory. Historical hypotheses that the differences in methodology that actually do exist between historical postulate particular past causes for currently observable phenomena and experimental science are founded upon a remarkably pervasive provide good examples.
    [Show full text]
  • Histological Positivism? an Approach to Claude Bernard's Epistemology
    WHO KILLED HISTOLOGICAL POSITIVISM? AN APPROACH TO CLAUDE BERNARD’S EPISTEMOLOGY JOSÉ LUIS GONZÁLEZ RECIO ABSTRACT. Along with numerous scientific contributions, Claude Bernard left a lucid and detailed defense of the applicability of the experimental method in physiology. Bernard explained that a rational therapeutic was absolutely nec- essary in clinical work, that this brought a pathology based on critical analysis of empirical data, and that such pathology would reach genuine knowledge when physiology had been freed from dogmatic attitudes. He set up a pro- gram, attacked by currents of thought hostile to the suppositions involved. The confrontation usher two tasks: first, to dismask the weakness of such currents; then, to define the role of conceptual-free invention and, likewise, how the methodological and epistemological guarantees of future physiology should act. This article examines such complex task; it enlarges on the reasons which have led Bernard to be seen as a precursor of Popper’s philosophy of science, and it pays special attention to the common factors in the historical context in which both Bernard and Popper developed their thoughts. KEY WORDS. C. Bernard, experimental physiology, hypotheses, Positivism, Vitalism, cellular theory, Empiricism, histology, Rationalism, K. Popper. INTRODUCTION I shall begin with a simple game. I will give the reader four short quotes and he or she must ask him or herself which might come from texts written by Claude Bernard and which from works by Karl Popper. The quotes are these: 1st. “Without a hypothesis, in other words, without an anticipation of the facts, there is no science 1.” 2nd. “Theories are no more than provisional ideas which we have about things in a particular state of our knowledge..
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science
    Chapter 10 Philosophy of Science (Alexander Bird, University of Edinburgh) Introduction The central concerns of the philosophy of science as a whole divide into two areas. One of these areas, perhaps the traditionally more dominant side, encompasses such questions as: Is scientific knowledge possible? If so, how? What methods of reasoning do scientists use? What is the role of observation and experiment in scientific reasoning? Are theories justified that concern entities and processes that cannot be observed? This area is where philosophy of science overlaps with epistemology, the theory of knowledge. The second area is situated where philosophy of science overlaps with metaphysics. Here we are concerned not with whether and why our theories amount to knowledge, but instead we focus on what our theories are about—in the most general terms. For example, the world contains laws of nature and is divided up into different kinds of things. Almost all scientific theories concern one or other of these two general features of the world—or at least their subject matter will reflect these features. Associated with features is the fact that most theories attempt to explain some phenomenon or other. These are metaphysical topics. In this chapter we shall look first at the second area, metaphysical philosophy of science, before returning to the first, epistemological philosophy of science. The metaphysics of science I mentioned three key components in the metaphysical part of the philosophy of science: laws of nature, natural kinds, and explanation. We can see these all operating together in John Dalton’s atomic hypothesis. The starting point is the obvious fact that chemists deal with different substances.
    [Show full text]
  • AFRREV STECH, Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013
    AFRREV STECH, Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013 AFRREV STECH An International Journal of Science and Technology Bahir Dar, Ethiopia Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013:94-112 ISSN 2225-8612 (Print) ISSN 2227-5444 (Online) Inductivism and Science: An Appraisal of Scientific Methodology Obi, Chidiebere Cyriacus Department of Philosophy, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka Anambra State, Nigeria E-mail: [email protected] Phone Number: +2348034946931 Abstract Inductivism is the claim that induction is the basis of proper scientific inquiry. Induction holds that we can infer that what we know to be true in a particular case or cases will be true in all cases, which resemble the former in certain assignable respects. Sequel to this, proponents of inductivism such as John Stuart Mill, Francis Bacon etc rejected every rationalistic or idealistic approach to scientific knowledge; instead, they suggested experience as the basis for any knowledge that is worthwhile. The history of philosophy has been characterized by arguments and counter arguments on what should constitute the nature of scientific methodology and this has led to absolutism in science that is, the belief that scientists must adhere to some stipulated method (s). This work employs critical method, functional analysis and hermeneutical method to appraise the above stated claim by first of all establishing the roles played by the human reason and a priori ideas in the scientific enterprise. After this, we will also examine issues surrounding the Copyright © IAARR 2012: www.afrrevjo.net/stech 94 Indexed African Researches Reviews online: www.arronet.info AFRREV STECH, Vol. 2 (1) January, 2013 methodology of science as raised by philosophers of science like Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, and Feyerabend etc.
    [Show full text]
  • MEC-109 Research Methods in Economics Indira Gandhi National Open University School of Social Sciences
    MEC-109 Research Methods in Economics Indira Gandhi National Open University School of Social Sciences Block 1 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY: ISSUES AND PERSPECTIVES UNIT 1 Research Methodology: Conceptual Foundation 7 UNIT 2 Approaches to Scientific Knowledge: Positivism and Post Positivism 21 UNIT 3 Models of Scientific Explanation 43 UNIT 4 Debates on Models of Explanation in Economics 57 UNIT 5 Foundations of Qualitative Research: Interpretativism and Critical Theory Paradigm 72 Expert Committee Prof. D.N. Reddy Prof. Romar Korea Rtd. Professor of Economics Professor of Economics University of Hyderabad, Hyderabad University of Mumbai Mumbai Prof. Harishankar Asthana Professor of Psychology Dr. Manish Gupta Banaras Hindu University, Varanasi Sr. Economist National Institute of Public Prof. Chandan Mukherjee Finance and Policy Professor and Dean New Delhi School of Development Studies Ambedkar University, New Delhi Prof. Anjila Gupta Professor of Economics Prof. V.R. Panchmukhi IGNOU, New Delhi Rtd. Professor of Economics Bombay University and Former Prof. Narayan Prasad (Convenor) Chairman ICSSR, New Delhi Professor of Economics IGNOU, New Delhi Prof. Achal Kumar Gaur Professor of Economics Prof. K. Barik Faculty of Social Sciences Professor of Economics Banaras Hindu University, Varanasi IGNOU, New Delhi Prof. P.K. Chaubey Dr. B.S. Prakash Professor, Indian Institute of Public Associate Professor in Economics Administration, New Delhi IGNOU, New Delhi Shri S.S. Suryanarayana Shri Saugato Sen Rtd. Joint Advisor Associate Professor in Economics Planning Commission, New Delhi IGNOU, New Delhi Course Coordinator: Prof. Narayan Prasad Block Preparation Team Units Resource Person IGNOU Faculty (Format, Language and Conent editing) 1 Prof. Narayan Prasad Professor of Economics Prof.
    [Show full text]