Downloaded from Brill.Com10/01/2021 09:01:16AM Via Free Access C.-P

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Downloaded from Brill.Com10/01/2021 09:01:16AM Via Free Access C.-P The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 7 (2013) 156-179 brill.com/jpt Possessed and Inspired: Hermias on Divine Madness* Christina-Panagiota Manolea Hellenic Open University [email protected] Abstract Hermias of Alexandria (5th cent. A.D.) wrote down the lectures given on the Phaedrus by his teacher Syrianus, Head of the Neoplatonic School of Athens. In the preserved text the Platonic distinction of madness is presented in a Neopla- tonic way. In the first section of the article we discuss Hermias’ treatment of possession. The philosopher examines four topics in his effort to present a Neo- platonic doctrine concerning possession. As he holds that divine possession is evident in all parts of the soul, he first argues that it is primarily applied to the one-in-the-soul. Secondly, he explains that possession is also applied to reason, opinion, imagination, thymos and desire, all the above being distinctive parts of the human soul, but not as important as the one-in-the-soul. The third issue he discusses is whether all causes of possession are identical to the divine. Then, Hermias examines the fact that possession is to be traced not only in the human soul but also in the statues. In the second section of the article Hermias’ analysis of the four kinds of Pla- tonic madness is presented. The philosopher first analyzes the interdependence between all four divine kinds of madness and then describes their function on two levels, inside and outside the soul. The function within the soul is richer and is realized in four fields: (a) the restoration of the soul after its fall, (b) the resto- ration of the human being as a whole, (c) the Pythagorean mathematical system and (d) the logic processes. The function outside the soul deals with the manifes- tations of the soul in human society. Under this perspective, Hermias clearly *) Earlier versions of the two main parts of this article were presented as papers at the 2011 Classical Association Conference (Durham, UK, April 2011) and the 9th Annual Conference of the International Society for Neoplatonic Studies (Atlanta, USA, June 2011) respectively. I would like to thank the participants of both conferences for their remarks, and especially Prof. Suzanne Stern-Gillet for her constant help and encouragement. © 2013 Christina-Panagiota Manolea DOI: 10.1163/18725473-12341261 This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported (CC BY-NC 3.0) License, http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/ Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 09:01:16AM via free access C.-P. Manolea / The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 7 (2013) 156-179 157 proposes an original classification of the kinds of madness, on the basis of which we encounter poetic madness. After that follow the madness of the seer, the teles- tic madness, and the madness of love. The whole analysis incorporates Platonic, Aristotelian, Pythagorean and theurgic elements that cover the fields of psychol- ogy, logic and metaphysics. Keywords Platonism, Neoplatonism, School of Athens, Hermias, Syrianus, Plato, Phaedrus, metaphysics, theurgy, literary criticism, reception Introduction Μadness is a theme touched by Plato in many dialogues (Ion, Philebus, Meno, Phaedrus, Res Publica, Timaeus) and is discussed in many ways, favorable or not.1 Nevertheless, the best known Platonic distinction is found at Phaedrus 265a-c: there are two types of madness, the one attrib- uted to human disease and the one stemming from the gods (divine mad- ness). The latter is further divided as follows: the madness of the seer caused by Apollo, telestic madness caused by Dionysus, poetic madness sent by the Muses and finally erotic madness attributed to Aphrodite and Eros.2 In this paper we will deal with divine madness, as analyzed by Hermias of Alexandria (5th century A.D.). Hermias was a student of Syrianus, Head of the Neoplatonic School of Athens. After he finished his studies, during which he is said to have been very diligent, he returned to Alexandria, along with his wife Aedesia, who was Syrianus’ niece. His death was premature, but this is not the only reason why his commentary on the Phaedrus is the only work of his that is known to us. In fact, the commentary is in 1) For instance, in books II, IV, VII and IX of the Res Publica madness is considered to be a disease, either of a milder or a more serious sort. On the contrary, in the Ion 533-534 it is faced rather favorably and is connected to the issue of inspiration. For further details on the Ion discussion see P. Murray, Plato on poetry. Ion, Republic 376e-398b, Republic 595-698b. Cambridge Greek and Latin Classics, Cambridge 1996, comm. ad loc. 2) Plato, Phaedrus 265a ff.: Μανίας δέ γε εἴδη δύο, τὴν μὲν ὑπὸ νοσημάτων ἀνθρωπίνων, τὴν δὲ ὑπὸ θείας ἐξαλλαγῆς τῶν εἰωθότων νομίμων γιγνομένην. (. .) Τῆς δὲ θείας τεττάρων θεῶν τέτ- ταρα μέρη διελόμενοι, μαντικὴν μὲν ἐπίπνοιαν Ἀπόλλωνος θέντες, Διονύσου δὲ τελεστικήν, Μουσῶν δ’ αὖ ποιητικήν, τετάρτην δὲ Ἀφροδίτης καὶ Ἔρωτος, ἐρωτικὴν μανίαν ἐφήσαμέν τε ἀρίστην εἶναι (. .). Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 09:01:16AM via free access 158 C.-P. Manolea / The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 7 (2013) 156-179 all probability a more or less faithful reproduction of Syrianus’ teaching, although the manuscript tradition attributes it to Hermias.3 The paper will be divided in two sections. In the first we will examine Hermias’ dis- cussion of possession while in the second we will proceed to a detailed analysis of the four Platonic types of divine madness. Possession Hermias deals with the four Platonic types of madness that are attributed to the gods at Phaedrus 265b. As any good reader of Plato would have done, Hermias starts his analysis by wondering whether madness is good or bad. After concluding that madness is the cause and mother of every- thing that is good (αἰτία καὶ μήτηρ ὅλων τῶν ἀγαθῶν) the philosopher pro- ceeds to a clearly Neoplatonic analysis of the function of the four Platonic types of madness. But before providing his students with this analysis, he gives a detailed description of divine possession (ἐνθουσιασμός). We 3) Undoubtedly the Phaedrus was included in the syllabus of the School of Athens. The thing is whether and to which extent the text that has come down to us is just a writing down of Syrianus’ lessons or has been reworked by Hermias. In our opinion, the com- mentary that we now have is either a text bearing no intervention by Hermias at all or a text that has been slightly reworked, in a way that it should be considered as preserv- ing a very accurate picture of Syrianus’ views and philosophical ideas. K. Praechter (“Her- meias” in Pauly-Wissova, Real-Encyclopädie d. class. Alterumswissenschaft 8.1, 1912, cols. 732-735) was the first to maintain in a rather convincing way that Hermias’ work should be read a source of Syrianus’ teaching and ideas. An opposite view has been expressed by P.A. Bielmeier (“Die Neuplatonische Phaedrusinterpretation”, Rhetorische Studien, 16, 1930, 4-96). C. Moreschini has also tried to give Hermias originality as a thinker in two articles: “Alcuni aspetti degli Scholia in Phaedrum di Ermia Alessandrino in M.O. Goulet-Gazé, G. Madec, D. O’ Brien (eds.) ΣΟΦΙΗΣ ΜΑΙΗΤΟΡΕΣ—“Chercheurs de sagesse”, Hommage à Jean Pépin, Paris 1992, 451-460 and “Alla scuola di Siriano: Ermia nella storia del neopla- tonismo”, in A. Longo (ed.), Syrianus et la metaphysiqe de l’ antiquité tardive. Actes du Colloque International, Université de Genève 29 Septembre-1er Octobre 2006, Napoli 2009, 516-522. H. Bernard (Hermeias von Alexandrien. Kommentar zu Platons Phaidros, Philoso- phische Untersuchungen, 1, 1997, Tübingen) has also followed the same line. For a discus- sion of the arguments of both sides that actually reaches the conclusion that Hemias text is a reliable source of Syrianus’ teachings and ideas see C.-P Manolea, The Homeric tradi- tion in Syrianus, Thessaloniki 2004, 47-50 and 52-58 and C.-P. Manolea, “The treatment of ancient Greek myth in Syrianus’ philosophical works”, in A. Longo (ed.) (2009), 500-501. Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 09:01:16AM via free access C.-P. Manolea / The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 7 (2013) 156-179 159 will stick to this fact, since Hermias treats madness (μανία) as a manifesta- tion of possession. In other words, according to Hermias madness depends exclusively to the susceptibility of the human soul to be possessed by the divine. The texts we are going to discuss in this section have been dealt with by modern scholars only once—it was actually O. Ballériaux who focused on the function and the importance of telestic madness.4 Nevertheless, many of the passages he analyzed are about possession in general, although the author in the conclusion treats them as referring to telestic madness. Moreover, Ballériaux made little reference to the hierarchy the philoso- pher accepts as far as the four Platonic kinds of madness are concerned. We will try to show Hermias’ attitude towards possession in general and not only telestic madness. At 88.15-215 the philosopher examines four topics in his effort to present a distinctive Neoplatonic doctrine concerning possession: which part of the soul is possessed, whether all parts of the soul are possessed, whether all sorts of possession derive from the divine and if there are other entities superior to the soul that are possessed. 1) The discussion of the first issue, i.e. which part of the soul is pos- sessed (ποῖον μόριον ἐστι τῆς ψυχῆς τὸ ἐνθουσιῶν) is elaborated at 88.21-89.14.6 4) O.
Recommended publications
  • Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2014 Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2014). Rhetoric and Platonism in fifth-century Athens. In R. C. Fowler (Ed.), Plato in the third sophistic (pp. 57-72). De Gruyter. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori (Trinity University) Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens There are reasons to believe that relations between Platonism and rhetoric in Athens during the fifth century CE were rather close.Z Both were major pillars of pagan cul- ture, or paideia, and thus essential elements in the defense of paganism against in- creasingly powerful and repressive Christian opponents. It is easy to imagine that, under these circumstances, paganism was closing ranks and that philosophers and orators united in their efforts to save traditional ways and values. Although there is no doubt some truth to this view, a closer look reveals that the relations be- tween philosophy and rhetoric were rather more complicated. In what follows, I will discuss these relations with a view to the Platonist school of Athens. By “the Platon- ist school of Athens” I mean the Platonist school founded by Plutarch of Athens in the late fourth century CE, and reaching a famous end under the leadership of Dam- ascius in 529.X I will first survey the evidence for the attitudes towards rhetoric pre- vailing amongst the most important Athenian Platonists of the time.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Florian Marion the Ἐξαίφνης in the Platonic Tradition: from Kinematics to Dynamics (Draft) Studies on Platonic 'The
    F. Marion – The ἐξαίφνης in the Platonic Tradition: from Kinematics to Dynamics Florian Marion The ἐξαίφνης in the Platonic Tradition: from Kinematics to Dynamics (Draft) Studies on Platonic ‘Theoria motus abstracti’ are often focused on dynamics rather than kinematics, in particular on psychic self-motion. This state of affairs is, of course, far from being a bland academic accident: according to Plato, dynamics is the higher science while kinematics is lower on the ‘scientific’ spectrum1. Furthermore, when scholars investigate Platonic abstract kinematics, in front of them there is a very limited set of texts2. Among them, one of the most interesting undoubtedly remains a passage of Parmenides in which Plato challenges the puzzle of the ‘instant of change’, namely the famous text about the ‘sudden’ (τὸ ἐξαίφνης). Plato’s ἐξαίφνης actually is a terminus technicus and a terminus mysticus at once3, in such a way that from Antiquity until today this Platonic concept has been interpreted in very different fashions, either in a physical fashion or in a mystical one. Nevertheless, it has not been analysed how those two directions have been already followed by the Platonic Tradition. So, the aim of this paper is to provide some acquaintance with the exegetical history of ἐξαίφνης inside the Platonic Tradition, from Plato to Marsilio Ficino, by way of Middle Platonism and Greek Neoplatonism. After exposing Plato’s argument of Parm, 156c-157b and its various interpretations (1), I shall investigate the ways by which Middle Platonists (especially Taurus) and Early Neoplatonists as Plotinus and Iamblichus have understood Plato’s use of ἐξαίφνης (2), and finally how this notion had been transferred from kinematics to dynamics in Later Neoplatonism (3).
    [Show full text]
  • Salaminius Hermias Sozomenus – the Ecclesiastical History
    0450-0450 – Salaminius Hermias Sozomenus – The Ecclesiastical History The Ecclesiastical History, comprising a History of the Church, from A.D. 323 to A.D. 425 this file has been downloaded from http://www.ccel.org/ccel/schaff/npnf202.html NPNF (V2-02) Socrates Scholasticus THE 179 ECCLESIASTICAL HISTORY OF SOZOMEN, COMPRISING A HISTORY OF THE CHURCH, FROM A.D. 323 TO A.D. 425. TRANSLATED FROM THE GREEK. Revised by CHESTER D. HARTRANFT, HARTFORD THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY. 191 Introduction. ———————————— Salaminius Hermias Sozomen ———————————— Part I.—The Life. 326 NPNF (V2-02) Socrates Scholasticus The name is an unusual and difficult one. It seems desirable to give preference to the order which Photius adopts, but to preserve the spelling in Nicephorus Callistus, and in the captions of the chief manuscripts, and therefore to call him Salaminius Hermias Sozomen. What the term Salaminius indicates, cannot yet be accurately determined. There are no data to show any official connection of Sozomen with Salamis opposite Athens, or Salamis (Constantia) in Cyprus; certainly there is no record of any naval service. In vi. 32, where he speaks of the greater lights of monasticism in Palestine, Hilarion, Hesychas, and Epiphanius, he remarks, “At the same period in the monasteries, Salamines, Phuscon, Malachion, Crispion, four brethren, were highly distinguished.” In the tart controversy between Epiphanius and the empress, the latter had said, “You have not power to revive the dead; otherwise your archdeacon would not have died.” Sozomen explains, “She alluded to Crispion, the archdeacon, who had died a short time previously; he was brother to Phuscon and Salamanus, monks whom I had occasion to mention when detailing the history of events under the reign of Valens” (viii.
    [Show full text]
  • The School of Ammonius, Son of Hermias, on Knowledge of the Divine
    ELIAS TEMPELIS THE SCHOOL OF AMMONIUS, SON OF HERMIAS, ON KNOWLEDGE OF THE DIVINE ΕΚΔΟΣΕΙΣ ΦΙΛΟΛΟΓΙΚΟΥ ΣΥΛΛΟΓΟΥ ΠΑΡΝΑΣΣΟΣ ΑΘΗΝΑΙ 1998 THE SCHOOL OF AMMONIUS, SON OF HERMIAS, ON KNOWLEDGE OF THE DIVINE ELIAS TEMPELIS THE SCHOOL OF AMMONIUS, SON OF HERMIAS, ON KNOWLEDGE OF THE DIVINE ΕΚΔΟΣΕΙΣ ΦΙΛΟΛΟΓΙΚΟΥ ΣΥΛΛΟΓΟΥ ΠΑΡΝΑΣΣΟΣ ΑΘΗΝΑΙ 1998 ISBN 960­85212­5­4 1998 © Ηλίας Τεμπέλης, 'Ογδόη οδός 3,152 36 Π. Πεντέλη ΕΚΔΟΣΕΙΣ ΦΙΛΟΛΟΓΙΚΟΥ ΣΥΛΛΟΓΟΥ ΠΑΡΝΑΣΣΟΣ Πλατεία Αγ. Γεωργίου Καρύτση 8,105 61 'Αθήναι Υπεύθυνος Τυπογραφείου: ΕΥΑΓΓ. ΜΠΟΥΛΟΥΚΟΣ Όδός Μίλωνος 26,117 45 Αθήναι Τηλ.: 93.45.204 - Fax: 93.17.188 To my wife Christina PREFACE This book is a slightly revised version of my Ph.D. thesis, on which I ' began work in 1990 and which I defended at the University of London in 1994. My study undertakes a reconstruction and critical assessment of the theory of the Neoplatonic school of Ammonius, son of Hermias, on the presuppositions of the acquisition of knowledge of the divine and also on the contents and the purpose of this knowledge. The metaphysical position of the human soul between the intelligible and the sensible worlds allows it to know the intelligible world and the divine, in particular, provided that the cognitive reason-principles in the human intellect are activated. The purpose of such knowledge is the as• similation to the divine and is achieved by means of a personal struggle with the help of theoretical and practical philosophy. The school of Am• monius compared its own philosophical attempt at knowledge of the di• vine to previous similar methods.
    [Show full text]
  • Olearius on Atomism and Theism in Heraclitus: a Presocratic in Late 17Th Century Germany
    Rhizomata 2015; 3(1): 94–123 Oliver Primavesi Olearius on Atomism and Theism in Heraclitus: A Presocratic in late 17th century Germany Abstract: In a 1697 monograph, Gottfried Olearius (1672–1715) endeavours to establish Heraclitus as an important new witness for a general thesis upheld by Ralph Cudworth in 1678. According to Cudworth, Greek philosophers earlier than or independent of Leucippus combined a version of atomism with the belief that the world is ruled by God(s). Olearius tries to improve on Cudworth by showing that Heraclitus, who does not figure among Cudworth’s authorities, also upheld both atomism and theism. As to Heraclitean atomism, Olearius starts from a contra diction within the doxographical tradition: According to some authors, the first principle of Nature in Heraclitus is fire, according to others it is exhala- tion, i.e. air. Olearius suggests that neither “fire” nor “exhalation” can bear their ordinary meaning here, but that Heraclitus uses both terms to hint at very small, swiftly moved, indivisible particles; yet defining such particles as principles of nature must count as atomism. This result is confirmed by a metallurgical simile, apparently used by Heraclitus, which was taken by Aristotle and the doxographi- cal tradition to imply that Heraclitus traced back everything there is to very small and indivisible fire particles prior to the One. The ascription of theism to Heracli- tus, in turn, rests on two further texts which report that Heraclitus ascribed the periodical condensation and rarefaction of matter to a Fate (εἱμαρμένη) function- ing as Demiurge, and that this power is to be identified with Logos and God.
    [Show full text]
  • On Plato Phaedrus 227A–245E
    CJ-Online, 2018.12.08 BOOK REVIEW Hermias: On Plato Phaedrus 227a–245e. Translated by DIRK BALTZLY and MICHAEL SHARE. Ancient Commentators on Aristotle. London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic, 2018. Pp. viii + 316. Hardback, £85.00. ISBN 978-1- 3500-5188-1. n English translation of the commentary on Plato’s Phaedrus by Hermias (c. 410–450 CE) has been needed, and thankfully has now been provid- ed—at least the first half of it—and in good form. It is regrettable, given Athe cost of these volumes, that the decision was made to divide the text. Hil- degund Bernard’s 1997 German translation managed the entire text and a gener- ous amount of ancillary material in 442 pages, well under twice the size of the present volume. Such decisions, of course, do not rest with the authors, and Baltz- ly and Share have done a commendable job. The particular interest in Hermias’ commentary is not only that it is the sole complete commentary on the Phaedrus surviving from antiquity, but also that it is reckoned to be a fairly direct report of the seminar given by the legendary Pla- tonist Syrianus (d. circa 437 CE), of whose own work we possess tragically little, but whose influence upon the history of philosophy looms large through his pu- pil Proclus. In the pages of Hermias we glimpse Syrianus the teacher, who is given to frequent digressions, but these never fail to be illuminating in their own right. At one point, we even find Hermias’ fellow student Proclus asking a couple of astute questions (96, 25–97,12).
    [Show full text]
  • Aeneas of Gaza and Zacharias Scholasticus on Plotinus Enn. 4.3 Sarah Klitenic Wear
    Another Link in the Golden Chain: Aeneas of Gaza and Zacharias Scholasticus on Plotinus Enn. 4.3 Sarah Klitenic Wear URING the late fifth century and early sixth century, the school of rhetoric in Gaza was an offshoot of the great school of Alexandria, with a prominent Christian D 1 membership educated in Platonism. At this time, two note- worthy philosophers emerged from this school: Aeneas, the so- called founder of the school of Gaza and a pupil of Hierocles, and Zacharias, a pupil of Ammonius Hermeiou, who spent little of his life in Gaza, but was immersed in the school of Alexandria.2 Both exhibit an appropriation of Hellenic thought 1 I. P. Sheldon-Williams calls this school of Gaza an offshoot of Alex- andria as Alexandria had been an offshoot of Athens: “The Reaction Against Proclus,” in A. Armstrong (ed.), Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge 1970) 484. Although in a general sense this is true, Gaza never had the predominance that Alexandria had as a major center of learning. Much of the recent scholarship on the Platonists in Gaza looks to their relationship with the contemporary monastic move- ment. For a general history of the Hellenic movement in Gaza see Y. Ashkenazi, “Sophists and Priests in Late Antique Gaza according to Cho- ricius the Rhetor,” in B. Bitton-Ashkelony and A. Kofsky (eds.), Christian Gaza in Late Antiquity (Leiden 2004) 195–198; cf. R. Van Dam, “From Paganism to Christianity in Late Antique Gaza,” Viator 16 (1985) 1–20. For an older but thorough study see G.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    Cover Page The handle http://hdl.handle.net/1887/24375 holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation Author: Wang, Qi Title: Boethius and the importance of basic logic and mathematics for philosophy Issue Date: 2014-03-06 Bibliography Bibliography I. Boethius’ Works Mathematical Works -(1867). Anicii Manlii Torquati Severini Boetii: De Institutione Arithmetica (libri duo); De institutione musica (libri quinque). Friedlein, G. (ed.). Lipsiae: in aedibus B.G. Teubner. -(1983). Boethian Number Theory: A Translation of the De Institutione Arithmetica. Masi, M. (transl.). Amsterdam: Rodopi. -(1989). Fundamentals of Music. Bower, C.M. (transl.). New Haven [etc.]: Yale University Press. -(1999). Anicii Manlii Severini Boethii De Arithmetica. Oosthout, H. and Schilling, J. (eds.). Turnhout: Brepols. Logical Works -An. Manl. Sev. Boetii In Porphyrium Dialogi A Victorino Translati. Partrologia Latina (Migne), Vol. 64 (LXIV): 9A-70D. -An. Manl. Sev. Boetii Commetaria In Porphyrium A Se Translatum. Partrologia Latina (Migne), Vol. 64 (LXIV): 71A-158D. -An. Manl. Sev. Boethii In Categorias Aristotelis Libri Quatuor. Partrologia Latina (Migne), Vol. 64 (LXIV): 159A-294C. -An. Manl. Sev. Boetii In Librum Aristotelis De Interpretatione Libri Duo: Editio Prima, Seu Minora Commentaria. Partrologia Latina (Migne), Vol. 64 (LXIV): 293D-640A. -An. Manl. Sev. Boetii De Syllogismo Hypothetico Libri Duo. Partrologia Latina (Migne), Vol. 64 (LXIV): 831B-876C. -(1906). Anicii Manlii Severini Boethii In Isagogen Porphyrii Commenta. Brandt S. Corpus Scriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum, Vol. XXXXVIII. - 171 - Bibliography Vindobonae [etc.]: Tempsky [etc.]. -(1957-1958). “The Second Edition of the Commentaries on the Isagoge of Porphyry, (Book I),” in McKeon, R. (ed.) Selections From Medieval Philosophers (I): Augustine to Albert the Great.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy, Ἱερατική, and the Damascian Dichotomy: Pursuing the Bacchic Ideal in the Sixth-Century Academy Todd Krulak
    Philosophy, Ἱερατική, and the Damascian Dichotomy: Pursuing the Bacchic Ideal in the Sixth-Century Academy Todd Krulak HE BEGINNING of the sixth century CE found the venerable Athenian Academy unexpectedly struggling T to maintain its very existence. The institution enjoyed both curricular and political stability for much of the fifth century under the capable leadership of Proclus of Lycia, but after his death in 485, the school struggled to find a capable successor. Edward Watts has suggested that the failing fortunes of the Academy in this period were due to a dearth of candi- dates who possessed the right combination of the intellectual heft required to carry on the grand tradition of the Academy and the political deftness needed to protect it against encroach- ing Christian authorities. As a result, the school was perched on the razor’s edge. In particular, Watts postulates that an im- politic emphasis on traditional forms of religious ritual in the Academy in the post-Proclan era, especially by the indiscrete Hegias, the head of the school around the beginning of the sixth century, intensified Christian scrutiny.1 Thus, the assump- tion of the position of scholarch, the head of the school, by the 1 See E. J. Watts, City and School in Late Antique Athens and Alexandria (Berke- ley 2006) 118–142; and “Athens between East and West: Elite Self-Presen- tation and the Durability of Traditional Cult,” GRBS 57 (2017) 191–213, which contends that, with regard to religion, Athens retained a decidedly traditional character well into the fifth century. Even after the temples were shuttered in the second quarter of that century, elites supportive of ancestral practices extended financial support to the Academy, for it was known to be sympathetic to traditional deities and rites.
    [Show full text]
  • Cleanthes' Hymn to Zeus
    Studien und Texte zu Antike und Christentum Studies and Texts in Antiquity and Christianity Herausgeber/Editor: CHRISTOPH MARKSCHIES (Berlin) Beirat/ Advisory Board HUBERT CANCIK (Berlin) • GIOVANNI CASADIO (Salerno) SUSANNA ELM (Berkeley) • JOHANNES HAHN (Münster) JÖRG RÜPKE (Erfurt) 33 Johan C. Thorn Cleanthes' Hymn to Zeus Text, Translation, and Commentary Mohr Siebeck JOHAN C.THOM, born 1954; studied Classics at the Universities of Stellenbosch (BA 1974) and Pretoria (MA 1980); New Testament and Early Christian Literature at the University of Chicago (PhD 1990); teaches Greek Language and Literature at the University of Stellenbosch, Professor of Classics since 1997; recipient of an Alexan- der von Humboldt Fellowship (Tübingen, 1995) and a Visiting Membership of the Institute for Advanced Study (Princeton, 2001-2002). ISBN 3-16-149174-2 ISBN-13 978-3-16-149174-0 ISSN 1436-3003 (Studien und Texte zu Antike und Christentum) Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbiblio- graphie; detailed bibliographic data is available on the Internet at http://iinb.d-nb.dc. Unrevised Paperback Edition 2006. © 2005 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher's written permission. This applies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and processing in electronic systems. The book was typeset by Martin Fischer in Tübingen using Bembo typeface, printed by Guide-Druck in Tübingen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Held in Rottenburg. Printed in Germany. For Sjarlene Preface Although the Hymn to Zeus is often cited as one of the most important docu- ments of early Stoic philosophy — indeed the only text to survive more or less intact - it has not yet received a detailed treatment in a monograph by itself.
    [Show full text]
  • The Status of Sexuality in Neoplatonism
    Graeco-Latina Brunensia 25 / 2020 / 2 https://doi.org/10.5817/GLB2020-2-12 The Status of Sexuality in Neoplatonism José María Zamora Calvo (Autonomous University of Madrid) Abstract The stereotype of “Platonic love” that developed during the Renaissance implies a type of relationship, between two people of the opposite gender, which does not involve sexual activ- ity. A new examination of certain relevant texts by Neoplatonists such as Plotinus, Porphyry, / ARTICLES ČLÁNKY Hierocles, Hermias, Proclus and Olympiodorus, written during the period of Late Antiquity, establish that the question of sexuality is present in the very architecture of their systems, thus maintaining a coherent approach over time. “Mixed love”, tending towards the sexual union that enables the conception of children, is morally good. Through an exegesis of the Sympo- sium, Phaedrus and First Alcibiades, each of these Neoplatonic philosophers explores sexuality through the prisms of cosmology, ethics and political theory. Keywords sexuality; Neoplatonism; mixed love; Neoplatonic love; Neoplatonic ethic 163 José María Zamora Calvo The Status of Sexuality in Neoplatonism In the Life of Isidore, Damascius tells the story of the philosopher Theosebius (a disciple of Hierocles of Alexandria and an admirer of Epictetus),1 who was not able to have chil- dren and as a result, suggested to his wife that she should either swap her wedding ring for a chastity ring (i.e. become celibate), or marry another man. She chose a life of absti- nence, and so the couple lived out the days of their marriage (with the help of this “talis- man” (φυλακτήριον), which also acted as a “contraceptive”) without maintaining sexual relations (Fr.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Motion and Reflection: Hermias and Proclus
    Page 44 3 Self-motion and reflection: Hermias and Proclus on the harmony of Plato and Aristotle on the soul Stephen Menn 1 A central puzzle of recent scholarship on late Neoplatonism has been to understand how what Richard Sorabji has called a ‘perfectly crazy position’, the thesis of the harmony of Plato and Aristotle, nonetheless ‘proved philosophically fruitful’2— whereas, for instance, the same philosophers’ perfectly crazy thesis of the harmony of Plato and Homer did not. In this chapter, starting from Hermias’ commentary on a passage of the Phaedrus which poses a difficulty for harmonization, I hope to shed some light on what the late Neoplatonists were asserting when they asserted the harmony of Plato and Aristotle, in general or on some particular issue (here the immortality of soul); on why they were inclined to make such assertions of harmony, and what they saw themselves as needing to do in order to defend them; and on why, in the process of defending them, they were led to conceptual clarifications which were in some cases of longstanding benefit to the conceptual store of philosophy. I will point to a sur- prising case of such a conceptual benefit resulting from Neoplatonic interpretations of this Phaedrus passage and its parallels in the Timaeus. While my central example will be from Hermias, the themes I am interested in are not peculiar to him, and I will also make use of other late Neoplatonic authors, especially Proclus. Hermias, and Proclus, to recall, were both students of Syrianus; at one point in Hermias’ commentary ‘our companion Proclus’ raises an aporia, and ‘the philosopher’—that is, ‘the professor’— 1 This chapter was worked out in its essentials in 1987–88.
    [Show full text]