On Defining Modality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On Defining Modality ON DEFINING MODALITY FERENC KIEFER 1. INTRODUCTION The term 'modality' has been used to refer to a relatively great number of apparently disparate things in linguistic and logical lit- erature. Sometimes modality has been restricted to expressions of possibility and necessity, in other cases it has been used äs a cover term for expressions of Speakers' attitudes. Modality may be iden- tified with what expressions of propositional attitudes do in sen- tences,butit may also betaken to cover the meanings of a linguisti- cally definable class of elements (modal auxiliaries, modal adver- bials, modal particles, parenthetical verbs, etc.). The logical tradition concentrates on the description of proposi- tions. Consequently, the inquiry into modality is restricted to what may be considered to be 'propositional' in modality. The linguistic tradition, on the other hand, emphasizes the 'non-propositional' aspects of modality. It is pointed out that modal expressions in natural language are mainly used to express the speaker's attitudes toward states-of-affairs. In the present paper I wish to make explicit some of the notions of modality — I hope the most important ones — which underlie current inquiries into the problems of modality. The notions which I am going to discuss are the following: (i) modality äs an expression of possibility or necessity, (ii) modality äs the meaning of propositional attitudes, (iii) modality äs expressions of speaker's attitudes. I am going to show that the logical tradition and the linguistic tradition need not be in conflict, that there is a way to reconcile the two traditions. 0165-4004/87/0021-67 $ 2,- © Moutpn Publishers, The Hague Societas Linguistica Europäer 68 2. MODALITY AS AN EXPRESSION OF POSSIBILITY OR NECESSITY The notions of 'necessarily true proposition' and 'possibly true proposition' are well-known in traditional logic.1 A proposition is necessarüy true or necessarily false if its truth or falsity does not depend on the way the world actually is, that is, if its truth or fal- sity is already guaranteed by the very meaning of the proposition. On the other hand, a proposition is possibly (or contingently) true if it is not necessarily false and it is possibly false if it is not neces- sarily true. Though they represent distinct categories, necessity and possibility are not independent notions. Either one can be elimi- nated in favor of the other one. If we denote the necessity operator by and the possibility operator by 0 we may formulate the relationship between necessity and possibility äs follows. (1) (a) D p = ~ 0 ~ p (b) 0 p = ~ D ~ p In addition, the following two implications are valid. (2) (a) D p => p (b) p =* 0 p That is, from the fact that p is necessarily true it follows that p is true, and from the fact that p is true it follows that p is possibly true. The type of modality which is exclusively concerned with the necessary or contingent truth of propositions is often referred to äs logical or alethic modality. Examples for alethic modality with must and can are given in (3) (a) —(b). (3) (a) Cats must be animals. (b) Cats can be dangerous. By making use of the equivalencies in (1) (a)—(b) the sentences in (3) (a)—(b) can be paraphrased äs (4) (a) —(b), respectively. (4) (a) It cannot be the case that cats are not animals. (b) It is not necessarily the case that cats are not dangerous. 69 Notice that the proposition Cats are animals is analytic, hence necessarily true. On the other band, the proposition Cats are dan- gerous is not analytic (it is contingent), hence possibly true. Alethic modality is a central notion in classical logic, in ordinary language, however, it is rather peripheric.2 Clear cases of alethically modal sentences do not occur frequently in everyday discourse. From a linguistic point of view the notions of epistemic and deontic modality are nrnch more important. Epistemic necessity and epistemic possibility are expressed by contingent propositions, i.e. not only 0 p but also depends on what the world is like. The proposition p is epistemically necessary iff p is entailed by what the Speaker knows about the world and the proposition p is epistemically possible iff p is compatible with what the Speaker knows about the world. The speaker's knowledge is representable äs a set of propositions.3 Epistemic necessity and epistemic possibility are interdefinable in the same way äs alethic necessity and alethic possibility are, i.e. the equivalence relations in (1) (a) —(b) hold with equal force in the case of epistemic modalities äs well. In addition, the implications (2) (a) —(b) remain valid. The following sentences may be illustrations of epistemic pos- sibility and epistemic necessity, respectively. (5) (a) It can be raining in Budapest, (b) It must be raining in Budapest. The meaning of (5) (a) can be circumscribed in the following fashion: "In view of what I know it is not excluded that it is raining in Budapest". The sentence (5) (b), on the other hand, may be given the following Interpretation: "From what I know it follows that it is raining in Budapest". The deontic modalities have to do with Obligations and permissions* Instead of the modal operators D and 0» deontic logic exploits two deontic operators usually denoted by O (for 'obligatory') and P (for 'permitted'). Something is considered to be obligatory or per- mitted with respect to some moral or legal System (with respect to a System of laws). Ä proposition^? is obligatory iff it is not permitted that ~ p and it is permitted iff it is not obligatory that ~ p. These are the deontic counterparts of the equivalence-relations (1) (a) —(b) In deontic logic, however, the implications (2) (a) —(b) are not valid. 70 Consider (6) (a) Op ^> p (b) p^Pp That is, from the fact that p is obligatory it does not follow that p is the case, and from the fact that p is the case it does not follow that p is permitted. The sentence (7) (a) may be considered äs expressing deontic possibility and the sentence (7) (b) äs expressing deontic necessity. (7) (a) Bill can go to Stockholm, (b) Bill must go to Stockholm. The close relations between deontic and modal concepts are also reflected in natural language. In most languages, the expressions of certainty, necessity and possibility are also used for obligations and permissions. The modalities discussed so far do not exhaust all possibilities. Thus, for example, possibility and necessity in the following sen- tences may have to do with the speaker's desires (boulomaic modal- tty). (8) (a) Bill can be our leader. (b) Bill must be our leader. Dlspositional modality refers to certain dispositions äs illustrated in (9) (a)-(b). (9) (a) Bill can sneeze. (b) Bill must sneeze. That is, (9) (a) may be taken to mean that in view of Bill's dispo- sitions it is not excluded that he sneezes and (9) (b) may mean that in view of BilFs dispositions it is necessary that he sneezes.5 In view of the various modalities it is important to look for a general framework which can be made use of in the definitions of all these modalities. Such a general framework is provided by possible world semantics? Possible worlds meeting a certain condition are called accessible possible worlds. The following def initions hold: 71 p is necessarily true iff p is true in all accessible possible worlds and p is possible iff there is at least one accessible possible world in which p is true. In the case of alethic modality all possible worlds are accessible from any possible world. As for epistemic modality, given a possible world w, those pos- sible worlds wl are accessible from w that are identical with respect to certain facts (what somebody knows to be the case). In the case of deontic modality the set of accessible possible worlds is the set of all worlds in which everybody acts according to some moral or legal System. Finally, in the case of boulomaic modality the accessible possible worlds are defined by the Speaker's desires: the accessible worlds are those that are compatible with the speaker's desires.7 In this way any number of modal concepts can be defined. Gen- erally, each modality will.correspond to a certain accessibility or alternativeness relation.8 It has also been argued that this relation can be replaced by the notionof background.9rfhus, what the Speaker knows defines an epistemic background, a moral or legal System defines a deontic background, the speaker's desires define a boulo- maic background, etc. The concepts of possibility and necessity can then be reconstructed in terms of logical entailment and logical compatibility. The following definitions hold: p is necessarily true iff it is logically entailed by the background and p is possibly true iff it is logically compatible with the background. To summarize, the concept of modality can be explicated in the following fashion. The modality of p means that p is necessarily true or false, or possibly true or false with respect to a certain background. Or, alternatively, the modality of p means that p is necessarily true or false, or possibly true or false in a certain set of possible worlds. This set is defined by the accessibility relation considered. For further reference we shall call this definition of modality the logical definition of modality. The logical definition of modality can easily be extended to cover graded possibilities äs well.10 We have todo with graded possibil- ities in the following sentences.
Recommended publications
  • The Strategy of Case-Marking
    Case marking strategies Helen de Hoop & Andrej Malchukov1 Radboud University Nijmegen DRAFT January 2006 Abstract Two strategies of case marking in natural languages are discussed. These are defined as two violable constraints whose effects are shown to converge in the case of differential object marking but diverge in the case of differential subject marking. The strength of the case bearing arguments will be shown to be of utmost importance for case marking as well as voice alternations. The strength of arguments can be viewed as a function of their discourse prominence. The analysis of the case marking patterns we find cross-linguistically is couched in a bidirectional OT analysis. 1. Assumptions In this section we wish to put forward our three basic assumptions: (1) In ergative-absolutive systems ergative case is assigned to the first argument x of a two-place relation R(x,y). (2) In nominative-accusative systems accusative case is assigned to the second argument y of a two-place relation R(x,y). (3) Morphologically unmarked case can be the absence of case. The first two assumptions deal with the linking between the first (highest) and second (lowest) argument in a transitive sentence and the type of case marking. For reasons of convenience, we will refer to these arguments quite sloppily as the subject and the object respectively, although we are aware of the fact that the labels subject and object may not be appropriate in all contexts, dependent on how they are actually defined. In many languages, ergative and accusative case are assigned only or mainly in transitive sentences, while in intransitive sentences ergative and accusative case are usually not assigned.
    [Show full text]
  • On Root Modality and Thematic Relations in Tagalog and English*
    Proceedings of SALT 26: 775–794, 2016 On root modality and thematic relations in Tagalog and English* Maayan Abenina-Adar Nikos Angelopoulos UCLA UCLA Abstract The literature on modality discusses how context and grammar interact to produce different flavors of necessity primarily in connection with functional modals e.g., English auxiliaries. In contrast, the grammatical properties of lexical modals (i.e., thematic verbs) are less understood. In this paper, we use the Tagalog necessity modal kailangan and English need as a case study in the syntax-semantics of lexical modals. Kailangan and need enter two structures, which we call ‘thematic’ and ‘impersonal’. We show that when they establish a thematic dependency with a subject, they express necessity in light of this subject’s priorities, and in the absence of an overt thematic subject, they express necessity in light of priorities endorsed by the speaker. To account for this, we propose a single lexical entry for kailangan / need that uniformly selects for a ‘needer’ argument. In thematic constructions, the needer is the overt subject, and in impersonal constructions, it is an implicit speaker-bound pronoun. Keywords: modality, thematic relations, Tagalog, syntax-semantics interface 1 Introduction In this paper, we observe that English need and its Tagalog counterpart, kailangan, express two different types of necessity depending on the syntactic structure they enter. We show that thematic constructions like (1) express necessities in light of priorities of the thematic subject, i.e., John, whereas impersonal constructions like (2) express necessities in light of priorities of the speaker. (1) John needs there to be food left over.
    [Show full text]
  • Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics
    Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics YEUNG, \y,ang -C-hun ...:' . '",~ ... ~ .. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Philosophy In Philosophy The Chinese University of Hong Kong January 2010 Abstract of thesis entitled: Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics Submitted by YEUNG, Wang Chun for the degree of Master of Philosophy at the Chinese University of Hong Kong in July 2009 This ,thesis investigates problems surrounding the lively debate about how Kripke's examples of necessary a posteriori truths and contingent a priori truths should be explained. Two-dimensionalism is a recent development that offers a non-reductive analysis of such truths. The semantic interpretation of two-dimensionalism, proposed by Jackson and Chalmers, has certain 'descriptive' elements, which can be articulated in terms of the following three claims: (a) names and natural kind terms are reference-fixed by some associated properties, (b) these properties are known a priori by every competent speaker, and (c) these properties reflect the cognitive significance of sentences containing such terms. In this thesis, I argue against two arguments directed at such 'descriptive' elements, namely, The Argument from Ignorance and Error ('AlE'), and The Argument from Variability ('AV'). I thereby suggest that reference-fixing properties belong to the semantics of names and natural kind terms, and not to their metasemantics. Chapter 1 is a survey of some central notions related to the debate between descriptivism and direct reference theory, e.g. sense, reference, and rigidity. Chapter 2 outlines the two-dimensional approach and introduces the va~ieties of interpretations 11 of the two-dimensional framework.
    [Show full text]
  • The Modal Logic of Potential Infinity, with an Application to Free Choice
    The Modal Logic of Potential Infinity, With an Application to Free Choice Sequences Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Ethan Brauer, B.A. ∼6 6 Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2020 Dissertation Committee: Professor Stewart Shapiro, Co-adviser Professor Neil Tennant, Co-adviser Professor Chris Miller Professor Chris Pincock c Ethan Brauer, 2020 Abstract This dissertation is a study of potential infinity in mathematics and its contrast with actual infinity. Roughly, an actual infinity is a completed infinite totality. By contrast, a collection is potentially infinite when it is possible to expand it beyond any finite limit, despite not being a completed, actual infinite totality. The concept of potential infinity thus involves a notion of possibility. On this basis, recent progress has been made in giving an account of potential infinity using the resources of modal logic. Part I of this dissertation studies what the right modal logic is for reasoning about potential infinity. I begin Part I by rehearsing an argument|which is due to Linnebo and which I partially endorse|that the right modal logic is S4.2. Under this assumption, Linnebo has shown that a natural translation of non-modal first-order logic into modal first- order logic is sound and faithful. I argue that for the philosophical purposes at stake, the modal logic in question should be free and extend Linnebo's result to this setting. I then identify a limitation to the argument for S4.2 being the right modal logic for potential infinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Definiteness and Determinacy
    Linguistics and Philosophy manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Definiteness and Determinacy Elizabeth Coppock · David Beaver the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract This paper distinguishes between definiteness and determinacy. Defi- niteness is seen as a morphological category which, in English, marks a (weak) uniqueness presupposition, while determinacy consists in denoting an individual. Definite descriptions are argued to be fundamentally predicative, presupposing uniqueness but not existence, and to acquire existential import through general type-shifting operations that apply not only to definites, but also indefinites and possessives. Through these shifts, argumental definite descriptions may become either determinate (and thus denote an individual) or indeterminate (functioning as an existential quantifier). The latter option is observed in examples like `Anna didn't give the only invited talk at the conference', which, on its indeterminate reading, implies that there is nothing in the extension of `only invited talk at the conference'. The paper also offers a resolution of the issue of whether posses- sives are inherently indefinite or definite, suggesting that, like indefinites, they do not mark definiteness lexically, but like definites, they typically yield determinate readings due to a general preference for the shifting operation that produces them. Keywords definiteness · descriptions · possessives · predicates · type-shifting We thank Dag Haug, Reinhard Muskens, Luca Crniˇc,Cleo Condoravdi, Lucas
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Modality, Mind, and Mathematics
    Epistemic Modality, Mind, and Mathematics Hasen Khudairi June 20, 2017 c Hasen Khudairi 2017, 2020 All rights reserved. 1 Abstract This book concerns the foundations of epistemic modality. I examine the nature of epistemic modality, when the modal operator is interpreted as con- cerning both apriority and conceivability, as well as states of knowledge and belief. The book demonstrates how epistemic modality relates to the compu- tational theory of mind; metaphysical modality; deontic modality; the types of mathematical modality; to the epistemic status of undecidable proposi- tions and abstraction principles in the philosophy of mathematics; to the apriori-aposteriori distinction; to the modal profile of rational propositional intuition; and to the types of intention, when the latter is interpreted as a modal mental state. Each essay is informed by either epistemic logic, modal and cylindric algebra or coalgebra, intensional semantics or hyperin- tensional semantics. The book’s original contributions include theories of: (i) epistemic modal algebras and coalgebras; (ii) cognitivism about epistemic modality; (iii) two-dimensional truthmaker semantics, and interpretations thereof; (iv) the ground-theoretic ontology of consciousness; (v) fixed-points in vagueness; (vi) the modal foundations of mathematical platonism; (vii) a solution to the Julius Caesar problem based on metaphysical definitions availing of notions of ground and essence; (viii) the application of epistemic two-dimensional semantics to the epistemology of mathematics; and (ix) a modal logic for rational intuition. I develop, further, a novel approach to conditions of self-knowledge in the setting of the modal µ-calculus, as well as novel epistemicist solutions to Curry’s and the liar paradoxes.
    [Show full text]
  • Branching Time
    24.244 Modal Logic, Fall 2009 Prof. Robert Stalnaker Lecture Notes 16: Branching Time Ordinary tense logic is a 'multi-modal logic', in which there are two (pairs of) modal operators: P/H and F/G. In the semantics, the accessibility relations, for past and future tenses, are interdefinable, so in effect there is only one accessibility relation in the semantics. However, P/H cannot be defined in terms of F/G. The expressive power of the language does not match the semantics in this case. But this is just a minimal multi-modal theory. The frame is a pair consisting of an accessibility relation and a set of points, representing moments of time. The two modal operators are defined on this one set. In the branching time theory, we have two different W's, in a way. We put together the basic tense logic, where the points are moments of time, with the modal logic, where they are possible worlds. But they're not independent of one another. In particular, unlike abstract modal semantics, where possible worlds are primitives, the possible worlds in the branching time theory are defined entities, and the accessibility relation is defined with respect to the structure of the possible worlds. In the pure, abstract theory, where possible worlds are primitives, to the extent that there is structure, the structure is defined in terms of the relation on these worlds. So the worlds themselves are points, the structure of the overall frame is given by the accessibility relation. In the branching time theory, the possible worlds are possible histories, which have a structure defined by a more basic frame, and the accessibility relation is defined in terms of that structure.
    [Show full text]
  • 29 Alethic Modal Logics and Semantics
    29 Alethic Modal Logics and Semantics GERHARD SCHURZ 1 Introduction The first axiomatic development of modal logic was untertaken by C. I. Lewis in 1912. Being anticipated by H. McCall in 1880, Lewis tried to cure logic from the ‘paradoxes’ of extensional (i.e. truthfunctional) implication … (cf. Hughes and Cresswell 1968: 215). He introduced the stronger notion of strict implication <, which can be defined with help of a necessity operator ᮀ (for ‘it is neessary that:’) as follows: A < B iff ᮀ(A … B); in words, A strictly implies B iff A necessarily implies B (A, B, . for arbitrary sen- tences). The new primitive sentential operator ᮀ is intensional (non-truthfunctional): the truth value of A does not determine the truth-value of ᮀA. To demonstrate this it suf- fices to find two particular sentences p, q which agree in their truth value without that ᮀp and ᮀq agree in their truth-value. For example, it p = ‘the sun is identical with itself,’ and q = ‘the sun has nine planets,’ then p and q are both true, ᮀp is true, but ᮀq is false. The dual of the necessity-operator is the possibility operator ‡ (for ‘it is possible that:’) defined as follows: ‡A iff ÿᮀÿA; in words, A is possible iff A’s negation is not necessary. Alternatively, one might introduce ‡ as new primitive operator (this was Lewis’ choice in 1918) and define ᮀA as ÿ‡ÿA and A < B as ÿ‡(A ŸÿB). Lewis’ work cumulated in Lewis and Langford (1932), where the five axiomatic systems S1–S5 were introduced.
    [Show full text]
  • PARASITIC MIRATIVITY of ENGLISH USE in COLIN TREVORROWS MOVIE “JURASSIC WORLD” Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of Th
    PARASITIC MIRATIVITY OF ENGLISH USE IN COLIN TREVORROWS MOVIE “JURASSIC WORLD” Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Sarjana Humaniora in English and Literature Department of Faculty of Adab and Humanities of UIN Alauddin Makassar By MUJI RETNO Reg. No. 40300111080 ENGLISH AND LITERATURE DEPARTMENT ADAB AND HUMANITIES FACULTY ALAUDDIN STATE ISLAMIC UNIVERSITY MAKASSAR 2016 PARASITIC MIRATIVITY OF ENGLISH USE IN COLIN TREVORROW’S MOVIE “JURASSIC WORLD” Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Sarjana Humaniora in English and Literature Department of Faculty of Adab and Humanities of UIN Alauddin Makassar By MUJI RETNO Reg. No. 40300111080 ENGLISH AND LITERATURE DEPARTMENT ADAB AND HUMANITIES FACULTY ALAUDDIN STATE ISLAMIC UNIVERSITY MAKASSAR 2016 i MOTTO “EDUCATION IS WHAT REMAINS AFTER ONE HAS FORGOTTEN WHAT ONE HAS LEARNED IN SCHOOL.” (Albert Eistein) “EDUCATION IS A PROGRESSIVE DISCOVERY OF OUR OWN IGNORENCE.” (Charlie Chaplin) “EVERY THE LAST STEP INEVITABLY HAS THE FIRST STEP” (Muji Retno) ii ACKNOWLEDGE All praises to Allah who has blessed, guided and given the health to the researcherduring writing this thesis. Then, the researcherr would like to send invocation and peace to Prophet Muhammad SAW peace be upon him, who has guided the people from the bad condition to the better life. The researcher realizes that in writing and finishing this thesis, there are many people that have provided their suggestion, advice, help and motivation. Therefore, the researcher would like to express thanks and highest appreciation to all of them. For the first, the researcher gives special gratitude to her parents, Masir Hadis and Jumariah Yaha who have given their loves, cares, supports and prayers in every single time.
    [Show full text]
  • Representing-Time-An-Essay-On-Temporality-As
    Representing Time To commemorate the centenary of J. E. McTaggart’s ‘The unreality of time’ (1908) Representing Time: An Essay on Temporality as Modality K. M. JASZCZOLT 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With oYces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York # K. M. Jaszczolt 2009 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2009 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Modality and Evidentiality in Gitksan at the Semantics-Pragmatics Interface By
    Epistemic Modality and Evidentiality in Gitksan at the Semantics-Pragmatics Interface by Tyler Roy Gösta Peterson B.Mus., University of British Columbia, 1999 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in The Faculty of Graduate Studies (Linguistics) THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA (Vancouver) April, 2010 c Tyler Roy Gösta Peterson 2010 Abstract The aim of this dissertation is to provide an empirically driven, theoretically informed investigation of how speakers of Gitksan, a Tsimshianic language spoken in the northwest coast of Canada, express knowledge about the world around them. There are three main goals that motivate this investigation, summarized below: (1) (i.) To provide the first detailed description of the evidential and modal system in Gitksan. (ii.) To provide a formal semantic and pragmatic account of this system that adequately explains the meanings of the modals and evidentials, as well as how they are used in discourse. (iii.) To identify and examine the specific properties the Gitksan evidential/modal system brings to bear on current theories of semantics and pragmatics, as well as the consequences this analysis has on the study of modality and evidentiality cross-linguistically. In addition to documenting the evidential and modal meanings in Gitksan, I test and work through a variety of theoretical tools from the literature designed to investigate evidentiality and modality in a language. This begins by determining what level of mean- ing the individual evidentials in Gitksan operate on. The current state of research into the connection between evidentiality and epistemic modality has identified two different types of evidentials defined by the level of meaning they operate on: propositional and illocutionary evidentials.
    [Show full text]
  • An Ultra-Condensed Introduction to Discourse Analysis: Two-Hour Tutorial at NICTA (National Information and Communication Technologies Australia)
    An ultra-condensed introduction to Discourse Analysis: two-hour tutorial at NICTA (National Information and Communication Technologies Australia) Rogelio Nazar Pontificia Universidad Católica de Valparaíso [email protected] 23 October 2015 Abstract: Linguistics has historically been devoted to the study of language as a system rather than its manifestation in particular texts. In spite of this, Discourse Analysis (DA) has been established for more than 60 years as a place of convergence of many disciplines interested in discourse. This tutorial is aimed at people with little or no knowledge of linguistic terminology and its purpose is to offer a shallow introduction to DA. This tutorial will not specifically address computational procedures for text analysis. On the contrary, the analytical methods explained here are to be conducted manually, but with systematic and almost mechanical methods. This is mainly a practical tutorial and the focus will be on analysing a real text in English. The first part presents the theoretical principles and analytical tools, while the rest is devoted to practical exercises implementing the proposed method. Given the limitations of time, this tutorial only comments upon a short number concepts. 1. Introduction It is a real pleasure for me to be here today in this not very sunny day in Canberra and I am delighted to have all of you here. As you probably know, I have been entrusted with the impossible task of summarizing 60 years of research in discourse analysis (DA) in a couple of hours. Facing such challenge, what I am going to do is not really to offer a real introduction, because we would need a semester course just to cover the essential readings.
    [Show full text]