Ordinal Numbers and Ordinal Arithmetic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ordinal Numbers and Ordinal Arithmetic Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Cardinal and ordinal numbers Cardinal numbers are counting numbers @ one, two, three, ··· , @0; 2 0 = c; ··· Ordinal numbers are ranking numbers first, second, third, ··· Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Well-order relation Recall that every set can be well-ordered by Zermelo’s Well-ordering Principle. For example, finite sets can be easily well-ordered. R with usual order ≤ is not well-ordered. N with usual order ≤ is well-ordered. 0 Consider a total order ≤ on N so that N = f1; 3; 5; ··· ; 2; 4; 6; · · · g 0 Then ≤ is a well-order relation on N. Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Order isomorphisms Definition Two well-ordered sets (A; ≤) and (B; ≤0) are called order-isomorphic, written (A; ≤) ≈ (B; ≤0) or simply A ≈ B, if there is an increasing bijection f : A ! B (a ≤ b ) f (a) ≤0 f (b)) Such a function is called an order-isomorphism. Example 0 (N; ≤) 6≈ (N; ≤ ) 0 Suppose 9f :(N; ≤ ) ! (N; ≤), an order-isomorphism. Then 0 fa 2 N j a < 2g is infinite, but fb 2 N j b < f (2)g is finite, a contradiction. Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Axiom of Ordinality Remark The order-isomorphic relation ≈ is an equivalence relation. AXIOM OF ORDINALITY O1 Each well-ordered set (A; ≤) is assigned an ordinal number ord(A; ≤), and if α is an ordinal number then α = ord(A; ≤) for some well-ordered set (A; ≤). O2 ord(A; ≤) = 0 iff A = ; O3 If (A; ≤) is a well-ordered set with cardA = k then ord(A; ≤) = k. O4 For two well-ordered sets (A; ≤) and (B; ≤0), ord(A; ≤) = ord(B; ≤0) iff (A; ≤) ≈ (B; ≤0) Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Briefly speaking n Sets o ∼(equipotency) $ fcardinal numbersg n Well-ordered Sets o ≈(order-isom) $ fordinal numbersg NOTATION ! := ord(N; ≤) = ordf1; 2; 3; · · · g Remark that ! 6= ordf1; 3; 5; ··· ; 2; 4; 6; · · · g Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Segments Definition Let (A; ≤) be a toset. A subset S of A is called a segment of A if y 2 S, x ≤ y with x 2 A ) x 2 S. Remark Let (A; ≤) be a well-ordered set. For x 2 A, let Ax := fa 2 A j a < xg. Then Ax is a segment of A. FACT: Every segment of A is either A itself or a segment of the form Ax . Example 0 For (N; ≤ ) = f1; 3; ··· ; 2; 4; · · · g, 0 we see that (N; ≤) ≈ (N2; ≤ ). Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Ordinal ordering Definition Let α = ord(A; ≤) and β = ord(B; ≤0) be ordinal numbers. We write α 4 β if (A; ≤) is order-isomorphic to a segment of (B; ≤0). Example ! 4; 6= ordf1; 3; 5; ··· ; 2; 4; 6; · · · g FACT: (1) The cardinal ordering 4 is a total order on cardinal numbers. (2) The ordinal ordering 4 is a total order on ordinal numbers. Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Ordinal Sum α + β Definition Let (A; ≤) and (B; ≤0) be two disjoint well-ordered sets. Define the order relation ≤∗ on A S B as follows: 8 a 2 A; b 2 B or <> a ≤∗ b , a; b 2 A; a ≤ b or > :a; b 2 B; a ≤0 b Then it is easy to see that (A S B; ≤∗) is a well-ordered set. Definition Let α = ord(A; ≤) and β = ord(B; ≤0) where A and B are disjoint. Define the ordinal sum α + β to be α + β := ord(A S B; ≤∗): Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Examples (1) 1 + ! = ! Why? 1 + ! = ord(f0g Sf1; 2; · · · g) = ordf1; 2; 3; · · · g = ! (2) ! 4; 6= ! + 1 Why? ∗ (i) f1; 2; 3 · · · g (A; ≤ ) = f1; 2; 3; ··· ; 0g, order-isomorphic to the segment A0, Hence 4. (ii) Let f :(A; ≤∗) = f1; 2; 3 ··· ; 0g ! f1; 2; 3; · · · g be an order-isomorphism. The segment A0 is infinite, by the segment Nf (0) is finite, a contradiction. Hence 6=. (3) Similarly, we can shows that α 4; 6= α + 1 for any ordinal number α. Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Ordinal product β α Definition Let α = ord(A; ≤) and β = ord(B; ≤0). Define the ordinal product β α to be β α := ord(A × B; ≤∗) where ≤∗ is the lexicographic ordering on A × B which is defined as follows: ( a < x or (a; b) ≤∗ (x; y) , a = x; b ≤0 y The fact is that the lexicographic ordering ≤∗ is a well-order relation on A × B. Note that ord(A × B; ≤∗) is β α, not αβ! Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Examples (1) 2! = ! Why? f1; 2; 3; · · · g × f0; 1g = f(1; 0); (1; 1); (2; 0); (2; 1); · · · g ≈ f1; 2; 3; · · · g (2) !2 = ! + ! Why? f0; 1g × f1; 2; 3; · · · g = f(0; 1); (0; 2); (0; 3); ··· ;(1; 1); (1; 2); (1; 3); · · · g ≈ f1; 3;; 5 ··· ; 2; 4; 6; · · · g Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Conclusion Theorem For any ordinal number α, 1 the set of ordinal numbers β such that β 4; 6= α fβ j β 4; 6= αg is a well-ordered set, and 2 α = ordfβ j β 4; 6= αg Can identify α ≡ fβ j β 4; 6= αg. Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Example 0 ≡ ; 1 ≡ f0g ··· k ≡ f0; 1; ··· ; k − 1g ··· ! ≡ f0; 1; 2; · · · g ∼ N ! + 1 ≡ f0; 1; 2; ··· ; !g ∼ N ! + 2 ≡ f0; 1; 2; ··· ; !; ! + 1g ∼ N ··· !2 ≡ f0; 1; 2; ··· ; !; ! + 1;! + 2; · · · g ∼ N !2 + 1 ≡ f0; 1; 2; ··· ; !; ! + 1;! + 2; ··· ; !2g ∼ N ··· Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic Initial ordinal Recalling that α ≡ fβ j β 4; 6= αg, we consider the set N = fα j α ∼ Ng: The fact is (N ; 4) is a well-ordered set. By the definition of well-order relation, N has the least element, say α0 2 N , and hence α0 ∼ N. The element α0 is called the initial ordinal for N. In fact, α0 = !. Ordinal numbers and Ordinal arithmetic.
Recommended publications
  • Math. Res. Lett. 20 (2013), No. 6, 1071–1080 the ISOMORPHISM
    Math. Res. Lett. 20 (2013), no. 6, 1071–1080 c International Press 2013 THE ISOMORPHISM RELATION FOR SEPARABLE C*-ALGEBRAS George A. Elliott, Ilijas Farah, Vern I. Paulsen, Christian Rosendal, Andrew S. Toms and Asger Tornquist¨ Abstract. We prove that the isomorphism relation for separable C∗-algebras, the rela- tions of complete and n-isometry for operator spaces, and the relations of unital n-order isomorphisms of operator systems, are Borel reducible to the orbit equivalence relation of a Polish group action on a standard Borel space. 1. Introduction The problem of classifying a collection of objects up to some notion of isomorphism can usually be couched as the study of an analytic equivalence relation on a standard Borel space parametrizing the objects in question. Such relations admit a notion of comparison, Borel reducibility, which allows one to assign a degree of complexity to the classification problem. If X and Y are standard Borel spaces admitting equivalence relations E and F respectively then we say that E is Borel reducible to F , written E ≤B F ,ifthereisaBorelmapΘ:X → Y such that xEy ⇐⇒ Θ(x)F Θ(y). In other words, Θ carries equivalence classes to equivalence classes injectively. We view E as being “less complicated” than F . There are some particularly prominent degrees of complexity in this theory which serve as benchmarks for classification problems in general. For instance, a relation E is classifiable by countable structures (CCS) if it is Borel reducible to the isomorphism relation for countable graphs. Classification problems in functional analysis (our interest here) tend not to be CCS, but may nevertheless be “not too complicated” in that they are Borel reducible to the orbit equivalence relation of a Borel action of a Polish group on a standard Borel space; this property is known as being below a group action.
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Concepts of Linear Order
    Basic Concepts of Linear Order Combinatorics for Computer Science (Unit 1) S. Gill Williamson ©S. Gill Williamson 2012 Preface From 1970 to 1990 I ran a graduate seminar on algebraic and algorithmic com- binatorics in the Department of Mathematics, UCSD. From 1972 to 1990 al- gorithmic combinatorics became the principal topic. The seminar notes from 1970 to 1985 were combined and published as a book, Combinatorics for Com- puter Science (CCS), published by Computer Science Press. Each of the "units of study" from the seminar became a chapter in this book. My general goal is to re-create the original presentation of these (largely inde- pendent) units in a form that is convenient for individual selection and study. Here, we isolate Unit 1, corresponding to Chapter 1 of CCS, and reconstruct the original very helpful unit specific index associated with this unit. Theorems, figures, examples, etc., are numbered sequentially: EXERCISE 1.38 and FIGURE 1.62 refer to numbered items 38 and 62 of Unit 1 (or Chap- ter 1 in CCS), etc. CCS contains an extensive bibliography for work prior to 1985. For further references and ongoing research, search the Web, particularly Wikipedia and the mathematics arXiv (arXiv.org). These notes focus on the visualization of algorithms through the use of graph- ical and pictorial methods. This approach is both fun and powerful, preparing you to invent your own algorithms for a wide range of problems. S. Gill Williamson, 2012 http : nwww:cse:ucsd:edun ∼ gill iii iv Table of Contents for Unit 1 Descriptive tools from set theory..............................................................3 relations, equivalence relations, set partitions, image, coimage surjection, injection, bijection, covering relations, Hasse diagrams, exercises and ex- amples.
    [Show full text]
  • Every Linear Order Isomorphic to Its Cube Is Isomorphic to Its Square
    EVERY LINEAR ORDER ISOMORPHIC TO ITS CUBE IS ISOMORPHIC TO ITS SQUARE GARRETT ERVIN Abstract. In 1958, Sierpi´nskiasked whether there exists a linear order X that is isomorphic to its lexicographically ordered cube but is not isomorphic to its square. The main result of this paper is that the answer is negative. More generally, if X is isomorphic to any one of its finite powers Xn, n > 1, it is isomorphic to all of them. 1. Introduction Suppose that (C; ×) is a class of structures equipped with a product. In many cases it is possible to find an infinite structure X 2 C that is isomorphic to its own square. If X2 =∼ X, then by multiplying again we have X3 =∼ X. Determining whether the converse holds for a given class C, that is, whether X3 =∼ X implies X2 =∼ X for all X 2 C, is called the cube problem for C. If the cube problem for C has a positive answer, then C is said to have the cube property. The cube problem is related to three other basic problems concerning the mul- tiplication of structures in a given class (C; ×). 1. Does A × Y =∼ X and B × X =∼ Y imply X =∼ Y for all A; B; X; Y 2 C? Equivalently, does A × B × X =∼ X imply B × X =∼ X for all A; B; X 2 C? 2. Does X2 =∼ Y 2 imply X =∼ Y for all X; Y 2 C? 3. Does A × Y =∼ X and A × X =∼ Y imply X =∼ Y for all A; X; Y 2 C? Equivalently, does A2 × X =∼ X imply A × X =∼ X for all A; X 2 C? The first question is called the Schroeder-Bernstein problem for C, and if it has a positive answer, then C is said to have the Schroeder-Bernstein property.
    [Show full text]
  • Decomposition of an Order Isomorphism Between Matrix-Ordered Hilbert Spaces
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 132, Number 7, Pages 1973{1977 S 0002-9939(04)07454-4 Article electronically published on February 6, 2004 DECOMPOSITION OF AN ORDER ISOMORPHISM BETWEEN MATRIX-ORDERED HILBERT SPACES YASUHIDE MIURA (Communicated by David R. Larson) Abstract. The purpose of this note is to show that any order isomorphism between noncommutative L2-spaces associated with von Neumann algebras is decomposed into a sum of a completely positive map and a completely co- positive map. The result is an L2 version of a theorem of Kadison for a Jordan isomorphism on operator algebras. 1. Introduction In the theory of operator algebras, a notion of self-dual cones was studied by A. Connes [1], and he characterized a standard Hilbert space. In [9] L. M. Schmitt and G. Wittstock introduced a matrix-ordered Hilbert space to handle a non- commutative order and characterized it using the face property of the family of self-dual cones. From the point of view of the complete positivity of the maps, we shall consider a decomposition theorem of an order isomorphism on matrix-ordered Hilbert spaces. Let H be a Hilbert space over a complex number field C,andletH+ be a self- dual cone in H.Asetofalln × n matrices is denoted by Mn.PutHn = H⊗Mn(= H 2 N H H+ 2 N H~ H~ 2 N Mn( )) for n . Suppose that ( , n ;n )and( , n, n )arematrix- ordered Hilbert spaces. A linear map A of H into H~ is said to be n-positive (resp. ⊗ H+ ⊂ H~+ n-co-positive) when the multiplicity map An(= A idn)satisfiesAn n n t H+ ⊂ H~+ t · (resp.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1702.04163V3 [Math.LO]
    The Euclidean numbers Vieri Benci Lorenzo Bresolin Dipartimento di Matematica Scuola Normale Superiore, Pisa Universit`adi Pisa, Italy. [email protected] [email protected] Marco Forti Dipartimento di Matematica Universit`adi Pisa, Italy. [email protected] Abstract We introduce axiomatically a Nonarchimedean field E, called the field of the Euclidean numbers, where a transfinite sum indicized by ordinal numbers less than the first inaccessible Ω is defined. Thanks to this sum, E becomes a saturated hyperreal field isomorphic to the so called Keisler field of cardinality Ω, and there is a natural isomorphic embedding into E of the semiring Ω equipped by the natural ordinal sum and product. Moreover a notion of limit is introduced so as to obtain that transfinite sums be limits of suitable Ω-sequences of their finite subsums. Finally a notion of numerosity satisfying all Euclidean common notions is given, whose values are nonnegative nonstandard integers of E. Then E can be charachterized as the hyperreal field generated by the real numbers together with the semiring of numerosities (and this explains the name “Euclidean” numbers). Keywords: Nonstandard Analysis, Nonarchimedean fields, Euclidean numerosi- ties MSC[2010]: 26E35, 03H05, 03C20, 03E65, 12L99 arXiv:1702.04163v3 [math.LO] 27 Jun 2020 Introduction In this paper we introduce a numeric field denoted by E, which we name the field of the Euclidean numbers. The theory of the Euclidean numbers combines the Cantorian theory of ordinal numbers with Non Standard Analysis (NSA). From the algebraic point of view, the Eucliean numbers are a non-Archimedean field with a supplementary structure (the Euclidean structure), which charac- terizes it.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 8 Ordered Sets
    Chapter VIII Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Transfinite Methods 1. Introduction In this chapter, we will look at certain kinds of ordered sets. If a set \ is ordered in a reasonable way, then there is a natural way to define an “order topology” on \. Most interesting (for our purposes) will be ordered sets that satisfy a very strong ordering condition: that every nonempty subset contains a smallest element. Such sets are called well-ordered. The most familiar example of a well-ordered set is and it is the well-ordering property that lets us do mathematical induction in In this chapter we will see “longer” well ordered sets and these will give us a new proof method called “transfinite induction.” But we begin with something simpler. 2. Partially Ordered Sets Recall that a relation V\ on a set is a subset of \‚\ (see Definition I.5.2 ). If ÐBßCÑ−V, we write BVCÞ An “order” on a set \ is refers to a relation on \ that satisfies some additional conditions. Order relations are usually denoted by symbols such asŸ¡ß£ , , or . Definition 2.1 A relation V\ on is called: transitive ifÀ a +ß ,ß - − \ Ð+V, and ,V-Ñ Ê +V-Þ reflexive ifÀa+−\+V+ antisymmetric ifÀ a +ß , − \ Ð+V, and ,V+ Ñ Ê Ð+ œ ,Ñ symmetric ifÀ a +ß , − \ +V, Í ,V+ (that is, the set V is “symmetric” with respect to thediagonal ? œÖÐBßBÑÀB−\ש\‚\). Example 2.2 1) The relation “œ\ ” on a set is transitive, reflexive, symmetric, and antisymmetric. Viewed as a subset of \‚\, the relation “ œ ” is the diagonal set ? œÖÐBßBÑÀB−\×Þ 2) In ‘, the usual order relation is transitive and antisymmetric, but not reflexive or symmetric.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Set Theory
    AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY Professor William A. R. Weiss November 21, 2014 2 Contents 0 Introduction 7 1 LOST 11 2 FOUND 23 3 The Axioms of Set Theory 29 4 The Natural Numbers 37 5 The Ordinal Numbers 47 6 Relations and Orderings 59 7 Cardinality 69 8 What's So Real About The Real Numbers? 79 9 Ultrafilters Are Useful 87 3 4 CONTENTS 10 The Universe 97 11 Reflection 103 12 Elementary Submodels 123 13 Constructibility 139 14 Appendices 155 .1 The Axioms of ZFC . 155 .2 Tentative Axioms . 156 CONTENTS 5 Preface These notes for a graduate course in set theory are on their way to be- coming a book. They originated as handwritten notes in a course at the University of Toronto given by Prof. William Weiss. Cynthia Church pro- duced the first electronic copy in December 2002. James Talmage Adams produced a major revision in February 2005. The manuscript has seen many changes since then, often due to generous comments by students, each of whom I here thank. Chapters 1 to 11 are now close to final form. Chapters 12 and 13 are quite readable, but should not be considered as a final draft. One more chapter will be added. 6 CONTENTS Chapter 0 Introduction Set Theory is the true study of infinity. This alone assures the subject of a place prominent in human culture. But even more, Set Theory is the milieu in which mathematics takes place today. As such, it is expected to provide a firm foundation for all the rest of mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Category of Cofinal Types. I 387
    THE CATEGORYOF COFINAL TYPES. I BY SEYMOUR GINSBURG AND J. R. ISBELL I.1) Introduction. Briefly, this paper introduces a category S£ which we call the category of cofinal types. We construct a concrete representation Sfi of So, and we determine explicitly the part of Sfi corresponding to the cofinal types of bases of open sets in regular topological spaces. These types have a privileged position in^, and we call them canonical types. Succeeding papers in this series will develop further machinery, particularly for the cofinal types of directed sets. The interest of the results depends heavily on the appropriateness of our definitions of convergent functions and equivalence of convergent functions between partially ordered sets (see below, before and after 1.1). In directed sets, a function f: P—>Q is convergent if and only if it takes every cofinal subset to a cofinal subset; in general, P and Q may have branching structure which / must respect. Equivalence of the convergent functions /: P —>Q and g:P—>Q means, except for some trivialities, that every function AC/Ug (i.e., every value h(p) is f{p) or gip)) is convergent. The relation gives us a quotient Sf of the category of all partially ordered sets and convergent functions. Two objects of SS/ become isomorphic in ^if and only if they are cofinally similar. We adapt a construction F from [2] to make several functors F, F°, F* on W such that the quotient category is So. F* induces a dual embedding of So in the category 96* of all complete Boolean algebras and complete homomor- phisms, and a duality between 96* and the full subcategory of canonical types in if.
    [Show full text]
  • Order Isomorphisms of Complete Order-Unit Spaces Cormac Walsh
    Order isomorphisms of complete order-unit spaces Cormac Walsh To cite this version: Cormac Walsh. Order isomorphisms of complete order-unit spaces. 2019. hal-02425988 HAL Id: hal-02425988 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02425988 Preprint submitted on 31 Dec 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. ORDER ISOMORPHISMS OF COMPLETE ORDER-UNIT SPACES CORMAC WALSH Abstract. We investigate order isomorphisms, which are not assumed to be linear, between complete order unit spaces. We show that two such spaces are order isomor- phic if and only if they are linearly order isomorphic. We then introduce a condition which determines whether all order isomorphisms on a complete order unit space are automatically affine. This characterisation is in terms of the geometry of the state space. We consider how this condition applies to several examples, including the space of bounded self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space. Our techniques also allow us to show that in a unital C∗-algebra there is an order isomorphism between the space of self-adjoint elements and the cone of positive invertible elements if and only if the algebra is commutative.
    [Show full text]
  • On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor's
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences CS 5 | 2005 Fonder autrement les mathématiques On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor’s theory of sets Christian Tapp Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/386 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.386 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 August 2005 Number of pages: 157-173 ISBN: 2-84174-372-1 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Christian Tapp, “On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor’s theory of sets”, Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], CS 5 | 2005, Online since 01 August 2008, connection on 15 January 2021. URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/386 ; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/ philosophiascientiae.386 Tous droits réservés On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor’s theory of sets∗ Christian Tapp Résumé : Georg Cantor a cherché à assurer les fondements de sa théorie des ensembles. Cet article présente les différentiations cantoriennes concernant la notion d’infinité et une perspective historique de l’émergence de sa notion d’ensemble. Abstract: Georg Cantor sought secure foundations for his set theory. This article presents an account of Cantor’s differentiations concerning the notion of infinity and a tentative historical parsepctive on his notion of set. ∗I am indebted to Joseph W. Dauben for his helpful advise. — Comments to the author are welcome. Philosophia Scientiæ, cahier spécial 5, 2005, 157–173. 158 Christian Tapp 1Introduction Historical accounts of the life and work of Georg Cantor (1845-1918) have generally focused chiefly on his mathematical creations, i.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordered Sets an Introduction
    Bernd S. W. Schröder Ordered Sets An Introduction Birkhäuser Boston • Basel • Berlin Bernd S. W. Schröder Program of Mathematics and Statistics Lousiana Tech University Ruston, LA 71272 U.S.A. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Schröder, Bernd S. W. (Bernd Siegfried Walter), 1966- Ordered sets : an introduction / Bernd S. W. Schröder. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-8176-4128-9 (acid-free paper) – ISBN 3-7643-4128-9 (acid-free paper) 1. Ordered sets. I. Title. QA171.48.S47 2002 511.3'2–dc21 2002018231 CIP AMS Subject Classifications: 06-01, 06-02 Printed on acid-free paper. ® ©2003 Birkhäuser Boston Birkhäuser All rights reserved. This work may not be translated or copied in whole or in part without the written permission of the publisher (Birkhäuser Boston, c/o Springer-Verlag New York, Inc., 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010, USA), except for brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis. Use in connection with any form of information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed is forbidden. The use of general descriptive names, trade names, trademarks, etc., in this publication, even if the former are not especially identified, is not to be taken as a sign that such names, as understood by the Trade Marks and Merchandise Marks Act, may accordingly be used freely by anyone. ISBN 0-8176-4128-9 SPIN 10721218 ISBN 3-7643-4128-9 Typeset by the author. Printed in the United States of America. 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Birkhäuser Boston • Basel • Berlin A member of BertelsmannSpringer Science+Business Media GmbH Contents Table of Contents .
    [Show full text]
  • Order-Isomorphism and a Projection's Diagram of C(X)
    Turk J Math 34 (2010) , 523 – 536. c TUB¨ ITAK˙ doi:10.3906/mat-0812-9 Order-isomorphism and a projection’s diagram of C(X) Ahmed S. Al-Rawashdeh and Sultan M. Al-Suleiman Abstract A mapping between projections of C∗ -algebras preserving the orthogonality, is called an orthoisomor- phism. We define the order-isomorphism mapping on C∗ -algebras, and using Dye’s result, we prove in the case of commutative unital C∗ -algebras that the concepts; order-isomorphism and the orthoisomorphism coincide. Also, we define the equipotence relation on the projections of C(X); indeed, new concepts of finiteness are introduced. The classes of projections are represented by constructing a special diagram, we study the relation between the diagram and the topological space X . We prove that an order-isomorphism, which preserves the equipotence of projections, induces a diagram-isomorphism; also if two diagrams are isomorphic, then the C∗ -algebras are isomorphic. Key Words: Commutative C∗ -algebras; projections order-isomorphism; infinite projections; clopen sub- sets. 1. Introduction The algebra of continuous complex-valued functions on a compact Hausdorff space X , denoted by C(X), is a commutative unital C∗ -algebra. Let us recall the following main theorem, known as the Gelfand-Naimark Theorem. Theorem 1.1 [8] Every commutative, unital C∗ -algebra A is isometrically ∗-isomorphic to C(A),whereA is the compact Hausdorff space of characters of A. Let P(A) denote the set of projections of A. A projection p ∈P(A) is said to be minimal if 0 is the only proper subprojection of p.
    [Show full text]