Ordinal Arithmetic
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Even Ordinals and the Kunen Inconsistency∗
Even ordinals and the Kunen inconsistency∗ Gabriel Goldberg Evans Hall University Drive Berkeley, CA 94720 July 23, 2021 Abstract This paper contributes to the theory of large cardinals beyond the Kunen inconsistency, or choiceless large cardinal axioms, in the context where the Axiom of Choice is not assumed. The first part of the paper investigates a periodicity phenomenon: assuming choiceless large cardinal axioms, the properties of the cumulative hierarchy turn out to alternate between even and odd ranks. The second part of the paper explores the structure of ultrafilters under choiceless large cardinal axioms, exploiting the fact that these axioms imply a weak form of the author's Ultrapower Axiom [1]. The third and final part of the paper examines the consistency strength of choiceless large cardinals, including a proof that assuming DC, the existence of an elementary embedding j : Vλ+3 ! Vλ+3 implies the consistency of ZFC + I0. embedding j : Vλ+3 ! Vλ+3 implies that every subset of Vλ+1 has a sharp. We show that the existence of an elementary embedding from Vλ+2 to Vλ+2 is equiconsistent with the existence of an elementary embedding from L(Vλ+2) to L(Vλ+2) with critical point below λ. We show that assuming DC, the existence of an elementary embedding j : Vλ+3 ! Vλ+3 implies the consistency of ZFC + I0. By a recent result of Schlutzenberg [2], an elementary embedding from Vλ+2 to Vλ+2 does not suffice. 1 Introduction Assuming the Axiom of Choice, the large cardinal hierarchy comes to an abrupt halt in the vicinity of an !-huge cardinal. -
Handout from Today's Lecture
MA532 Lecture Timothy Kohl Boston University April 23, 2020 Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 1 / 26 Cardinal Arithmetic Recall that one may define addition and multiplication of ordinals α = ot(A, A) β = ot(B, B ) α + β and α · β by constructing order relations on A ∪ B and B × A. For cardinal numbers the foundations are somewhat similar, but also somewhat simpler since one need not refer to orderings. Definition For sets A, B where |A| = α and |B| = β then α + β = |(A × {0}) ∪ (B × {1})|. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 2 / 26 The curious part of the definition is the two sets A × {0} and B × {1} which can be viewed as subsets of the direct product (A ∪ B) × {0, 1} which basically allows us to add |A| and |B|, in particular since, in the usual formula for the size of the union of two sets |A ∪ B| = |A| + |B| − |A ∩ B| which in this case is bypassed since, by construction, (A × {0}) ∩ (B × {1})= ∅ regardless of the nature of A ∩ B. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 3 / 26 Definition For sets A, B where |A| = α and |B| = β then α · β = |A × B|. One immediate consequence of these definitions is the following. Proposition If m, n are finite ordinals, then as cardinals one has |m| + |n| = |m + n|, (where the addition on the right is ordinal addition in ω) meaning that ordinal addition and cardinal addition agree. Proof. The simplest proof of this is to define a bijection f : (m × {0}) ∪ (n × {1}) → m + n by f (hr, 0i)= r for r ∈ m and f (hs, 1i)= m + s for s ∈ n. -
Well-Orderings, Ordinals and Well-Founded Relations. an Ancient
Well-orderings, ordinals and well-founded relations. An ancient principle of arithmetic, that if there is a non-negative integer with some property then there is a least such, is useful in two ways: as a source of proofs, which are then said to be \by induction" and as as a source of definitions, then said to be \by recursion." An early use of induction is in Euclid's proof that every integer > 2 is a product of primes, (where we take \prime" to mean \having no divisors other than itself and 1"): if some number is not, then let n¯ be the least counter-example. If not itself prime, it can be written as a product m1m2 of two strictly smaller numbers each > 2; but then each of those is a product of primes, by the minimality of n¯; putting those two products together expresses n¯ as a product of primes. Contradiction ! An example of definition by recursion: we set 0! = 1; (n + 1)! = n! × (n + 1): A function defined for all non-negative integers is thereby uniquely specified; in detail, we consider an attempt to be a function, defined on a finite initial segment of the non-negative integers, which agrees with the given definition as far as it goes; if some integer is not in the domain of any attempt, there will be a least such; it cannot be 0; if it is n + 1, the recursion equation tells us how to extend an attempt defined at n to one defined at n + 1. So no such failure exists; we check that if f and g are two attempts and both f(n) and g(n) are defined, then f(n) = g(n), by considering the least n where that might fail, and again reaching a contradiction; and so, there being no disagreement between any two attempts, the union of all attempts will be a well-defined function, which is familiar to us as the factorial function. -
The Set of All Countable Ordinals: an Inquiry Into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness
W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2009 The Set of All Countable Ordinals: An Inquiry into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness Jacob Hill College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Hill, Jacob, "The Set of All Countable Ordinals: An Inquiry into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness" (2009). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 255. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/255 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Set of All Countable Ordinals: An Inquiry into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Science with Honors in Mathematics from the College of William and Mary in Virginia, by Jacob Hill Accepted for ____________________________ (Honors, High Honors, or Highest Honors) _______________________________________ Director, Professor David Lutzer _________________________________________ Professor Vladimir Bolotnikov _________________________________________ Professor George Rublein _________________________________________ -
A Translation Of" Die Normalfunktionen Und Das Problem
1 Normal Functions and the Problem of the Distinguished Sequences of Ordinal Numbers A Translation of “Die Normalfunktionen und das Problem der ausgezeichneten Folgen von Ordnungszahlen” by Heinz Bachmann Vierteljahrsschrift der Naturforschenden Gesellschaft in Zurich (www.ngzh.ch) 1950(2), 115–147, MR 0036806 www.ngzh.ch/archiv/1950 95/95 2/95 14.pdf Translator’s note: Translated by Martin Dowd, with the assistance of Google translate, translate.google.com. Permission to post this translation has been granted by the editors of the journal. A typographical error in the original has been corrected, § 1 Introduction 1. In this essay we always move within the theory of Cantor’s ordinal numbers. We use the following notation: 1) Subtraction of ordinal numbers: If x and y are ordinals with y ≤ x, let x − y be the ordinal one gets by subtracting y from the front of x, so that y +(x − y)= x . 2) Multiplication of ordinals: For any ordinal numbers x and y the product x · y equals x added to itself y times. 3) The numbering of the number classes: The natural numbers including zero form the first number class, the countably infinite order types the second number class, etc.; for k ≥ 2 Ωk−2 is the initial ordinal of the kth number class. We also use the usual designations arXiv:1903.04609v1 [math.LO] 8 Mar 2019 ω0 = ω ω1 = Ω 4) The operation of the limit formation: Given a set of ordinal numbers, the smallest ordinal number x, for which y ≤ x for all ordinal numbers y of this set, is the limit of this set of ordinals. -
Transfinite Induction
Transfinite Induction G. Eric Moorhouse, University of Wyoming Notes for ACNT Seminar, 20 Jan 2009 Abstract Let X ⊂ R3 be the complement of a single point. We prove, by transfinite induction, that X can be partitioned into lines. This result is intended as an introduction to transfinite induction. 1 Cardinality Let A and B be sets. We write |A| = |B| (in words, A and B have the same cardinality) if there exists a bijection A → B; |A| à |B| if there exists an injection (a one-to-one map) A → B; |A| < |B| if |A| à |B| but there is no bijection from A to B. The Cantor-Bernstein-Schroeder Theorem asserts that if |A| à |B| and |B| à |A|, then |A| = |B|. (The proof is elementary but requires some thought.) So we may reasonably speak of the cardinality of a set, as a measure of its size, and compare any two sets according to their cardinalities. The cardinality of Z is denoted ℵ0. Every set A having |A| à ℵ0 is called countable; in this case either A is finite, or |A|=ℵ0 (countably infinite). Examples of countably infinite sets include {positive integers},2Z ={even integers}, and Q. Cantor showed that R is uncountable; we denote |R| = 2ℵ0. This cardinality, which we call the cardinality of the continuum, strictly exceeds ℵ0; it is also the cardinality of Rn for every positive integer n. In this context it is almost obligatory to mention the Continuum Hypothe- ℵ sis (CH), which is the assertion that there is no set A satisfying ℵ0 < |A| < 2 0. -
Arxiv:1702.04163V3 [Math.LO]
The Euclidean numbers Vieri Benci Lorenzo Bresolin Dipartimento di Matematica Scuola Normale Superiore, Pisa Universit`adi Pisa, Italy. [email protected] [email protected] Marco Forti Dipartimento di Matematica Universit`adi Pisa, Italy. [email protected] Abstract We introduce axiomatically a Nonarchimedean field E, called the field of the Euclidean numbers, where a transfinite sum indicized by ordinal numbers less than the first inaccessible Ω is defined. Thanks to this sum, E becomes a saturated hyperreal field isomorphic to the so called Keisler field of cardinality Ω, and there is a natural isomorphic embedding into E of the semiring Ω equipped by the natural ordinal sum and product. Moreover a notion of limit is introduced so as to obtain that transfinite sums be limits of suitable Ω-sequences of their finite subsums. Finally a notion of numerosity satisfying all Euclidean common notions is given, whose values are nonnegative nonstandard integers of E. Then E can be charachterized as the hyperreal field generated by the real numbers together with the semiring of numerosities (and this explains the name “Euclidean” numbers). Keywords: Nonstandard Analysis, Nonarchimedean fields, Euclidean numerosi- ties MSC[2010]: 26E35, 03H05, 03C20, 03E65, 12L99 arXiv:1702.04163v3 [math.LO] 27 Jun 2020 Introduction In this paper we introduce a numeric field denoted by E, which we name the field of the Euclidean numbers. The theory of the Euclidean numbers combines the Cantorian theory of ordinal numbers with Non Standard Analysis (NSA). From the algebraic point of view, the Eucliean numbers are a non-Archimedean field with a supplementary structure (the Euclidean structure), which charac- terizes it. -
On the Necessary Use of Abstract Set Theory
ADVANCES IN MATHEMATICS 41, 209-280 (1981) On the Necessary Use of Abstract Set Theory HARVEY FRIEDMAN* Department of Mathematics, Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 43210 In this paper we present some independence results from the Zermelo-Frankel axioms of set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC) which differ from earlier such independence results in three major respects. Firstly, these new propositions that are shown to be independent of ZFC (i.e., neither provable nor refutable from ZFC) form mathematically natural assertions about Bore1 functions of several variables from the Hilbert cube I” into the unit interval, or back into the Hilbert cube. As such, they are of a level of abstraction significantly below that of the earlier independence results. Secondly, these propositions are not only independent of ZFC, but also of ZFC together with the axiom of constructibility (V = L). The only earlier examples of intelligible statements independent of ZFC + V= L either express properties of formal systems such as ZFC (e.g., the consistency of ZFC), or assert the existence of very large cardinalities (e.g., inaccessible cardinals). The great bulk of independence results from ZFCLthe ones that involve standard mathematical concepts and constructions-are about sets of limited cardinality (most commonly, that of at most the continuum), and are obtained using the forcing method introduced by Paul J. Cohen (see [2]). It is now known in virtually every such case, that these independence results are eliminated if V= L is added to ZFC. Finally, some of our propositions can be proved in the theory of classes, as formalized by the Morse-Kelley class theory with the axiom of choice for sets (MKC), but not in ZFC. -
Ordinal Rankings on Measures Annihilating Thin Sets
TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 310, Number 2, December 1988 ORDINAL RANKINGS ON MEASURES ANNIHILATING THIN SETS ALEXANDER S. KECHRIS AND RUSSELL LYONS ABSTRACT. We assign a countable ordinal number to each probability mea- sure which annihilates all H-sets. The descriptive-set theoretic structure of this assignment allows us to show that this class of measures is coanalytic non-Borel. In addition, it allows us to quantify the failure of Rajchman's con- jecture. Similar results are obtained for measures annihilating Dirichlet sets. A closet subset E of the unit circle T = R/Z is called an H-set if there exists a sequence {n^} of positive integers tending to oo and an interval (i.e., a nonempty open arc) 7 C T such that for all k and all x € E, n^x ^ I. These sets play a fundamental role as examples of sets of uniqueness for trigonometric series [KL; Z, Chapters IX, XII]. A (Borel) probability measure fj, on T is called a Rajchman measure if fi(n) —*0 as \n\ —>oo, where jx(n) = fTe(—nx)dn(x), e(x) = e2wix. We denote by R the class of such measures. These measures have also been very important to the study of sets of uniqueness. In particular, every Rajchman measure annihilates every set of uniqueness, hence every H-set. After establishing these relationships [Rl, R2], Rajchman conjectured that, in fact, the only measures which annihilate all //"-sets are those in R. This, however, is false [LI, L2, L3, L5]. Here, we shall quantify how distant Rajchman's conjecture is from the truth. -
SET THEORY for CATEGORY THEORY 3 the Category Is Well-Powered, Meaning That Each Object Has Only a Set of Iso- Morphism Classes of Subobjects
SET THEORY FOR CATEGORY THEORY MICHAEL A. SHULMAN Abstract. Questions of set-theoretic size play an essential role in category theory, especially the distinction between sets and proper classes (or small sets and large sets). There are many different ways to formalize this, and which choice is made can have noticeable effects on what categorical constructions are permissible. In this expository paper we summarize and compare a num- ber of such “set-theoretic foundations for category theory,” and describe their implications for the everyday use of category theory. We assume the reader has some basic knowledge of category theory, but little or no prior experience with formal logic or set theory. 1. Introduction Since its earliest days, category theory has had to deal with set-theoretic ques- tions. This is because unlike in most fields of mathematics outside of set theory, questions of size play an essential role in category theory. A good example is Freyd’s Special Adjoint Functor Theorem: a functor from a complete, locally small, and well-powered category with a cogenerating set to a locally small category has a left adjoint if and only if it preserves small limits. This is always one of the first results I quote when people ask me “are there any real theorems in category theory?” So it is all the more striking that it involves in an essential way notions like ‘locally small’, ‘small limits’, and ‘cogenerating set’ which refer explicitly to the difference between sets and proper classes (or between small sets and large sets). Despite this, in my experience there is a certain amount of confusion among users and students of category theory about its foundations, and in particular about what constructions on large categories are or are not possible. -
An Introduction to Set Theory
AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY Professor William A. R. Weiss November 21, 2014 2 Contents 0 Introduction 7 1 LOST 11 2 FOUND 23 3 The Axioms of Set Theory 29 4 The Natural Numbers 37 5 The Ordinal Numbers 47 6 Relations and Orderings 59 7 Cardinality 69 8 What's So Real About The Real Numbers? 79 9 Ultrafilters Are Useful 87 3 4 CONTENTS 10 The Universe 97 11 Reflection 103 12 Elementary Submodels 123 13 Constructibility 139 14 Appendices 155 .1 The Axioms of ZFC . 155 .2 Tentative Axioms . 156 CONTENTS 5 Preface These notes for a graduate course in set theory are on their way to be- coming a book. They originated as handwritten notes in a course at the University of Toronto given by Prof. William Weiss. Cynthia Church pro- duced the first electronic copy in December 2002. James Talmage Adams produced a major revision in February 2005. The manuscript has seen many changes since then, often due to generous comments by students, each of whom I here thank. Chapters 1 to 11 are now close to final form. Chapters 12 and 13 are quite readable, but should not be considered as a final draft. One more chapter will be added. 6 CONTENTS Chapter 0 Introduction Set Theory is the true study of infinity. This alone assures the subject of a place prominent in human culture. But even more, Set Theory is the milieu in which mathematics takes place today. As such, it is expected to provide a firm foundation for all the rest of mathematics. -
On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor's
Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences CS 5 | 2005 Fonder autrement les mathématiques On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor’s theory of sets Christian Tapp Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/386 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.386 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 August 2005 Number of pages: 157-173 ISBN: 2-84174-372-1 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Christian Tapp, “On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor’s theory of sets”, Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], CS 5 | 2005, Online since 01 August 2008, connection on 15 January 2021. URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/386 ; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/ philosophiascientiae.386 Tous droits réservés On Some Philosophical Aspects of the Background to Georg Cantor’s theory of sets∗ Christian Tapp Résumé : Georg Cantor a cherché à assurer les fondements de sa théorie des ensembles. Cet article présente les différentiations cantoriennes concernant la notion d’infinité et une perspective historique de l’émergence de sa notion d’ensemble. Abstract: Georg Cantor sought secure foundations for his set theory. This article presents an account of Cantor’s differentiations concerning the notion of infinity and a tentative historical parsepctive on his notion of set. ∗I am indebted to Joseph W. Dauben for his helpful advise. — Comments to the author are welcome. Philosophia Scientiæ, cahier spécial 5, 2005, 157–173. 158 Christian Tapp 1Introduction Historical accounts of the life and work of Georg Cantor (1845-1918) have generally focused chiefly on his mathematical creations, i.