Consequentialism with Wrongness Depending on the Difficulty of Doing Better

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Consequentialism with Wrongness Depending on the Difficulty of Doing Better This is a repository copy of Consequentialism with Wrongness Depending on the Difficulty of Doing Better. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/103082/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Gustafsson, Johan orcid.org/0000-0002-9618-577X (2016) Consequentialism with Wrongness Depending on the Difficulty of Doing Better. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy. 108–118. ISSN 2161-2234 https://doi.org/10.1002/tht3.200 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ [This is the pre-peer-reviewed version of the following article ‘Consequentialism with Wrongness Depending on the Difficulty of Doing Better’ Thought ¢ (ó): Õþ–ÕÕ, óþÕä.] Consequentialism with Wrongness Depending on the Difficulty of Doing Better Johan E. Gustafsson∗ Moral wrongness comes in degrees. On a consequentialist view of ethics, the wrong- ness of an act should depend, I argue, in part on how much worse the act’s conse- quences are compared to those of its alternatives and in part on how difficult it is to perform the alternatives with better consequences. I extend act consequentialism to take this into account, and I defend three conditions on consequentialist theories. The first is consequentialist dominance, which says that, if an act has better conse- quences than some alternative act, then it is not more wrong than the alternative act. The second is consequentialist supervenience, which says that, if two acts have equally good consequences in a situation, then they have the same deontic status in the situation. And the third is consequentialist continuity, which says that, for every act and for any difference in wrongness δ greater than zero, there is an arbitrarily small improvement of the consequences of the act which would, other things being equal, not change the wrongness of that act or any alternative by more than δ.I defend a proposal that satisfies these conditions. Traditional consequentialism states that an act is right if and only if its conse- quences are at least as good as those of every alternative act and, if the act is not right, it is wrong. The wrong acts, however, might differ in ways that could be morally relevant. The consequences of one of them might be almost optimal while those of another are catastrophic in comparison. In addition to value dif- ference, a further intuitively morally relevant difference between different wrong acts is how hard it would have been to avoid them—how hard it would have ∗ I would be grateful for any comments on this paper, which can be sent to me at [email protected]. ±u oh¶±í o fu±±u§ ó been to perform a better act instead.Ö In this study, I shall defend an extended version of consequentialism that is capable of taking these kinds of differences into account for a more fine grained grading of the wrongness of acts. It is natural to assume that consequentialism can account for degrees of wrongness by taking into account how much worse the consequences of a wrong act are than those [p. ÕþÉ] of the right acts.ô Consider a choice situation where there are three available alternatives with consequences valued as follows: Situation Õ Act Value aÔ Õþþ aò ÉÉ aç þ Here, it appears reasonable to say that aç is more wrong than aò, because the loss of value compared to the optimal alternative, aÔ, is greater for aç than for aò. Moreover, it seems that, aç is not just more wrong than aò, it is much more wrong than aò because the loss of value relative to aÔ is much greater for aç than for aò.í Ö If we grant the possibility of being passive and not performing any act in a choice situation, there might be a difference between how hard it is to avoid an act and how hard it is to perform an alternative act. For the purposes of this study, however, I shall count being passive in a choice situation as an act. ô See, for example, Mackie (ÕÉßß, p. óþ¢), Eriksson (ÕÉÉß, pp. óÕ–óÕÉ), and Calder (óþþ¢, p. óóÉ). Mill’s (ÕÉäÉ, p. óÕþ) proportionality criterion of wrongness, which says that acts are wrong ‘as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness’, might be read as suggesting a similar view. í The main theoretical interest in such cardinal information about how much more wrong an act is compared to another act (rather than merely ordinal information about whether it is more wrong than the other act) is that it affords a neat solution for dealing with the following kind of case—first discussed by Regan (ÕÉþ, p. óä¢)—where two states of nature are equally likely: Act State Õ (ý. ) State ó (ý. ) aÔ Very minor wrong Very minor wrong aò Major wrong Right aç Right Major wrong In this case, it seems that a morally conscientious person would choose aÔ, which is known to be slightly wrong, rather than one of aò and aç, each of which might be right but they both have a ý. chance of being very wrong. However, if aÔ were instead known to be almost as wrong as aò and aç are in states Õ and ó respectively, it appears that a morally conscientious person would instead choose one of aò and aç. Hence it appears that morally conscientious people are not just concerned with avoiding wrong acts; their concern with avoiding wrong acts is proportional to the acts’ degrees of wrongness; see Graham (óþÕþ, p. ÉÉ) and Bykvist (óþÕÕ, p. ìß). A natural way of spelling this out is that morally conscientious people act as to minimize expected moral wrongness, and that requires cardinal rather than merely ordinal degrees of wrongness. ±u oh¶±í o fu±±u§ ì We introduce the following notation: W(x) is the degree of wrongness of x. V(x) is the value of the consequences of x. Ω is the set of available alternatives. Given that each alternative might be performed without difficulty, the following appears plausible: (Õ) W(x) = max V(y) − V(x) T y ∈ Ω. In other words, one calculates the degree of wrongness of an alternative x by, for each alternative y, calculating the result of subtracting V(x) from V(y). According to equation (Õ), the greatest of these results is equal to the degree of wrongness of x. Given that all acts in situation Õ can be performed without difficulty, this yields that W(aç) = Ôýý and W(aò) = Ô. These results are, I think, in line with what one would expect from a consequentialist theory capable of han- dling degrees of wrongness. Another welcome feature is that the acts with optimal consequences—that is, the right acts according to traditional consequentialism— always get a zero degree of wrongness: In situation Õ, for instance, equation (Õ) yields that W(aÔ) = ý. In addition to value difference, the wrongness of an act might depend on the difficulty of the acts with better consequences. In the literature, there are various accounts of degrees of easiness and difficulty of acts.Ø I shall try to remain neutral between these accounts. I shall assume, however, that each act among your alternatives is securable in the sense that you cannot fail to perform the act you have chosen to perform. Hence the easiness of an act should not be thought Note that this is not the only formula that could account for the intuitions we have appealed to so far. Taking an act’s degree of wrongness to be proportional to the value difference between the act’s consequences and those of the right act (or acts) appears, however, to be the simplest, most straightforward way to do so. The aim of this paper is mainly to find one plausible account of degrees of wrongness depending on the difficulty of doing something better and not to show that it is the only plausible account of this kind. Compare Parfit (Õɦ, p. ìì), who suggest that if it is very hard to not act in a certain way, acting that way is only morally bad in a very weak sense. Moreover, compare Berlin (ÕÉ¢, p. Õ¢n) who suggests that the morally relevant sense of freedom depends not just on which possibilities are open to the agent but also on how easy or hard they are to achieve. Ø For an early account of degrees of ability, see Benson (ÕÉß, p. ìóÉ). Moreover, see Portmore (óþþß, p. Õþ) for a distinction between degree of difficulty and degree of effort, and Cohen (ÕÉß, pp. óì–óìÉ) for a distinction between difficulty and cost. ±u oh¶±í o fu±±u§ ¦ of as the probability of successfully performing the act given that you have chosen to perform it. Non-securable acts—such as, buying a winning lottery ticket—are better modelled as securable acts with an uncertain outcome—such as, buying a lottery ticket when one does not know whether the ticket is a winner.
Recommended publications
  • Research in Practical Philosophy
    Research in Practical Philosophy in Sweden: 1998 - 2008, appendix to Report of the International Panel for the Evaluationof Swedish Research in Philosophy to the Swedish Research Council Rabinowicz, Wlodek 2009 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Rabinowicz, W. (2009). Research in Practical Philosophy in Sweden: 1998 - 2008, appendix to Report of the International Panel for the Evaluationof Swedish Research in Philosophy to the Swedish Research Council. Swedish Research Council. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Wlodek Rabinowicz Research in Practical Philosophy in Sweden: 1998-2008 In this short summary, which is aimed to give a rough picture of the main lines of research in practical philosophy in Sweden during the last decade, I have decided to organize the presentation by universities rather than by particular research subjects.
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Practical Philosophy
    The Future of Practical Philosophy James Stacey Taylor James Stacey Taylor is an Assistant Professor of philosophy at Louisiana State University, USA. He has published numerous articles on the theory of autonomy, ethics, and applied ethics. He is the editor of Personal Autonomy: New essays (Cambridge University Press, 2005), and the author of Stakes and Kidneys: Why markets in human body parts are morally imperative (Ashgate Press, 2005). ABSTRACT Over the last two decades the practice of applied philosophy has undergone resurgence. It is now common for philosophers to sit on ethics committees in hospitals, or to provide ethical advice to businesses, and many universities and colleges now offer courses in practical philosophy. Despite this, practical philosophy is subject to increasing criticism, with persons charging that (1) it is philosophically shallow, and (2) it has little to offer persons grappling with concrete ethical problems, either because (a) its techniques or too removed from such problems, or (b) because ethical theory is too abstract. In this paper I develop responses to these criticisms, and offer suggestions as to how practical philosophy should be developed. Over the last two decades the practice of applied philosophy has undergone resurgence. It is now common for philosophers to sit on ethics committees in hospitals, or to provide ethical advice to businesses. Many universities and colleges now offer courses in practical philosophy, ranging from courses in bioethics and business ethics to more innovative courses, such as philosophy as conversation. Such courses frequently prove popular. The popularity of practical philosophy is reflected in the demand for people who can teach practical philosophy (especially applied ethics), with this section of the academic job market in philosophy currently being especially strong.1 And it is not only the practice and teaching of practical philosophy that is currently flourishing.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Practical Postulates and the Limits of the Critical System
    Kant’s Practical Postulates and the Limits of the Critical System Sebastian Gardner The topic that I wish to consider is the significance, both systematic and historical, for Kant’s system as a whole, of the postulates of pure practical reason, more specifically, of the two theological postulates concerning the existence of God and personal immortality which form the basis of Kant’s moral theology. My discussion will focus on the problems of Kant’s moral theology in the eyes of his early contemporaries, for whom it constituted a crux in Kant’s project. Different views were taken by Kant’s contemporaries of what exactly these problems signified regarding the future of Critical philosophy. For the thinkers I will be looking at here, the miscarriage of the moral theology constituted a fatal fault in the Kantian project. For the German Idealists, the moral theology instead provided a vital clue as to how the Kantian system could be transformed into a more radical idealism, while confirming that it needed to be. The role of the practical postulates in the development of German Idealism demands a separate treatment; what I will argue here is simply that the practical postulates do indeed represent a point at which Kant’s philosophical system displays a deep and interesting tension, in light of which both historical responses are prima facie intelligible. I. Kant on practical cognition Let me begin with some examples of Kant’s use, in connection with the moral theology and practical postulation, of the concept of practical cognition, praktische Erkenntnis. The following, key statements are taken from the second and third Critiques: [T]he concept of freedom, insofar as its reality is proved by an apodictic law of practical reason, constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason, even of speculative reason; and all other concepts (those of God and immortality) ..
    [Show full text]
  • Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals CAMBRIDGE TEXTS in the HISTORY of PHILOSOPHY
    CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IMMANUEL KANT Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Series editors KARL AMERIKS Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame DESMOND M. CLARKE Professor of Philosophy at University College Cork The main objective of Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy is to expand the range, variety and quality of texts in the history of philosophy which are avail- able in English. The series includes texts by familiar names (such as Descartes and Kant) and also by less well-known authors. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each volume contains a critical introduction together with a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and textual apparatus. The volumes are designed for student use at undergraduate and postgraduate level and will be of interest not only to students of philosophy but also to a wider audience of readers in the history of science, the history of theology and the history of ideas. For a list of titles published in the series, please see end of book. IMMANUEL KANT Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals TRANSLATED AND EDITED BY MARY GREGOR WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY CHRISTINE M. KORSGAARD Harvard University CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vie 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcon 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Cambridge University Press 1997 This book is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • Course Description 2019-2020
    COURSE DESCRIPTION 2019-2020 YEAR ONE Introduction to Philosophy [OFS01] The course is introductory and basic, is offered to those who have no previous studies in philosophy, both to those who already have studied the history of philosophy benefit from further possibility of deepening of philosophical issues particularly related to their specific university studies. It is to introduce students to the question of fundamental philosophy, recalling the main stages of its development in the context of Western thought and culture, and providing adequate epistemological philosophy with respect to various scientific disciplines (with a particular attention to so-called "human and social sciences") and with respect to theology. At the end of the course students will be able to: - know the milestones and the main topics of Western philosophical thought, putting them in dialogue with other traditions wisdom and emerging issues of contemporary society; Know how to argue and provide a definition of philosophy as a science, and the reason for its individual and particular nature. Know how to relate the philosophical knowledge with the various forms of scientific rationality and theology; Know the main topics of philosophy and contemporary disciplines in relation to these issues mainly from the world of education and communication. Proposed Bibliography: 1. Basic didactical subsidies of the professor. 2. The Supreme Pontiff John Paul II, Encyclical Letter: Fides et Ratio, on the relationship between Faith and Reason. Citta‘ del Vaticano, LEV, 1998. 3. ABBAGNANO N.-FORNERO G. (a cura), Dizionario di Filosofia (Torino, UTET 1998). 4. MANTOVANI M., Là dove osa il pensiero. Introduzione alla filosofia (Dispensa, UPS, Roma, 2015).
    [Show full text]
  • Ibn Sīnā's Practical Philosophy
    Religious Inquiries Vol. 2, No. 3, Winter and Spring 2013, 5-27. Ibn Sīnā’s Practical Philosophy Hajj Mohammad Legenhausen1 This article is a brief review of Ibn Sīnā‘s practical philosophy. It begins with a discussion of the Platonic, Aristotelian, and Neo-Platonic influences on Ibn Sīnā‘s practical philosophy, as well as the influence of Fārābī and of Islamic religious teachings. The creative synthesis invented by Ibn Sīnā requires a particular view of the relation between religion and philosophy in such a manner that religion shapes the direction of philosophical inquiry, and philosophy opens the way to a more profound and esoteric understanding of religion. Keywords: Aristotle, Avicenna, Ibn Sīnā, Fārābī, ethics, neo-Platonism, Plato, practical wisdom, prophet, revelation, virtue. What is Practical Philosophy? Aristotle defines practical wisdom (φρόνησις, phronesis) as a kind of excellence or virtue: The distinction between virtues also reflects this difference. For some virtues are called virtues of thought, other virtues of character; wisdom, comprehension and intelligence (phronesis) are called virtues of thought, generosity and temperance, virtues of character. (Aristotle 1985, 1103a 4-6) So, if we begin with excellences or virtues, we may divide them into intellectual and moral virtues. Among the intellectual virtues will be found both theoretical and practical wisdom, that is, sophia and phronesis. In Arabic, these are called al- ikmat al-na ariyya and al- ikmat al-ʽamaliyya. The manner in which Ibn Sīnā uses these terms shows that he was following Aristotle‘s usage in the Nicomachean Ethics.2 1. Professor, Imam Khomeini Educational and Research Institute, Iran ([email protected]) 2.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study on Conscience: the Content and Function
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Summer 1-1-2016 A Study on Conscience: The onC tent and Function Nalan Sarac Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Sarac, N. (2016). A Study on Conscience: The onC tent and Function (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/105 This One-year Embargo is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A STUDY ON CONSCIENCE: THE CONTENT AND FUNCTION A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Nalan Saraç August 2016 Copyright by Nalan Saraç 2016 A STUDY ON CONSCIENCE: THE CONTENT AND FUNCTION By Nalan Saraç Approved July 7, 2016 ________________________________ ________________________________ Ronald Polansky Thérèse Bonin Professor of Philosophy Associate Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ Jennifer Ann Bates Professor of Philosophy Committee Member) ________________________________ ________________________________ James Swindal, Dean Ronald Polansky The McAnulty College and Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT A STUDY ON CONSCIENCE: THE CONTENT AND FUNCTION By Nalan Saraç August 2016 Dissertation supervised by Ronald Polansky The aim of this study is to contribute to the understanding of conscience by critically examining turning points of the traditionalist approach that conceptualizes conscience primarily as a cognitive capacity.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Practical Philosophy: the Realization of Freedom
    9 ROBERT PIPPIN Hegel’s practical philosophy: the realization of freedom I In Hegel’s Encyclopedia system, what we would nowadays call his practical phi- losophy is called the “philosophy of spirit.” By practical philosophy, we usually mean a philosophical account of the possibility of the distinct sorts of events for which we may appropriately demand reasons or justifications from subjects whom we take to be responsible for such events occurring, or we mean an account of actions, and an assessment of what rightly count as such reasons or justifications.1 The central problem in other words is the status of the condition usually taken as necessary for such a delimitation of a class of events as actions: freedom. What is it, is it possible, how important is it? Such a philosophy of spirit has a specific place in Hegel’s systematic enterprise. That system is divided into what looks like the basic or foundational enterprise,2 a “Science of Logic,” or his own version of a theory of concepts and the possibil- ity of conceptual content (an account of all possible account-giving, as it were); and then into a “Philosophy of Nature” and a “Philosophy of Spirit”; or it relies on some argument about why the very possibility of an objective judgment requires just such delimited contents, that a successful account must be an account either of nature or of spirit.3 (For all their differences, there is a parallel here with Kant’s architectonic and the relation between the first Critique and the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science on the one hand,
    [Show full text]
  • (1724-1804). Immanuel Kant Was Born and Spent His Life in Königsberg, Prussia, Now Kaliningrad, Russia
    1 KANT, IMMANUEL (1724-1804). Immanuel Kant was born and spent his life in Königsberg, Prussia, now Kaliningrad, Russia. Although his family was poor, Kant was educated in a good Pietist school and attended the University of Königsberg from 1740- 1747. From 1747-1755 he worked as a private tutor for various families in the Königsberg area. From 1755 -1770 he was a Privatdozent at the University, lecturing on subjects as diverse as logic, mathematics, metaphysics, ethics, anthropology, and geography. In 1770 he became Professor of Logic and Metaphysics. He taught until 1796, and died in 1804. Restricted to a quiet life by a modest income, delicate health, and a demanding workload, Kant never married or traveled. Popular tradition portrays Kant as rigid and moralistic, as devoted to system and rule in his life as he was in his work. This picture must be tempered by the less familiar set of images handed down to us by his friends and students: of a genial host famous for his powers of conversation; of an immensely popular teacher whose students claimed that they “never left a single lecture in his ethics without having become better men”; and of “the Old Jacobin” whose passionate defense of the French Revolution astonished and inspired his contemporaries. EARLY VIEWS AND THE CRITICAL PROJECT. Kant was educated in the predominant “Leibniz-Wolffian philosophy,” an extreme form of dogmatic rationalism, but its influence on him was mitigated by his interest in British philosophy and science. A disposition to question the power of pure reason shows up even in his “pre-critical” works, those written before he made the discoveries that led to the three Critiques.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Didactics of Philosophy
    Journal of Didactics of Philosophy Volume 4, Number 2 ISSN 2624-540X Editors Jonas Pfister (Bern, Switzerland) Philipp Richter (Bochum, Germany) Editorial Board Ricardo Guttierez Aguilar (Madrid, Spain) Geert-Lueke Lueken (Leipzig, Germany) Anne Burkard (Göttingen, Germany) Leo Luks (Tartu, Estonia) Beate Børresen (Oslo, Norway) Kirsten Meyer (Berlin, Germany) Bruno Curko (Zagreb, Croatia) Dirk Oosthoek (Rotterdam, Netherlands) Julia Dietrich (Berlin, Germany) Attila Pato (Prague, Czech Republic) Klaus Feldmann (Wuppertal, Germany) Moris Polanco (Guatemala City, Guatemala) Andreas Gelhard (Bonn, Germany) Donata Romizi (Vienna, Austria) Thor Steinar Grødal (Oslo, Norway) Luca Scarantino (Paris/Milan, France/Italy) Eric Gustafsson (Stockholm, Sweden) Gisele Secco (Porto Alegre, Brazil) Shinji Kajitani (Tokyo, Japan) Marjan Simenc (Ljubljana, Slovenia) Edward Kanterian (Kent, UK) Christian Thein (Münster, Germany) Jens Kertscher (Darmstadt, Germany) Silvia Tonti (Darmstadt, Germany) Minkyung Kim (Chemnitz, Germany) René Torkler (Eichstätt/Ingolstadt, Germany) Helge Kminek (Frankfurt/Main, Germany) Floris Velema (Rotterdam, Netherlands) Ivan Kolev (Sofia, Bulgaria) Peter Zimmermann (Fribourg, Switzerland) Journal of Didactics of Philosophy 4 (2020) About The Journal of Didactics of Philosophy is a peer-reviewed academic journal devoted to research on the teaching and learning of philosophy. It is published online twice a year. The access to all articles is free. Articles may be about any level of education. However, the main focus is on high school philosophy. We welcome work with a philosophical or normative approach as well as reports of results from empirical qualitative and quantitative research. The journal also publishes reviews of books, textbooks, and other educational material of international interest as well as country reports. These reports present information about ways of teaching philosophy, its institutions and activities in different countries.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Contributions to the Concept of a Conscience
    Aristotelian Contributions to the Concept of a Conscience Master's Thesis submitted for the Research Master’s Philosophy Utrecht University October 19, 2019 Michael Simon John Ashfield Student Number: 3782700 Supervisor: Johannes Van Ophuijzen Second Reader: Teun Tieleman Third Reader: Joel Anderson 1 Abstract The question this thesis seeks to address is that of whether there is a basis to be found in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics for developing an understanding of what we now call moral conscience, and, if established, how this compares with a much later, post-Cartesian ethics which explicitly and more organically includes a concept of moral conscience. Our usage of the term today seems to imply that moral conscience is about feeling as well about thinking. Yet accounts of it such as that found in Kant focus on the rational. I look first at how the term conscience appeared in philosophical writings in Ancient Greece and how the concept evolved and acquired its moral application as it passed through Stoic, and early and medieval Christian thinkers. I then focus on one example of a modern, developed conception of conscience - that of Kant - and endeavour to examine this concept with a view to evaluating whether it can account for the ways in which we invoke the concept of a conscience today. The internal reasoning of the self-legislated moral individual Kant speaks of constitutes an ‘inner court’ in which one judges the moral value of one’s actions. I try to show how for Kant, conscience, this inner court, is a built-in element of his practical reasoning, whereas for Aristotle there is the awareness resulting from the apparentness of one’s end and the means best corresponding to it, this awareness being an imagination and sensitivity which develops out of the interdependency of phronesis and moral virtue.
    [Show full text]
  • Phronesis and Virtue of Character: the Making of Morally Right Goals in Aristotle’S Nicomachean Ethics by Yuchen Liang
    Phronesis And Virtue of Character: The Making of Morally Right Goals in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics by Yuchen Liang A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy in the University of Michigan 2017 Advisor: Professor Laura Ruetsche Second Reader: Professor Maria Lasonen-Aarnio 1 1. Virtue Makes the Goal Right? The Humean Controversy In this chapter I aim to set the stage for a debate on the nature of the starting-point of phronesis. Phronesis is generally translated as “practical wisdom”. It is the knowledge of how to perform morally right actions. Its starting-point, as I will later explain in detail, is the setting of morally right goals. Why does there have to be a debate in the first place? The short answer would be that some Aristotle scholars disagree with ways to read an important sentence in Nicomachean Ethics (EN). This infamous sentence is: 1. Virtue makes the goal right, phronesis the things towards it. (EN 1144a6-9) I will refer to this sentence as the “making the goal right” sentence throughout this thesis. Many philosophers worry that a literal reading of this sentence would lead to a “Humean” interpretation of Aristotle’s ethics. The term “Humean” here denotes a specific type of ethical system, rather than what Hume says strictly. A “Humean” ethical system emphasizes the role of desire in ethical decisions, in contrast to intellect. Some claim that this Humean system contradicts Aristotle’s general attitude towards moral actions, especially his definition of phronesis.
    [Show full text]