R.M. Van Den Burg, Proclus' Commentary on the Cratylus In

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

R.M. Van Den Burg, Proclus' Commentary on the Cratylus In Book Reviews / Th e International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 3 (2009) 154-201 161 R.M. Van den Burg, Proclus’ Commentary on the Cratylus in Context. Ancient Th eo- ries of Language and Meaning (Leiden: Brill, 2008), pp. 239, $127, ISBN 9789004163799. In a notorious sentence, Richard Sorabji once remarked that Neoplatonists adhered to the “perfectly crazy” proposition that Plato and Aristotle are largely or entirely in agreement, but that this crazy proposition proved “philosophically fruitful.” It is with something of this spirit that Robbert Van den Berg (hereafter VdB) approaches the commentary of Proclus on Plato’s Cratylus.1 On the one hand, he has devoted a fi ne and sensitive monograph to the commentary and the history of etymological theories in previous Greek philosophy. Indeed this book seems to me to be a defi nitive study of the Cratylus commentary. On the other hand he thinks that Proclus, along with other Neoplatonists, got the central idea of the Cratylus “completely wrong” (xv, cf. 38-9, 79, 132). Plato, on VdB’s read- ing, presented a critique of the philosophical use of etymology and had a deep suspicion about the dialectical adequacy of natural language. Th e Neoplatonists, blithely missing this point, were happy not only to embrace the etymologies of the Cratylus but also to invent further etymologies of their own. Th is is a familiar feature of post-Iamblichean Neoplatonic texts, whose eff ect on the modern reader might be compared to that of the equally off -putting numerological proclivities of these same authors. Now, much as Dominic O’Meara has put Neoplatonic numer- ology within its proper intellectual context,2 VdB seeks to situate Proclus’ theory of names within the preceding tradition and Proclus’ own wider thought. Although VdB thinks Proclus has misunderstood Plato’s attitude towards natu- ral language, he allows that there is something right about Proclus’ approach. For the Cratylus is indeed intimately related to Platonic metaphysics, just as Proclus assumed. In his fi rst chapter VdB argues for a metaphysical reading of the Cratylus which is compatible with his reading of Plato as an etymological pessimist. He plausibly connects the Cratylus to remarks on naming found in the Sophist and Statesman (8-13). In those remarks, the Eleatic Stranger welcomes appropriate natural names for the items involved in collection and division. But he also shows awareness of the limits of these names, sometimes criticizing names for not divid- ing nature “at the joints” (e.g. the name “barbarian,” Statesman 262c-d), at other times saying that new names must be devised. Similarly, the Cratylus does accept that we can uncover the intentions of primordial name-givers—so that the task of etymologizing is not merely being mocked in the dialogue. But it then turns out that these name-givers had a mistaken philosophical outlook, being committed to 1) Th e commentary was recently translated in Sorabji’s Ancient Commentators Series: see B. Duvick (trans.), Proclus: On Plato Cratylus (London: 2007). 2) See D.J. O’Meara, Pythagoras Revived. Mathematics and Philosophy in Late Antiquity (Oxford: 1989). © Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2009 DOI: 10.1163/187250809X12474505284026 Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 12:39:44AM via free access 162 Book Reviews / Th e International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 3 (2009) 154-201 a Heraclitean theory according to which all things are in fl ux.3 Th us names are, in a sense, worse than mere empty symbols: they preserve a false philosophical view of the world and are thus apt to mislead anyone who does dialectic by analyzing names. VdB contrasts this position to that of Aristotle, who thought that natural language is conventional, but frequently a good guide to truth despite its limits. Th ere are several reasons why Proclus was never likely to read the Cratylus in this way. For one thing, there is the widespread tendency of ancient philoso- phers to assume that humans of previous ages surpassed us in their wisdom and insight. Plato himself seems to endorse this sentiment in other contexts (e.g. the opening sections of the Timaeus). Th us Proclus would not have been as ready as we are to think that the original name-givers could have been, by Plato’s lights, systematically mistaken. Furthermore, Neoplatonists tended in any case to see the physical realm as subject to fl ux. So on this score Proclus might have agreed with Plato’s name-givers, at least so far as physical things are concerned (more on this below). For another thing, VdB’s reading casts no doubt on the validity of the etymologies of divine names presented in the Cratylus, and it is clearly these etymologies that Proclus considered most important. In light of this, VdB may put too much emphasis on the Neoplatonic “misreading” of the Cratylus. Regarding what was, for them, the most important aspect of the dialogue, they read Plato more or less the way that VdB does.4 VdB has enlightening things to say about why Neoplatonists, or at least post- Iamblichean Neoplatonists, were so determined to hold on to the divine names and to etymologize them. Th at they did so might at fi rst come as a surprise, given the ineff ability of the gods. But in fact it is the very transcendence of the divine that made etymology so important. As VdB points out, Plotinus was able largely to dispense with etymology because he was an “epistemic optimist.” He thought that we can uncover the nature of the Forms and the divine realm through rational inquiry, because a part of our soul always remains in contact with this higher realm (67, 73, 86). By contrast later Platonists, who rejected Plotinus’ doctrine of the undescended soul,5 thought that the divine would remain unaccessible to us unless it were somehow revealed. Th eurgy is one way that Iamblichus and other Platonists thought this could be brought about. An example from Proclus that VdB mentions several times is statues of the gods, which perform the same func- tion as names by “resembling” the gods. Here Platonist epistemology supports a widespread religious and cultural commitment, namely the immense respect that was paid both to divine names and to statues (74, 111). It’s tempting to say that this attitude functions as an endoxon which Proclus seeks to vindicate. 3) Here VdB is following D.N. Sedley, Plato’s Cratylus (Cambridge: 2003). 4) He agrees with Sedley that the divine etymologies are basically endorsed by Plato: see 117. 5) On this see C.G. Steel, Th e Changing Self. A Study on the Soul in Later Neoplatonism: Iambli- chus, Damascius and Priscianus (Brussels: 1978). Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 12:39:44AM via free access Book Reviews / Th e International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 3 (2009) 154-201 163 But one should not assume that all Greek thinkers were enthusiastic users of etymology, for divine names or names in general.6 As VdB points out, the Platonist stance may be an inheritance from the Stoics, who decisively rejected convention- alism and even invented the word etymologia (34). Quite possibly in reaction to the Cratylus, the Stoics used etymology to uncover the insight of original name-givers, which for them had subsequently been obscured by the development of Greek language. Of course, the Stoics made no ontological distinction between divine and physical realms, such that names could adequately represent the former and falsely the latter (this, as we have seen, is eff ectively VdB’s reading of Plato). Th is is relevant to VdB’s interesting chapter on the linguistic views of Porphyry, whose remarks about names are a sort of miniature version of his incorporation of Aristo- tle within a Platonist philosophy. Porphyry seems to endorse Aristotle’s conven- tionalism regarding names, and he was criticized for this by Iamblichus (71). But this conventionalism went hand-in-hand with his strategy of assigning Aristotelian philosophy, and especially the organon with its treatment of language, to our lower physical realm. Th e aforementioned Stoic position may have played arole here. If Porphyry followed a Stoicizing account of etymology, he may also have followed the link they drew between even divine names and physical phenomena (74). As on so many other issues, the works of Proclus give us our best extant evi- dence for the post-Porphyrian consensus on the correctness of names, originated by Iamblichus. And among Proclus’ works, of course, it is the Cratylus commen- tary that addresses the question most extensively. However Proclus did not claim that the aim (skopos) of the Cratylus was names or their correctness. Rather, he read it as a dialogue about psychology: name-giving is simply a central example of the “generative activity and assimilative power of souls” (96). Because souls are, as Plotinus put it, on the horizon between the sensible and intelligible worlds, the names they give are of two kinds. Th e names of eternal things manifest our capac- ity for knowledge (they are given kat’ epistêmên), whereas names of physical things manifest a kind of opinion (doxa) and are subject to chance (98-101). Proclus puts this point to use in his account of the diff erent characters in the dialogue. Cratylus insists on natural correctness of names but errs in assuming that all things are in fl ux, whereas Hermogenes fails to lift his gaze above the realm of changing par- ticulars and thus assumes that all names are correct only by convention (102). VdB thus suggests that for Proclus Hermogenes would represent the Aristotelian position (106). Th e two-world metaphysics also allows Proclus to explain, for instance, variation in natural languages: two words that are the same in form and correctly signify the same thing might nonetheless diff er in their “acoustic matter” 6) In the pre-Plotinian period a strikingly critical stance towards natural language is shown by Galen (56-8).
Recommended publications
  • From Cratylus to Aristotle
    From Cratylus to Aristotle Article by Martha Keltz Heraclitus and Cratylus – From the Sixth to the Fifth Century Before Christ Heraclitus, Cratylus and the Essenes “The name of John is connected with the city of Ephesus, and equipped with Imaginative insight into world history, he is continually referred back along an inner path to the ancient temple of Diana of Ephesus, and confronts these significant words: 'In the primal Beginning was the Logos. And the Logos was with God. And the Logos was a God. “ ...When the evangelist could read about Ephesus in the Akasha Record, could read that for which his heart thirsted, [he found] the right form in which to clothe what he wanted to say to humanity concerning the mystery of the beginning of the world.” - Rudolf Steiner , Mystery Centers. “Thus we show how Eabani [from The Epic of Gilgamesh ], in the incarnation between the life as Eabani and the life as Aristotle, was able under the influence of the ancient Mystery teachings, into which forces streamed from the supersensible worlds, to imbibe the principles which in certain Mystery schools were essential to the further development of the human soul... In such Mystery schools the feelings and impulses paramountly awakened were those capable of eradicating every trace of egoism from the soul... In the Mysteries to which I am here referring, the soul had to learn to feel pity and compassion for everything human, for everything cosmic – compassion born from the overcoming of the physical plane.” - Occult History . The life between Eabani and Aristotle was that of Cratylus.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Cases of the Golden Age: the Hesiodic Utopia and the Platonic Ideal State
    TWO CASES OF THE GOLDEN AGE: THE HESIODIC UTOPIA AND THE PLATONIC IDEAL STATE A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY GÜNEŞ VEZİR IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY SEPTEMBER 2019 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Assoc. Prof. Dr. Sadettin Kirazcı Director (Acting) I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Halil Turan Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Halil Turan Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assoc. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, PHIL) Prof. Dr. Halil Turan (METU, PHIL) Assist. Prof. Dr. Refik Güremen (Mimar Sinan Fine Arts Uni., PHIL) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last Name: Güneş Vezir Signature : iii ABSTRACT TWO CASES OF THE GOLDEN AGE: THE HESIODIC UTOPIA AND THE PLATONIC IDEAL STATE Vezir, Güneş MA, Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Halil Turan September 2019, 119 pages This study was prepared to give information about the Golden Age myth, and in this regard, to illustrate for what purposes and in which ways the myth is used by Hesiod and Plato and the interaction and similarities between these thinkers.
    [Show full text]
  • Arethas of Caesarea and the Scholia On
    Ryan Bailey ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 MA Thesis in Medieval Studies Central European University CEU eTD Collection Budapest May 2012 ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 by Ryan Bailey (USA) Thesis submitted to the Department of Medieval Studies, Central European University, Budapest, in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Master of Arts degree in Medieval Studies. Accepted in conformance with the standards of the CEU. ____________________________________________ Chair, Examination Committee ____________________________________________ Thesis Supervisor ____________________________________________ Examiner ____________________________________________ CEU eTD Collection Examiner Budapest May 2012 ii ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 by Ryan Bailey (USA) Thesis submitted to the Department of Medieval Studies, Central European University, Budapest, in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Master of Arts degree in Medieval Studies. Accepted in conformance with the standards of the CEU. ____________________________________________ External Reader CEU eTD Collection Budapest May 2012 iii ARETHAS OF CAESAREA AND THE SCHOLIA ON PHILOSTRATUS’ VITA APOLLONII IN LAUR. 69.33 by Ryan Bailey (USA) Thesis submitted to the Department of Medieval Studies, Central European University, Budapest, in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the Master of Arts degree in Medieval Studies. Accepted in conformance with the standards of the CEU. ________________________ Supervisor ____________________________________________ External Supervisor CEU eTD Collection Budapest May 2012 iv I, the undersigned, Ryan Bailey , candidate for the MA degree in Medieval Studies, declare herewith that the present thesis is exclusively my own work, based on my research and only such external information as properly credited in notes and bibliography.
    [Show full text]
  • Etymology Five Examples of Another Truth, from Democritus to Foucault
    Etymology Five Examples of Another Truth, From Democritus to Foucault Vincent W.J. van Gerven Oei Ph.D. (European Graduate School, 2011) M.Mus. (Royal Conservatoire, 2007) M.A. (Leiden University, 2005) A thesis presented for the degree of Ph.D. in Modern Thought at the University of Aberdeen. 2016 Summary In lieu of an introduction, this dissertation starts with a short exposé on the paradigm, or the example, which provides the general framework in which the argument will de- velop – namely to the side of more classical modes of deductive or inductive reasoning. Our argument here is that in order to inspect a concept – etumos logos – that has been repressed throughout most of the history of metaphysics, our biggest chance of uncov- ering some of it is to avoid modes of the logos that have been specifically prominent in that history of repression. In the First Example we investigate the predominance of alētheia as philosophically dominant word for truth, while locating in the work of Martin Heidegger a sustained attempt to undermine and recast the precise meaning of that word. It is our claim that even though Heidegger, ever reaching farther back in the history of Western philosophy, up to the first, non-philosophical, poetical attestations of the Ancient Greek language, manages to uncover many subtleties in the meaning and origin of truth as alētheia, he fails to notice that in the epic literature predating the first philosophical works alētheia is in no way the privileged word for truth. By investigating the precise semantics of the contrast between etumos/etētumos/ eteos and alēthēs in the work of Homer and Hesiod, and the slow disappearance of this contrast in Aeschylus and Pindar, we suggest a parallel between on the one hand the disappearance of the former and Heidegger’s insistent neglect of this disappearance.
    [Show full text]
  • Stepping Into Rivers: Ontology in Heraclitus
    Stephen Aylward Stepping into Rivers: Ontology in Heraclitus Cratylus famously attempted to correct Heraclitus by amending his claim that “you cannot step twice into the same rivers; for fresh waters are flowing in upon you” (B2) to the more radical position that one cannot step even once into the same river (Arist. Metaph. 1010a10-15).1 This reading of Her- aclitus, which commits him to a radical doctrine of flux, in which things fail to maintain any sort of on- tological unity through time, was popular in ancient times, and is preserved in both Plato and Aristotle as the main teaching of Heraclitus. While more recent scholarship has cast doubt on this traditional in- terpretation of Heraclitus, most of the discussion of the issue has centered on philological considerations, pertaining to whether or not Heraclitus had been properly interpreted by Plato and Aristotle.2 The mod- ern attempt to alter Heraclitus’ reputation as the philosopher of ta panta rei has thus been left open to the charge that the new interpretation is not coherent with regard to the extant fragments. So, W.K.C. Guthrie argues that, “in fact, the extant fragments offer no challenge to the universal ancient view.”3 In the course of this paper, I propose to evaluate some of the philological issues at stake, as a precursor to a philosophical discussion of the extant fragments, in the hope of at least sketching a response to the chal- lenge set by Guthrie. I will therefore demonstrate on the basis of the text that Cratylus was mistaken, and that the ontological unity of the river does in fact persist through time.
    [Show full text]
  • The Legacy of Hermes: Deception and Dialectic in Plato's Cratylus
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy J. anc. philos. (Engl. ed.), São Paulo, v.10, n.1. p. 26-58, 2016. ISSN 1981-9471 - FFLCH/USP DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v10i1p26-58 www.revistas.usp.br/filosofiaantiga The Legacy of Hermes: Deception and Dialectic in Plato’s Cratylus Olof Pettersson Against the background of a conventionalist theory, and staged as a defense of a naturalistic notion of names and naming, the critique of language developed in Plato’s Cratylus does not only propose that human language, in contrast to the language of the gods, is bound to the realm of myth and lie. The dialogue also concludes by offering a set of reasons to think that knowledge of reality is not within the reach of our words. Interpretations of the dialogue’s long etymological sections often neglect this critique and tend to end up with an overly optimistic assessment of the theory of language on offer. In the light of one of the dialogue’s central etymological accounts – Socrates’ etymology of the name Hermes – this paper discusses two recent and influential versions of such a view: David Sedley’s theory of onomatopoetic encapsulation and Franco Trivigno’s qualified referentialism. It argues that the complex relation between language and reality expressed in the Cratylus cannot be exhaustively captured by either of these theories because Plato considers all names to be semantically underdetermined until they are put to use. It suggests that Plato rather works with a functionalistic notion of names and naming, and that the dialogue’s account of natural and correct naming is to be understood in these terms.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Cratylus and Aristotle's
    CHAPTER ONE PLATO’S CRATYLUS AND ARISTOTLE’S DE INTERPRETATIONE: SETTING THE SCENE 1. Introduction A study into the reception of the Cratylus in Antiquity has almost inevi- tably got to start with a discussion of the Cratylus itself. Once relatively neglected, the dialogue has received its fair share of attention in recent years. In most of these studies the Cratylus is presented either as a work about the philosophy of language, a category which as such did not yet exist in Antiquity, or about linguistics, especially because of the many etymologies.1 Only few publications discuss the Cratylus as primarily a dialogue concerning Platonic dialectic. Most ancient interpreters, on the contrast, taking their clue from the fact that Socrates presents names as the instruments of a dialectician, assume that the Cratylus deals with the dialectical function of names. Below I shall explore a reading of the Cratylus from this dialectical perspective. On the one hand, within the context of the present study, such a discussion will provide a useful foil for the study of the ancient interpretations. On the other hand, as regards the interpretation of the Cratylus itself, such an approach will appear to contribute to a better understanding of the dialogue. That is not to say that I adopt the ancient interpretations of the Cratylus, nor do I advice that we adopt uncritically ancient readings of Plato in general. There is no reason to assume that these are in principle any better than modern approaches, since they tend to be determined by all kinds of assumptions about Plato and his work that we may nd impos- sible to share.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cratylus
    Anthós (1990-1996) Volume 1 Number 2 Article 7 1991 Explication: The Cratylus Joseph S. Gray Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/anthos_archives Part of the Classics Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Gray, Joseph S. (1991) "Explication: The Cratylus," Anthós (1990-1996): Vol. 1 : No. 2 , Article 7. Available at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/anthos_archives/vol1/iss2/7 This open access Article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- ShareAlike 4.0 International License (CC BY-NC-SA 4.0). All documents in PDXScholar should meet accessibility standards. If we can make this document more accessible to you, contact our team. EXPLICATION: THE CRATYLUS Joseph Stephen Gray lato's Cratylus is a dialogue on language P involving Cratylus, Hermogenes, and Socrates. It is an argument between nomos (law, convention) and phusis (nature), two concepts which explain the process by which things are named. Socrates, in this dialogue, seeks to discover whether names originate out of convention and a,greement, or whether these names evolve,d out of some similarity to the object they represe~t. .He supports and rejects both points to some degree. He finds that names can be altere9 and taken apart to find their literal meaning from other names. He also notices that certain sounds tend to be characteristic of qualities found in the object being named. Socrates defines the naming process as agreed information given to distinguish things, and uses the word legislation, a word used mainly to describe lawmaking, to describe it.
    [Show full text]
  • Pythagoras : His Life, Teaching, and Influence / Christoph Riedweg ; Translated by Steven Rendall in Collaboration with Christoph Riedweg and Andreas Schatzmann
    riedweg 3rd correx.qxp 1/21/2005 12:21 PM Page i Pythagoras riedweg 3rd correx.qxp 1/21/2005 12:21 PM Page ii riedweg 3rd correx.qxp 1/21/2005 12:21 PM Page iii Pythagoras His Life, Teaching, and Influence Christoph Riedweg Translated by Steven Rendall in collaboration with Christoph Riedweg and Andreas Schatzmann Cornell University Press Ithaca and London riedweg 3rd correx.qxp 1/21/2005 12:21 PM Page iv This is a licensed English translation of Christoph Riedweg, Pythagoras: Leben, Lehre, Nachwirkung. Eine Einführung, published by C. H. Beck in 2002. © Verlag C. H. Beck oHG, München 2002 Cornell University Press gratefully acknowledges receipt of a subven- tion from the Zürcher Universitätsverein, which aided in the publi- cation of this book. English translation copyright © 2005 by Cornell University All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book, or parts thereof, must not be reproduced in any form without per- mission in writing from the publisher. For information, address Cornell University Press, Sage House, 512 East State Street, Ithaca, New York 14850. First published 2005 by Cornell University Press Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Riedweg, Christoph. Pythagoras : his life, teaching, and influence / Christoph Riedweg ; translated by Steven Rendall in collaboration with Christoph Riedweg and Andreas Schatzmann. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-8014-4240-0 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Pythagoras. I. Title. B243.R54 2005 182′.2--dc22 2004023906 Cornell University Press strives to use environmentally responsible suppliers and materials to the fullest extent possible in the publish- ing of its books.
    [Show full text]
  • Andrei Lebedev Pythagoras, Parmenides, Heraclitus
    DOI:10.30842/ielcp230690152352 Andrei Lebedev (RAS Institute of Philosophy/HSE University) IDEALISM (MENTALISM) IN EARLY GREEK METAPHYSICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY: Pythagoras, Parmenides, Heraclitus, Xenophanes and others (with some remarks on the «Gigantomachia over being» in Plato’s Sophist) Abstract and table of contents: (1) Preliminary criticism of the presuppositions of the denial of existence of idealism in early Greek thought: pseudohistorical evolu- tionism, Platonocentrism that ignores the archaic features of Plato’s metaphysics and psychology, and the modern stereotype of «Presocratics» as physicalists, a product of the late 19th century (excessive) positivist reaction against Hegelianism and German idealism in the English-speaking historiography of Greek philosophy. (2) Demiourgos and creationism in Pre-Platonic philosophy. Creation by divine mind is a form of objective idealism (mentalism). (3) The thesis of Myles Burnyeat and Bernard Williams (no idealism in Greek philosophy) is criticized. We point to scholastic and ancient (Platonic) roots of Descartes’ substance dualism of body and mind, as well as to the even more ancient Pythagorean roots of Plato’s doctrine of immortal soul. (4) A provisional taxonomy of different types of idealism (mentalism) in ancient Greek philosophy is proposed. 11 types are distinguished. (5) The evidence of the Orphic-Pythagorean graffiti from Olbia on the early Pythagorean substance dualism of body and soul proves its Preplatonic origin. (6) Criticism of modern naturalistic interpretations of Pythagorean first principles peras and apeiron (Burkert, Huffman and others). Peras and apeiron (a geometrical analogue of later terms form and matter) are self- subsistent incorporeal mathematical essences, out of which physical bodies are «constructed» (ἁρμόζειν, another geometrical term for «construction») by the divine mind-demiourgos.
    [Show full text]