<<

Radical : Applying Libertarian Principles to Dealing with the Unjust Government, Part II

Walter Block Loyola University, New Orleans

This is Part II of an essay that attempts to trace out the implications of the libertarian philosophy for the proper relationship between an inhabitant of a country and its unjust government. 1 Part I of this essay included Section 2, which set the stage for addressing this challenging task, Section 3, in which the essence of the state was discussed, Section 4, in which libertarian punishment theory was introduced, the beginning of Section 5, in which the concept of the libertarian Nuremberg trial was explored, and Section 5a, wherein the assumption that all citizens are guilty of the crimes of the unjust state was rejected. In Part II of this essay, we now begin with section 5b, which considers the possibility that all and only minions of the unjust state are guilty for its crimes, in a continuation of our libertarian Nuremberg trial analysis. Section 5c introduces libertarian ruling class theory. Section 6 traces out the proper relations between the subjects and the unjust government. Section 7 asks whether it is ever legitimate to disrupt such an institution, and we conclude in Section 8.

5b. All and only minions of the state are guilty A second possibility is that all politicians, judges, bureaucrats, and any other type of government employee of the Nazi German state are guilty of crimes against freedom, and that this applies to no one else. There are grave problems with this perspective as well. First, it is over-inclusive. It will capture in its net of guilt people at the very bottom of the statist pyramid of power: those who clean government cesspools, carry away the garbage, rake the leaves, deliver the mail door to door, wash the public toilets, etc. These people, surely, are more sinned against than sinning. As well, it includes anyone associated with a public university: professor,

1 Part I of this paper appeared as , “Radical Libertarianism: Applying Libertarian Principles to Dealing with the Unjust Government, Part I,” Reason Papers 27 (Fall 2004), pp. 117-33.

Reason Papers 28 (Spring 2006): 85-109. Copyright © 2006

Reason Papers Vol. 28 student, administrator, grounds keeper, etc., and anyone involved in a state hospital: doctor, nurse, floor-sweep, etc. It will also declare guilty those who have striven mightily to overturn the evil system, but from a position within government. Take , for example. 2 Although he is a member of the U.S. House of Representatives, he is a libertarian in good standing. His congressional votes are all on the side of .3 During any proper libertarian Nuremberg trial, he would be on the bench, not in the dock. Second, it is under-inclusive. It gives a free ride to all those not officially part of the government who may have nevertheless played important roles in supporting the Nazi evil, for example, the businessmen who bankrolled Hitler into power not out of defensive motives, but for their own purposes, 4 as well as the intellectuals who wove apologetics and defenses for the regime. 5 c. Ruling class theory A third perspective, which far better separates the innocent wheat from the guilty chaff is ruling class theory. It must be admitted at the outset that this sounds rather tinny to the libertarian ear since it is usually couched in Marxist rhetoric. According to Marxism, the ruling class is composed of those who employ labor and the victims are employees. The exploitation of the latter by the former occurs because of the labor theory of value. Workers are responsible for the total product; they receive it, but only when profits are subtracted. The difference between the entire GDP and labor's share of it, typically in the neighborhood 6 of 75 percent, measures the level of exploitation.

2 Whenever a person from the U.S. is mentioned, or from any country other than Cuba, North Korea, the U.S.S.R., or Nazi , I am using him only as a hypothetical example. More specifically, in referring to Ron Paul, I have in mind the contrary-to- fact case of his equivalent in one of these four outlaw states.

3 Typically, whenever there is a 436 to 1 vote, it is Ron Paul who is in the minority.

4 Motive is not always unimportant. I argued that it should all but be ignored in the case of accidental , or in the shooting of an innocent person by a baby in the crib. However, motive can also determine membership in the ruling class, or not, as I shall discuss below.

5 We discuss below the difference between aiding and abetting evil, on the one hand, e.g., being a member of a criminal gang who himself commits no explicit violence such as the getaway car driver, and free speech, on the other hand.

6 Morgan O. Reynolds , Economics of Labor (South-Western College Publishing, 1995).

86 Reason Papers Vol. 28

But this is nonsense on stilts, apart from the fact that millions of people have been killed by communists under the banner of this philosophy, and millions more made to suffer economically because of it. 7 Mud pies are worth far less than cherry pies, even if an identical amount of labor goes in to the creation of the two "products." 8 A nugget lying on the ground in plain sight, big as a fist, is highly valuable, even though it takes no virtually no labor to pick it up. So much for Marxist class theory. But libertarian class analysis is entirely another matter. In this case, the exploiter is not the employer, nor the exploitee the employee. Very much to the contrary, the "bad guy" is the thief or murderer, and the "good guy" is the victim of this aggression against non- aggressors. John C. Calhoun 9 noted that the fiscal activities of the government— taxing and subsidizing—necessarily 10 divided the populace into two groups of people: net tax-payers and net tax-consumers. Those who paid in more than they were reimbursed would be considered victims, and those who spent less than they took from the system would be victimizers. This is a reasonably good, but only first, approximation to the distinction between members of the ruled and ruling classes. If we could but ignore what I will below call the Ragnar Danneskjold phenomenon, there would be a perfect congruency between the two sets of concepts. One group that would receive the attention of our libertarian Nurembergers is, of course, private criminals: purse snatchers, auto thieves, rapists, etc. There is nothing controversial here. But this also applies to all those responsible for government (for the libertarian anarchist) and excessive government (in the case of the minarchist); they would also and very properly be considered criminals. Government of this sort is the very embodiment of

7 Eugen Bohm-Bawerk, Capital and Interest trans. George D. Hunke and Hans F. Sennholz (Libertarian Press, 1959 [1884]); see particularly Part I, Chapter XII, "Exploitation Theory of -."

8 The Marxist might reply that only "socially necessary" labor counts, and it has been applied to the cherry pie, not its mud counterpart. But this is circular, as the only way we can beforehand know that the one embodies socially necessary labor, and the other not, is by already having information as to the very different values of these two products. That is, there is no definition of socially valuable labor that is independent of markets and consumer demands, the real source of value.

9 John C. Calhoun, A Disquisition on Government (Liberal Arts Press, 1953), pp. 16- 18.

10 Unless, of course, what each person pays into the government coffers, in the form of taxes, is exactly what he takes out of them in the form of subsidies. But this, in the words of Calhoun, “would make the process nugatory and absurd . . . .” Ibid., p. 17.

87 Reason Papers Vol. 28 the violation of the libertarian non-aggression axiom. The state is systematic, organized, initiatory violence. The only difference between the two sources of brutalization is that the latter has achieved a modicum of legitimacy, based on the massive amounts of its very well invested in suborning the academic, journalistic, religious and intellectual classes. A word is needed about free speech. The right to say exactly what you please 11 is something near to the very core of libertarianism. This philosophy, indeed, takes a rather extremist position on free speech, championing such things as libel, 12 blackmail, 13 even incitement 14 to violence.

11 On your own property, of course.

12 Murray N. Rothbard, ( University Press, 1998), pp. 126-28; Walter Block, Defending the Undefendable (Fox and Wilkes, 1991), pp. 59- 62.

13 Eric Mack, "In Defense of Blackmail," Philosophical Studies 41 (1982), p. 274; Rothbard, The Ethics of Liberty ; Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy and State (, 1993), p. 443 n. 49; Ronald Joseph Scalise, Jr., “Blackmail, Legality and ,” Tulane Law Review 74 (2000), pp. 1483-1517; Walter Block, "The Blackmailer as Hero," (December 1972), pp. 1-4; Walter Block, Defending the Undefendable (Fox and Wilkes, 1976), pp. 44-49; Walter Block and David Gordon, "Extortion and the Exercise of Free Speech Rights: A Reply to Professors Posner, Epstein, Nozick and Lindgren," Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 19, no. 1 (November 1985), pp. 37-54; Walter Block, "Trading Money for Silence," University of Hawaii Law Review 8, no. 1 (Spring 1986), pp. 57-73; Walter Block, "The Case for De-Criminalizing Blackmail: A Reply to Lindgren and Campbell," Western State University Law Review 24, no. 2 (Spring 1997), pp. 225-46; Walter Block, “A Libertarian Theory of Blackmail: Reply to Leo Katz’s ‘Blackmail and Other Forms of Arm-Twisting,’” Irish Jurist XXXIII (1998), pp. 280-310; Walter Block and Robert W. McGee, "Blackmail from A to Z,” Mercer Law Review 50, no. 2 (Winter 1999), pp. 569-601; Walter Block and Robert McGee, "Blackmail as a Victimless Crime," Bracton Law Journal 31 (1999), pp. 24-28; Walter Block, “Blackmail and Economic Analysis,” Thomas Jefferson Law Review 21, no. 2 (October 1999), pp. 165- 92; Walter Block, “Blackmailing for Mutual Good: A Reply to Russell Hardin,” Vermont Law Review 24, no. 1 (Fall 1999), pp. 121-41; Walter Block, “The Crime of Blackmail: A Libertarian Critique,” Criminal Justice Ethics 18, no. 2 (Summer/Fall 1999), pp. 3-10; Walter Block, “Replies to Levin and Kipnis on Blackmail,” Criminal Justice Ethics 18, no. 2 (Summer/Fall 1999), pp. 23-28; Walter Block and Christopher E. Kent, “Blackmail,” Magill’s Legal Guide (Salem Press, 1999), p. 109; Walter Block, Stephen Kinsella, and Hans-Hermann Hoppe, "Second Paradox of Blackmail," Business Ethics Quarterly 10, no. 3 (July 2000), pp. 593-622; Walter Block, “The Legalization of Blackmail: A Reply to Professor Gordon,” Seton Hall Law Review 30, no. 4 (2000), pp. 1182-1223; Walter Block, “Threats, Blackmail, Extortion and Robbery and Other Bad Things,” University of Tulsa Law Journal 35, no. 2 (Winter 2000), pp. 333-51; Walter Block, “Blackmail Is Private Justice,” University of British Columbia Law Review 34, no. 1 (2000), pp. 11-37; Walter Block, “Reply to Wexler:

88 Reason Papers Vol. 28

And yet, in our analysis, we appear to be not only questioning this stance, but also actively attacking the free speech rights of Marxists, statists, and other opponents of libertarianism. Nothing could be further from the truth. In the viewpoint being put forth here, communists are free to express themselves in any private venue they wish. However, when they take on a position at, say, a state university, now the expression of their ideas takes on a very different and far more ominous perspective. As part and parcel of the apparatus of the state, they are now not merely expressing an opinion; rather, they are now actively aiding and abetting in the rights violations of the multitudes of the people. Take Hitler, himself, as an example. He may never have pulled a single trigger, nor directly killed anyone. Let us stipulate, only for the sake of argument, that he did not. Are we then to let him off the Nuremberg hook on the ground that he limited himself to an exercise of his free speech rights? Not a bit of it. His role was an instrumental one in the mass murder committed by the Nazi regime; indeed, he played a chief role in this regard. His is not to be interpreted merely as free speech. Rather, he gave orders, with implicit and explicit threats backing them up, which were part of the process of rights violation. But the same can be said of the Marxist professor in a public university. His salary, too, is paid for out of compulsive levies. He, too, aligns himself with the evil empire, and, by the very nature of the enterprise, promotes his views through force. Another way to tease out the implications of ruling class theory is to borrow a leaf from the European military practices of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. It was typical for each country to impress the common sailor or soldier, but to commission the officers. When captured, the officers were traded for their equivalents in the other army or navy, and given parole for the duration of imprisonment. Often, they were allowed to wear their

Libertarianism, Blackmail and Decency,” University of British Columbia Law Review 34, no. 1 (2000), pp. 49-53; Walter Block, “Toward a Libertarian Theory of Blackmail,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 15, no. 2 (Winter 2001), pp. 55-88; Walter Block, “The Logic of the Argument in Behalf of Legalizing Blackmail,” Bracton Law Journal , 33 (2001), pp. 56-80; Walter Block and Gary Anderson, “Blackmail, Extortion and Exchange,” New York Law School Law Review 44, nos. 3-4 (2001), pp. 541-61.

14 Rothbard, The Ethics of Liberty , p. 126; for a critique of this position, from a self- styled libertarian, see , “Against Libertarian Legalism,” Journal of Libertarian Studies (forthcoming); for rejoinders, see Walter Block, “Reply to ‘Against Libertarian Legalism’ by Frank van Dun,” Journal of Libertarian Studies (forthcoming), and , “Rejoinder to van Dun on Libertarian Legalism,” Journal of Libertarian Studies (forthcoming).

89 Reason Papers Vol. 28 swords. A different fate awaited the commoners; they were impressed into the fighting forces of the country that captured them. 15 The point of this analogy is to blame the officers of the government, but not the common soldiers. Just as the Nuremberg trials went after the general and colonels, not the privates and corporals, the libertarian authorities will make a similar distinction with respect to the minions of the state. Well, then, who are the leaders of the modern state, or the officers, and who are the followers, or the common soldiers? There are no hard-and- fast conclusions; there are gray areas; there is a continuum, perhaps, between guilt and innocence; there are complications. Nevertheless, through the clouds and fog, there are principles that can help us shed light on the issue. Let us first divide governmental activities into two categories: those things that are intrinsically evil, and those which would occur even in a free society, but which are improperly taken over by the bureaucrats. In the first case, for example, it is wrong, plain wrong, to incarcerate people for engaging in prostitution, drug sales, paying wages below legal minima, or charging more than allowed by a rent control law. Everyone, everyone , directly involved in such viciousness, without exception, would be considered guilty of a rights violation, and punished appropriately by a libertarian court. This includes, but is probably not limited to, the police who capture such people, the wardens who jail them, the attorneys general who prosecute them, the judges and juries who find them guilty, etc. However, it would not include people only indirectly involved in such activities, such as those who sweep the floors in the court houses which find guilty such innocent (but actual) violators of these unjust laws, nor in the jails which later house them. Members of the coast guard and soldiers fighting in defensive wars would have nothing to fear from the libertarian court. 16 Matters would be completely otherwise for those who have taken part in foreign wars of aggression, when there was no attack from them on the shores of the U.S. But members of the System, that is, those from the professional "officer corps" and above certainly would, since there could be no such thing as a central in the pure . 17

15 Similarly, when captured by barbarian forces, the common soldiers were sometimes impressed into the new army, while the officers were typically killed.

16 This applies to both anarchists and minarchists. For these are legitimate roles that would be filled in the free society.

17 See Murray N. Rothbard, (1994), (The Mises Institute 1994); and Murray N. Rothbard, (Richardson and Snyder, 1983).

90 Reason Papers Vol. 28

Now consider functions of government that are legitimate, or, rather, would be were they carried out by private enterprise, such as the provision of roads, libraries, schools, museums, post office, welfare (private charity), health, hospitals, etc. It would be only people at the very top of these institutions who would be considered as members of the ruling class. For example, the Postmaster General and but a handful of his top administrators would be deemed guilty of violating the libertarian edict against non- aggression. True, private enterprise equivalents would or could exist, but we cannot forget that these people have taken a leading role in managing what is an illegitimate enterprise, if only because it is in the public sector. So, one general principle is that intrinsically evil government actions are to be penalized very heavily, reaching, down, for example, to the cop on the beat who busts a prostitute or drug dealer, but not to the handyman who fixes toilets in the police station, while for those functions that are not intrinsically evil (e.g., a government day care center) only those at the very top would be good candidates for membership in the guilty or ruling class. Another general principle is that the higher up you are placed in the hierarchy of government, the greater is the presumption that you are part of the ruling class. Let us illustrate this with a three-by-three matrix, offering three choices on the two dimensions of intrinsically evil, intermediate, and not intrinsically evil, with high, medium, and low options.

Evil : Yes Intermediate No

Degree : High A B C Medium D E F Low G H I

Let us suppose that A is the judge or legislator who promulgates the policy of setting free murderers and rapists who are guilty beyond any doubt at all on the totally frivolous and spurious grounds that they were not Mirandized, or that the arresting officers had no ground to search the premises of the murderer, 18 D is the police captain who orders his beat cop to carry out

18 Libertarians hold no brief with the thumbscrew school of interviewing prisoners. But if the police err in the enthusiasm of their interviewing techniques, then surely it is they who should be punished, proportionally to the crime committed. To allow a stipulated murderer or rapist to roam free as a result is surely a perversion of justice.

91 Reason Papers Vol. 28 this malevolent plan, and G is the jailer who sets free the murderer. 19 It is clear that A is by far the most guilty, D occupies an intermediate position, and that perhaps only a light penalty should be imposed upon G. Anti-trust is an illegitimate law, since people are punished who did not initiate any violence or theft against anyone else. 20 Again, the legislators, judges, and top prosecutors responsible for this occupy the top position of guilt, or B, the assistant prosecutors position E, and the professionals who take part in this judicial travesty (e.g., legal aides, assistants, researchers) position H. But promoting murder and rape are far more serious crimes against humanity than is punishing economic non-crimes such as monopolization. Therefore, the guilt level of A would be the most serious; B and D might be roughly equal, as are E and G. The Librarian of Congress, call him the Chief Librarian of the country, would occupy position C, and would achieve a level of guilt similar to that attained by E and G. In other words, there is a rate of exchange between height in the hierarchy and evilness of the deeds. A similar analysis would apply to several types of courts. If what a court is confined to doing is per se violations of human and property rights (e.g., courts upholding and promoting slavery in the pre-Civil War South, or

19 Remember that, under the libertarian code, a murderer owes a very heavy debt to the victim or his heirs. Anyone who allows him to escape is thus "stealing" from the latter.

20 On this point, see William Anderson, Walter Block, Thomas J. DiLorenzo, Ilana Mercer, Leon Snyman, and Christopher Westley, “The Microsoft Corporation in Collision with Antitrust Law,” The Journal of Social, Political and Economic Studies 26, no. 1 (Winter 2001), pp. 287-302; Dominick T. Armentano, The Myths of Antitrust (Arlington House, 1972); Dominick T. Armentano, Antitrust and Monopoly: Anatomy of a Policy Failure (Wiley, 1982); Dominick T. Armentano, Antitrust Policy: The Case for Repeal (The , 1991); Donald Armstrong, Competition versus Monopoly: Combines Policy in Perspective (The , 1982); Walter Block, Amending the Combines Investigation Act (The Fraser Institute, 1982); Walter Block, "Austrian Monopoly Theory – A Critique," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 1, no. 4 (Fall 1977), pp. 271-79; Walter Block, "Total Repeal of Anti-trust Legislation: A Critique of Bork, Brozen, and Posner," Review of Austrian Economics 8, no. 1 (1994), pp. 35-70; Thomas J. DiLorenzo, "The Myth of Natural Monopoly," Review of Austrian Economics 9, no. 2 (1997), pp. 43-58; Donald J. Boudreaux, and Thomas J. DiLorenzo, "The Protectionist Roots of Antitrust," Review of Austrian Economics 6, no. 2 (1992), pp. 81-96; Jack High, "Bork's Paradox: Static vs Dynamic Efficiency in Antitrust Analysis," Contemporary Policy Issues 3 (1984-1985), pp. 21-34; Fred McChesney, "Antitrust and Regulation: Chicago's Contradictory Views," 10 (1991); Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State (Nash, 1970); William F. Shugart II, "Don't Revise the Clayton Act, Scrap It!" Cato Journal , 6 (1987), p. 925; Fred L. Smith, Jr., "Why not Abolish Antitrust?" Regulation (Jan-Feb 1983), p. 23.

92 Reason Papers Vol. 28 landlord-tenant courts in a city with rent control), then guilt reaches further down into the hierarchy than for more ordinary courts, which combine legitimate functions (e.g., stopping crime with real victims) with illicit statist activity. Another complication is that all of this can be used only to establish a refutable presumption. For example, suppose that a Nazi German equivalent of our Saint Ron Paul were to become chief librarian to the country, in category C. Would he necessarily have to pay the moderate penalty appropriate for that position? Not necessarily. If he could prove that he was really a "mole," or an enemy of the evil state, working behind "enemy lines," he would certainly save himself from such a fate. For example, if he contributed money surreptitiously (but not anonymously) to libertarian causes, this would certainly be evidence in his favor. What about businessmen who are hand-in-glove with the apparatus of the state? According to Rand, 21 businessmen are "America's Most Persecuted Minority." What with the modern level of regulations, there is no doubt at least some truth to this contention. But the issue is far more complicated than this. For there are also businessmen active in the dissolution of the free-enterprise system. They do so, presumably, for ideological reasons of their own, or in order to attain a short-run profit advantage. 22 That is, they actively promote government intervention into the economy in general, and subsidies (and/or the reduction of competition against them) for themselves. The key element in guilt or innocence, unfortunately, is often motive. A ruling class businessman and an innocent one might undertake very similar or even the same acts (e.g., contributions to politicians, bribes to public officials, etc.). The difference is that the one is an initiator of the system, while the other only engages in such acts out of self-defense. How do we tell the difference between them? Evidence for the difference consists, in part, of the publications and speeches of the business executives. If they are promoting regulations to handicap their competitors, then this is an indication of ruling class behavior. As a first approximation, if they oppose subsidies to firms in their industry, but fight for them if others are given them, then this is evidence in the other direction. 23 How about if they voluntarily contribute money to the

21 Available online at http://www.free-market.net/features/pageoftheweek/98spring.html.

22 Gabriel Kolko, Triumph of (Quadrangle Books, 1963).

23 But see the discussion below of accepting government subsidies.

93 Reason Papers Vol. 28 government or to ruling class institutions such as Harvard 24 or Yale Universities? These acts would clearly support membership in the ruling class. Bill Gates 25 is an anomaly in this regard. On the one hand, some of his own signed editorials are very much in keeping with the free market philosophy, 26 while others are not 27 ; on the other hand, his charitable giving seems directed toward Harvard University, surely no bastion of laissez-faire capitalist thinking, and other similar institutions beloved of the liberal left.

24 I again remind the reader that the examples used in the text are not from the . Therefore, the names of the universities mentioned should be read as “the equivalent of Harvard and Yale in a country which has an illegitimate government, such as North Korea, Cuba, Nazi Germany, the USSR, etc."

25 Ditto. This should be read as “the equivalent of a Bill Gates character in a rogue country.”

26 Available online at http://home.labridge.com/~iicsla/politics/gates.htm; http://www.cato.org/gatesvisit.html.

27 Here is a question posed by the Marin Independent Journal (August 3, 1998), p. C5, followed by an answer from Bill Gates:

Q: “In a speech, you spoke of bringing citizens and the government into closer contact via a ‘digital nervous system.’ Don't you think that this concept is contrary to what people want—distance from the government?" A: “Government is pervasive, and most interactions people have with it are positive. Governments create order and provide services, including school and health systems. “Even if you don't personally reach out to the representatives of government, certain infrastructures and issues related to the rule of law are important to you. Nobody challenges the right of governments to issue a parking ticket, or to ask you to get a business license or a passport or to pay your real estate taxes. “Because we agree these are legitimate functions of government, why not use technology to make government more efficient, for the benefit of the people it serves—you and me? “As we make governments more efficient by equipping them with digital nervous systems, they'll have new potential to gather and consolidate information about and groups. This will give rise in many societies to explicit rules about what governments can or can't do with the information they accumulate.”

The problem here, it should be clear to any libertarian, is that there is nothing here that couldn't or wouldn't be articulated by Hillary or . This sort of thing will not save “a” Bill Gates from the libertarian tribunal.

94 Reason Papers Vol. 28

The foundation he has set up promotes almost entirely left-wing socialistic causes. What is the dividing line between universities in the ruling class and those apart from it? A first approximation is that all public institutions of higher learning are illegitimate. This follows directly from the fact that education is not a proper role for the state. But what of private colleges? Some are, some are not; Hillsdale College, Grove City College, and clearly fall outside of the realm of ruling class institutions. None of them accepts any government money whatsoever, not even scholarships directed at students. In that way, they are not subject to onerous rules such as those mandating affirmative action. 28 But ruling class status does not depend upon the amount of money received from the government, for, as we shall see below when we discuss Ragnar Danneskjold, it is licit for non- ruling class members to relieve the government of its ill-gotten gains. The criterion, then, must be something else, similar to that used to separate the business sheep from the business goats: principles espoused in speeches and publications on the part of the owners, boards of trustees, presidents, and other high officers of the establishment. Thus, Harvard, Yale, Princeton, and other Ivy Leaguers are members of the ruling class in good standing not because they accept (scads of) government money, but rather, because they are diploma mills for the government. They weave apologetics for its rule; they are safe houses for out- of-work politicians; they provide vast armadas of professorial talent to the government 29 for programs not compatible with libertarianism. University professors also furnish an interesting example with which to flesh out our theory. Those working at non-ruling class (non-public, and non-private but non-ruling class) institutions may profess on their own time and with their own anything they wish without falling afoul of libertarian sensibilities. The right of free speech, after all, protects them from violence no matter what they say. They can advocate the complete takeover of private initiatives if they wish, and libertarianism stands foursquare behind their right to mouth such platitudes. However, the presumption of innocence vanishes when one enters the halls of a ruling class institution. Now, a bit more care needs to be taken. Publications and speeches no longer need be interpreted purely as a matter of

28 All, however, were among the earliest to accept blacks and women as students and teachers.

29 G. William Domhoff, The Higher Circles: The Governing Class in America (Vintage Books, 1971); G. William Domhoff, Who Rules America ? (Prentice-Hall, 1967).

95 Reason Papers Vol. 28 free speech. In this venue the professor is part of an apparatus that is engaged in a massive enterprise of rights violations. He indulges in his free speech only at his own risk. It is the difference between a Nazi scribbler on his own and as part of the public relations apparatus of the German regime. The role of "court historian" is a pivotal one, potentially a dangerous one. 30 What is proper behavior in the modern mixed economy? In a word, it is to act in such a way as not to invite the negative attention of the future libertarian Nuremberg tribunal. If you want to go "behind enemy lines," so to speak, and become a bureaucrat, an advisor, a judge, a politician, or a general in the army, then clear it with at least one libertarian who stays "out" of the closet. Do this, or risk becoming indistinguishable from real anti-libertarians. 31 Don't do anything evil per se. If you join the FBI, then don't shoot or fire-bomb innocent people at places like Waco or Ruby Ridge. Don't become a murderous bastard. Don't violate libertarian law in any way. If you are a prosecuting attorney, then don't take on drug cases. If you are a cop, then don't arrest prostitutes (or Johns). If you are a faculty member in a ruling class institution, then don't profess statism, unless it is on your own time, separate from any organized criminal behavior such as occurs at all state universities and most "private" ones (e.g., the ones that are part of the ruling class). In the free society, there will of course be policemen, prosecuting attorneys, and professors, but not ones who act incompatibly with the libertarian strictures of non-aggression.

6. Proper Relations between the Subjects and the Government Let us consider a series of cases under the rubric set out in the previous subsection. Should the libertarian use the public sidewalks? At first glance, this would appear to be a trap for the follower of this philosophy. For in the ideal fully free society, there would be no such thing as socialized sidewalks. All would be privatized. It would appear, then, that for the libertarian who favors to nevertheless utilize governmental

30 Available online at http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1541; http://www.mises.org/blockonmnr.asp; http://www.mises.org/misesreview_detail.asp?control=28&sortorder=issue.

31 At the risk of being overly repetitive, I again reiterate that the only countries under discussion for a future Nuremberg trial on libertarian principles in this essay are those with “bandit” governments, such as Mao’s China, Stalin’s Russia, Pol Pot’s Cambodia, Hitler’s Germany, and Castro’s Cuba.

96 Reason Papers Vol. 28 amenities of this sort is the rankest of hypocrisy. "Why can't you act consistently with your own principles?" the critic might ask. 32 There are more than mere sidewalks at stake, here. For this problem applies to everything now provided by the state for the anarchist libertarian, and to everything except courts, armies, and police for the minarchist. Were the libertarian forced by the logic of his own premises to eschew everything from roads to libraries to schools to museums to baseball stadiums to welfare offices to social security benefits to unemployment insurance to use of U.S. fiat currency, he would be driven to lead a very narrow and constricted life, one, perhaps, of complete hermitage. Unfortunately, the libertarian response to this challenge has been less than fully satisfying. For example, states Jane Shaw, "I cringe at the thought of well-off and able-bodied friends accepting unemployment compensation, but I generally accept the fact that there is no immorality in receiving what's available. I expect to receive Social Security. I do not think that we must all be as high-minded as and reject it." 33 There are problems here. If it is moral to accept government largesse, why the "cringing"? If it is "high-minded" to reject statist benefits, then there must be at least some immorality involved in accepting it. It would appear that there is more than just a little bit of ambivalence involved in this perspective. The problem comes about, I contend, due to failure to perceive (excessive) government as a criminal activity. Once we realize that the state is nothing more than a puffed-up robber gang with great spin-doctors, 34 relations with it become clear. Suppose that the local Mafia, or Blood, or Crips, or Jesse James Gang were to come around to your neighborhood, force you and all your neighbors to pay for sidewalks or a retirement plan, and then actually spend some small proportion of the "swag" on these amenities in your behalf.

32 For another reply, see Roy Whitehead and Walter Block, “Direct Payment of State Scholarship Funds to Church-Related Colleges Offends the Constitution and Title VI,” Brigham Young University Journal of Public Law 14, no. 2 (2000), pp. 191-207.

33 Jane Shaw, "Responsibility and the State," Liberty Magazine (September 1998), p. 10.

34 All right. Give the devil his due. I refer to no less than the best public relations efforts in the history of the universe. Who else could fool the populace into believing that the institution that has murdered more innocents than any other is actually our friend? R. J. Rummel, Death by Government (Transaction, 1996), calculates the total number of noncombatants killed by their own governments during the twentieth century as 169,198,000.

97 Reason Papers Vol. 28

Would you have any reservations at all about accepting this largesse, which you had paid for in the first place? Not at all. It was theft, pure and simple, on their part. In allowing you to avail yourself of these programs, you are merely engaging in a bit of returning stolen property. You would have no compunctions about this at all. It would not at all be "high-minded" to refuse. "Cringing" would be the last thing on your mind. You might admire the audacity of the gang in thinking they could actually buy your good will by returning a small part of what they had stolen from you, but there would be absolutely no guilt involved on your part in accepting their largesse, which stemmed, originally, from your pocket. But let us pursue this example further. Would you have any moral reservations about breaking into this gang's warehouse in the middle of the night, assuming that you could get away with it for sure, and relieve them of their ill-gotten booty? No more so than with any other gang, criminal conspiracy, or group of pirates. These people are the lowest of the low, and pretty much anything you do to or against them will be more than fully deserved. We can also see that the proper reply to the question of why libertarians are justified in walking on public sidewalks even though they oppose them cannot be answered by resort to legality. That is, the fact that it is legal to traverse public sidewalks is no answer at all. For , as enacted, that is, de jure law, is what they have determined it should be. There is a higher law, libertarian law, and the laws of the land, particularly of rogue states such as Nazi Germany, Stalin’s USSR, etc., are of no moment at all. Their doctrine is that of legal positivism, that is, whatever the law is, that is the correct law; this doctrine deserves to be consigned to the dust bin of legal theory. Were we to accord any credence to this theory at all, this would sound the death knell of the Nuremberg trials, whether on a libertarian basis or any other. For, according to legal positivism, whatever the law is, it is justified. So, too, would be the argument: “But I was only following (legal) orders.” The real Nuremberg trials gave the back of their hands to this claim, and very properly so. As it happens, the Nazis came to power not through a coup d'etat , but rather, as a result of democratic elections . So much, therefore, says the libertarian, for democratic elections. Merely because a majority of people can be fooled, or inspired, or convinced of anything at all, this does not make it right. Were a good justification for anything, it could be used (horrors!) to defend Nazi depredations. Nor was there ever any prior

98 Reason Papers Vol. 28 agreement to be bound by ensuing elections, which would indeed lend them some much needed libertarian legitimacy. 35 But suppose that a stranger came to your neighborhood and passed by on the sidewalk. He had made no financial contribution to the creation of the sidewalk, since he did not live in the area under the control of the gang. Would he have any right to walk on this public property? Or, were he to be able to break into the gang's warehouse and take some of their stolen property, would he be in the right in doing so? For the libertarian, these are questions it is easy to answer in the positive. For if there is anything clear, it is that the gang is the sole "bad guy" in this little scenario, and that anything done to them, up to and including exacting two teeth for a tooth from them, would be justified. The point is that while "getting my own money back" is indeed a sufficient justification for relieving the state of its ill-gotten gains, it is by no means a necessary one. Anyone , whether stolen from by the government or not, is justified in taking from the public coffers. 36 Note my steadfast refusal to refer to taking from the government as "stealing." This is because, as a matter of logic, it is only possible to steal from the rightful owner. When one relieves the thief (e.g., the illicit government) of what it had itself stolen from the citizenry, 37 this is not theft, but a transfer of funds away from robbers. It is a logical impossibility, a veritable misuse of language, to describe taking from a thief as "robbery." Thieves are by the laws of logic prevented from stealing from those who are not the rightful owners; from them, they can only "liberate" or "transfer from," but never “steal.” But what of the original and rightful owners, those whose private property it was before the renegade government stole from them? Shouldn't the liberator of state property return what he has taken from governmental coffers to these people? Let us put this in letter format. A stands for the rightful owner, B stands for the evil government which has stolen A's property through taxation,

35 On this point, see , No Treason (Ralph Myles, 1966 [1870]); Roberta A. Modugno and Murray N. Rothbard, e l'anarco-capitalismo americano (Soveria Mannelli, 1998).

36 The headline of the U.S. News and World Report of August 3, 1998, states: "Dirty Diamonds: How the FBI and some Honest Moscow Cops Broke Up a Ring that was Looting Tons of Gold and Gems from the Russian National Treasury." Had this applied to the evil empire U.S.S.R., then, according to the logic of this article, it would have been fully justified.

37 Yet again, here is a reminder. We are now limiting our discussion to countries such as the old U.S.S.R., Cuba, North Korea, and Nazi Germany.

99 Reason Papers Vol. 28 and C depicts the heroic Ragnar Danneskjold, 38 who relieves B of its booty. One important question which arises is, Must C return the stolen property back to its rightful owner, A? And the libertarian answer to this question is, Yes, but . . . . Yes, but what? There are several complications. First of all, let us get one thing straight. Even if Danneskjold does not return the property to the rightful owner, 39 the situation is far improved, from a libertarian point of view, compared to the one where he does not get into the act at all and the government, B, keeps the entire swag. Let us put this into hierarchical order.

I. The best case scenario: B steals money from A; C takes money from B and returns it to A. II. The next best case: B steals money from A; C takes money from B and keeps it for himself. III. The worst case: B steals money from A; C does nothing; B keeps its prize.

Yes, we do well to dwell on the fact that I is preferable to II from a libertarian perspective. However, let us spend a little time, also, in contemplation of the undeniable fact that II is also vastly preferable to III, which is the status quo in all too many cases. Surely, it is better that a non - thief, Danneskjold, end up with the valuables, than that a thief , the government, be placed in this position. The second complication is as follows. How much of the stolen property that C just took from B does he have to return to A? At first glance, this seems simple. Why, all of it, is the easy response. A utilitarian consideration, perhaps not even worthy of mention, is that if C has to return all of A's losses to him, then he has no financial incentive to beard the den of B and relieve him of his improper enrichment. B, after all, is a powerful, evil government. It is no mean attainment to be able to break into (a non-U.S.) Fort Knox and transfer money out of that stronghold. If all of it must go back to A, only benevolence will be the motivator of this act in the first place. But we all know what Adam Smith 40 said about benevolence. Surely, we would

38 , (Random House, 1957).

39 We are, of course, now assuming that this rightful owner is not a member of the ruling class. If he is, then his claim over this property is greatly and perhaps fatally compromised.

40 Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Modern Library, 1965 [1776]), pp. 26-27: "It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity but of their

100 Reason Papers Vol. 28 do well to consider, also, self-interest, particularly if we want to encourage relieving the state of its illegitimate gains. But this, as I say, is merely a utilitarian consideration. More to the point, C is owed something for undertaking this Herculean task. There is a principled justification for allowing Danneskjold to keep part of what he returns. This is based on the law of the sea merchant, which is a part of the common law. 41 When ships are lost at sea, the common practice, instituted throughout many centuries and thus entrenched in the common law, was for the salvager to keep one third of the value of what he turned over to the original owner. I suggest that we borrow a leaf from this tried and true practice, and apply it to the present situation. Accordingly, C would be compelled, on pain of violating libertarian law, to return only 2/3 to A 42 of what he takes from the coffers of B. 43 advantages"; see also, Arthur Seldon and Ralph Harris, "Not from Benevolence: Twenty Years of Economic Dissent" (Institute for Economic Affairs, 1977).

41 Bruce L. Benson, "The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial Law," Southern Economic Journal 55 (1989), pp. 644-61; Bruce L. Benson, The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State (Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); Bruce L. Benson, "Customary Law as a Social Contract: International Commercial Law," Constitutional 2 (1992), pp. 1-27; Bruce L. Benson, "The Impetus for Recognizing Private Property and Adopting Ethical Behavior in a Market Economy: , Government Law, or Evolving Self Interest," The Review of Austrian Economics 6, no. 2 (1993), pp. 43-80.

42 I am unable to intellectually justify 2/3 as opposed to 1/2 or 3/4 or 4/5. This is in sharp distinction to the case of two teeth for a tooth.

43 This case must be distinguished from another one with the same 1/3-2/3 split. During the epoch of U.S. slavery, white masters in effect stole labor from blacks, and used this to enhance the value of their holdings. Full justice at the end of the Civil War would have implied the application of "two teeth for a tooth" against the masters on behalf of their slaves. But what can be done at present, some 150 years later? The land that white grandfather W passed on to his son, W', which is now in the hands of the grandson, W'', should instead have been given to slave B, who, in the ordinary course of events would have bequeathed this to his son, B'. In justice, B'', the black grandson of the slave would now be in possession of this property. The libertarian answer is to now change the present pattern of property titles so as to as closely as possible approximate what would have obtained were we able to promote justice at the earliest possible moment. What this means, specifically, is that the land which embodies the labor of B should be taken away from W'' and turned over to B''. W'' is himself innocent of the crime of slave holding (e.g., kidnapping); thus, this is not a punishment directed against him. But W'' is now sitting on property which, in justice, never should have been given to him in the first place. He must vacate it.

101 Reason Papers Vol. 28

Let us now consider an attempted reductio ad absurdum of the libertarian perspective on justice in property titles. I have been employed as a college professor for a governmental institution. 44 Let us suppose further that I came from another country, 45 and thus there was no question of getting my own money back, or that which my parents had spent in my behalf, from the state. You now approach me and demand 1/3 of my salary (your buddies wait behind you to also insist on their 1/3 of my rapidly decreasing funds). Have I a leg to stand on, or must I give in to your demands? There are several possible responses. First, why don't you go and get your money directly from the criminals, not from those, such as myself, who are themselves acting in opposition to them? Under the theory of the enemy of my enemy is my friend, you are, in attacking me in this way, supporting the state. That is, you are removing my economic incentive to relieve the state of its illicit gains. Thus, you perhaps reveal yourself as a member of the ruling class.

Suppose that this land is worth $1 million, but W'' has erected a house on it with a value of one-half million dollars. He did so with his own rightful earnings. Who should get what? The answer is that W'' should keep 1/3 of the total value, and B'' 2/3. This familiar set of fractions does not emanate from salvage considerations, but merely from the accident of these numbers. For more on this point, see Murray N. Rothbard, “The Problem of Land Theft,” in The Ethics of Liberty (New York University Press, 1998), pp. 63-67; see also Walter Block and Guillermo Yeatts, “The Economics and Ethics of Land Reform: A Critique of the Pontifical Council for Justice and Peace’s ‘Toward a Better Distribution of Land: The Challenge of Agrarian Reform,’” Journal of Natural Resources and Environmental Law 15, no. 1 (1999-2000), pp. 37-69. Consider another complication. Suppose that 100 slaves worked on the plantation, but only one heir of any of them, B'', can now be found. Does B'' get the entire value of the landed estate (apart from the house), or only one percent of it. The answer is the latter. For possession is 9/10ths of the law. He who is the present land holder (W'' in our case) is always deemed to be the proper owner, unless evidence to the contrary can be adduced. But the claim of B'', stemming from the work of his grandfather, B, can at most encompass what he, B, that is, contributed to the enhancement of the value of the property. The other ninety-nine percent of the value of this land will remain with W'', until and unless other grandchildren of slaves come forth with proof of parentage.

44 It is full confession time. As it happens, during my career as an academic, I have been employed by the following fully public institutions: Stony Brook SUNY, CUNY, Rutgers Newark, and the University of Central Arkansas. I have also been employed by Holy Cross College, which is clearly "ruling class" in terms of the present analysis, in that it takes anti-free-enterprise institutional positions.

45 Or a different planet, as some of my detractors might suppose.

102 Reason Papers Vol. 28

Second, I owe at most only 1/3 of any property I took from the government, not a series of 1/3 of what I have remaining from this amount to all and sundry. Once I have paid this amount, I owe no more. Third, while I owe 1/3 to some victim of state aggrandizement, it need not be you . I can if I wish choose the victim I wish to compensate. In the novel Atlas Shrugged , Danneskjold chose Hank Rearden as the person he first wished to compensate out of liberated funds. Surely, this choice would, similarly, be up to me, given that I am in this position. Fourth, this consideration will only disrupt the financial incentive libertarian professors have in working for the state, given the assumption that the government has not all along been taxing them. It is only a possible reductio , that is, for those from another country—given no entangling relations between their host and original nations, which is another unlikely assumption. 46

7. Disrupting Government a. Destruction Is it legitimate to disrupt government, to destroy its property? Of course; remember that we are discussing such states as the USSR, Cuba, North Korea, and Nazi Germany. Why ever would it not be licit to interfere with these evil empires, and as much as ever possible? Let us consider libraries, for the moment. Here, we are not discussing a libertarian borrowing a book, even though he opposes public libraries; we have already answered the possible charge of hypocrisy. Nor, yet, are we thinking about borrowing a book, not returning it, and somehow escaping the payment of a fine. We are asking whether it is legitimate to blow up the public library. And the answer must be in the affirmative for the libertarian, but subject to one constraint: no innocent persons must perish, or

46 What of the argument that if the state taxes people, then it at least returns to them services which, by the very nature of things, are at best far more valuable than what was taken? If so, then there is no warrant to consider the government as a thief, nor that it has any "ill-gotten" gains of which it would be justified to relieve it. This argument cannot be accepted, because the chief element in proving benefits is mutual agreement. That is, if I trade you my tie for your pen, then the outside economist is forced to conclude that I value your pen more than my tie (otherwise, why would I give up my tie for your pen?) and that you make the opposite evaluation. But if we were forced to make this trade, then no such conclusion would be warranted. As all dealings between government and are under duress, we can never conclude that they are beneficial.

103 Reason Papers Vol. 28 even be (physically) harmed, as they were at the blowing up in 1995 of the Murrah Building in Oklahoma. 47 Let us consider a few objections to the foregoing view. First, it is one thing for Danneskjold to liberate government property, and to do so without destroying it; in this way, he could always, at least in principle, return it to its rightful owners. But when C destroys the property now in B's hands, which actually belongs to A, then the very possibility of return is destroyed as well. Therefore, it is never justified to destroy government property. The problem with this objection is that it is no longer A's property; it is now , actually, the property of the state . Of course, it is still the legitimate possession of A; this can never change. 48 But that is entirely irrelevant to the point that, but for libertarian activity to the contrary, this bit of property will remain in state hands, presumably to be used for evil purposes. Surely, it is preferable that the property be destroyed rather than be used by the government to reduce human welfare. Here is another case. Danneskjold is about to toss a hand grenade at a Nazi German Panzer tank, when along comes A, who argues, "No, don't do it! One thousandth of the value of that tank belongs to me. If you destroy the tank, you will be destroying my property, and I refuse you permission to do so." There are difficulties with this objection, too. For A is taking the part of the ruling class, no matter how innocent he may have been of such a charge before his recent rash action of defending the tank against Danneskjold 's onslaught. The point is that there is not here an option to melt down the tank into 1,000 bits of equal value and return them all to their rightful owners. Rather, the only options are to blow it up now or stand by and allow this implement of war to be used for nefarious Nazi purposes. If the owner still insists upon leaving the tank as is, so that it can be used to kill good guys, then he becomes converted, himself, into genus ruling class member, species Nazi bad guy. This is enough, more than enough, to override his initial claim as a legitimate property owner. b. Seizure Similarly, it would be quite within keeping of the libertarian philosophy for a group of citizens to go out and seize part of a public highway, 49 thus converting it to the private sector. This group could then

47 Ayn Rand depicted, positively, a similar episode (i.e., blowing up a public housing project) in her novel .

48 There are no statutes of limitation on justice in libertarianism.

49 This would not be justified under the doctrine of “just war” of Catholic social thought unless those who engaged in this activity were unable to achieve their just goals in a peaceful way, the gains were more than commensurate with the risks, etc.

104 Reason Papers Vol. 28 charge tolls, improve the roadway, impose speed limits, penalize drunken drivers, etc., just like any other entrepreneur could manage his own property. Alternatively, they would be well within their rights to destroy any stretch of government highway they could put their hands on. There are several other sorts of seizure that come to mind. A libertarian could be a squatter in public housing, or could organize a "sit in" at a state museum or park. And then there is the famous "bum in the library" controversy. Here, a smelly bum comes into a library, sits down, and starts reading a book. Due to his odoriferousness, however, no one else can sit comfortably within 100 feet of him. There are some commentators, such as Hans-Hermann Hoppe, who maintain that the bum should be thrown out on his rear end, 50 that, in effect, we should treat public property exactly as we do its private counterpart. Since no private library owner in his right mind would allow his establishment to be overrun with bums, this should apply as well to public libraries. There are difficulties here, however. We may well agree with that, as a matter of managerial considerations, it is not at all good business practice to allow the bum access to one's premises. But this is pretty much beside the point. The real question is, Does the private owner have a right to admit bums to his place of business, whether or not it maximizes profits? The obvious answer is, "Yes, he does." If so, then it cannot be shown that putting public property on a business basis yields the conclusion that the bum must be tossed out. As well, Rothbard is on record in opposing for very good reason putting government commercial activities on a business basis. He states: "Government . . . has no checkrein on itself, i.e., no requirement of meeting a test of profit-and-loss or valued service to consumers . . . ." 51 Why these considerations should not apply to the present case is unclear. Another difficulty with this position emerges when we consider the ownership status of government property, that is, it is not being used for legitimate state purposes. Since both anarchist and minarchist libertarians

On this issue, see available online at http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/j/justwar.htm. Libertarianism, in contrast, is not bound in this manner.

50 Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Democracy—The God That Failed: The Economics and of Monarchy, Democracy, and Natural Order (Transaction Publishers, 2001), pp. 180-81.

51 Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State , pp. 821-22. See, more generally, ibid., “The Fallacy of Government on a ‘Business Basis,’” pp. 821-25. See also, Murray N. Rothbard, “Government in Business,” Freeman (September 1956), pp. 39-41, reprinted in Essays on Liberty IV (Foundation for Economic Education, 1958), pp. 183-87.

105 Reason Papers Vol. 28 would agree that this applies to public libraries, the analysis is straightforward: The library is un-owned property, despite statist claims to the contrary. It is thus there for the taking. It would be licit for anyone , not himself a member of the ruling class, to seize this property. Surely, a bum qualifies in this regard. But if the bum may seize library property, then surely he may occupy it for a time. 52 c. "Cheating" Is it okay to cheat on your income taxes? You bet it is. It is not quite a duty, that is, you are not required to resist acting under duress, 53 but it at least a virtue. 54 If you can evade road tolls, then this too is a good deed. The less money there is in the coffers of the criminal state, the better. This reasoning also holds with regard to bus fares. And, if you can manage it, this also goes for museum entry fees, paying for credits at state universities, sneaking into governmental recreation centers, etc. What about cheating on exams in public schools? The same analysis applies. These are not legitimate institutions. Therefore, their rules may be disobeyed with moral impunity. Imagine the bloody cheek of a criminal band of thieves insisting upon virtue from those in their thrall. The state may have the de facto power to penalize you for any of these acts, and on pragmatic grounds you might do well not to act in this supererogatory manner, but that is entirely another matter. As far as virtue 55 is concerned, it is all on the side of resisting the power of the tyrant, not knuckling under to it. Of course, none of this applies to private institutions. To cheat on private school exams, or to steal from them (e.g., by evading their legitimate demands for payment), is the very paradigm case of violation of libertarian principles. The reason this does not apply in the case of the (rogue) government is that this institution is itself in violation of these norms of civilized behavior.

52 We need not (but will) add the proviso that we are limiting our discussion to public libraries in the U.S.S.R., Cuba, North Korea, and Nazi Germany.

53 At least when it comes to paying taxes to rogue governments. However, if a marauder pulls a gun on you, and threatens to shoot you (or a loved one) unless you kill another innocent person in your sights, then libertarianism requires you to refrain (assuming these are the only options). If he kills someone, then that is on his head. You , as a libertarian, cannot do any such thing. If you do, then you cease to be acting as a libertarian.

54 Let it be repeated here once again that we are discussing the U.S.S.R., Nazi Germany, North Korea, and Cuba, not the U.S., Canada, Great Britain, Australia, or any other country I might ever visit or reside in.

55 For a very different view of virtue, see William Bennett, The Book of Virtues (Simon & Schuster, 1993).

106 Reason Papers Vol. 28

Counterfeiting, too, is entirely justified 56 on these grounds. It is one thing to fraudulently substitute a fake currency for a real one, e.g., gold backed notes. But fiat currency is entirely a different matter. 57 Here, the government has already engaged in counterfeiting, in effect, in supplanting its own fake currency for the gold backed dollar. Thus, anyone who now comes along and counterfeits statist currency is actually counterfeiting counterfeit currency, which can be no crime—at least according to libertarian law. 58 We can borrow a leaf from warring governments in this regard. One of the many arrows in their quiver is to destabilize the country with which they are at war. There are records, for example, in the attempt of the allies and the axis powers to destabilize each others’ economies by flooding their enemy with vast amounts of counterfeit currency. 59 If this is good enough medicine for one illegitimate government, then why not for others? And if this is justified when done by one state against another, then why not by disaffected libertarians within a given illicit country? d. Political assassination We have seen that in the libertarian philosophy, the death penalty is justified for those whose crimes rise to a sufficient degree of severity. Surely, there are heads of state whose evil deeds many times eclipse such a level. Thus, it would altogether be justified to end their lives by violence. How many novels have been written with a motif of, What would have happened had Hitler been assassinated, during different epochs of his career? There is no doubt that the lives of Hitler, Pol Pot, Stalin, Lenin, Mao, Castro, etc. were morally forfeit, that it would have been the highest form of justice to end them. Were there a case in Nazi Germany equivalent to Ruby Ridge or Waco and the Davidians, then, only those directly responsible for the murder of innocent civilians would be liable for the death penalty, not their fellow

56 See Walter Block, pp. 109-20.

57 On this, see Murray N. Rothbard, What has Government Done to Our Money? (Mises Institute, 1990); Murray N. Rothbard, “The Case For a 100 Percent Gold Dollar,” in In Search of a Monetary Constitution . ed. Leland Yeager, (Harvard University Press, 1962), pp. 94-136. Reprinted as The Case For a 100 Percent Gold Dollar (Libertarian Review Press, 1974); Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Guido Hulsmann, and Walter Block, "Against Fiduciary Media," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 1, no. 1 (1998), pp. 19-50.

58 This case exactly parallels the fact that you can only steal from the rightful owner. You cannot steal from the thief; you can only liberate the property from him.

59 See available online at http://www.ess.uwe.ac.uk/documents/eight.htm.

107 Reason Papers Vol. 28 colleagues in arms. 60 It is simply not the case, for example, that all U.S. servicemen posted in were responsible for the My Lai massacre. This applies only to those who actually pulled the relevant triggers. And, of course, this also applies to those who gave the orders, or "took responsibility" for these outrages. The Nuremberg trials quite properly focused attention on the generals who gave the orders, even in preference to those closer to the ground who were more directly responsible. If there were a Nazi German or Soviet Janet Reno who "took responsibility" for an abomination of this sort, then that person, certainly, would also fall under this purview.

8. Conclusion Among the worst possible roles for the libertarian to play is that of being an efficiency expert for the state, under the guise of promoting economic and civil freedom. In many cases, this is all too easy a trap in which to fall. The government is so obviously inefficient. It is a matter of almost child's play to see the flaws in its operation, and to set them straight. In what follows, I should like to defend myself against the possible charge of violating this edict. Starting in the 1980s, I published a spate of articles advocating the privatization of roads, highways, streets, sidewalks, and other pedestrian and vehicular thoroughfares. 61 I made the moral case in behalf of this initiative, tried to show how it might function economically speaking, and defended it against possible objections. But, in so doing, I discussed why private road owners would be led by Adam Smith's "invisible hand" in the direction of making innovations that would improve safety records and other functioning of government highways. In this vein I made a number of specific suggestions—speculations, really—as to how entrepreneurial management might improve matters. For example, I maintained that road owners might well install peak load pricing in order to iron out demand over rush hour times, and impose electronic credit card charges, instead of utilizing the present very inefficient highway toll booths. I am not at all grandiose enough to think that these initiatives were and have been recently introduced because of my writings. Yet, there is some disquiet. Should I have kept silent, lest, inadvertently, I contributed to the better functioning of an enterprise that is at bottom illegitimate? In my view, in order to answer this conundrum, we need to return to basic libertarian principles of non-aggression against non-aggressors. In

60 Needless to say at this point, we are limiting our focus on countries such as the U.S.S.R., North Korea, Cuba, and Nazi Germany. As the U.S. government is not on this list, the cases in that country are mentioned for illustrative purposes only.

61 See my articles cited in note 13 above.

108 Reason Papers Vol. 28 trying to demonstrate the virtue of private ownership of highways by pointing out how entrepreneurs might improve matters, I violated no personal or private property rights. If the civil service managers of these amenities saw fit to adapt some suggestions made in this regard to their own nefarious purposes, then a commentator in my position is still blameless. It is as if invented the automobile, and a criminal utilized one as a getaway car from a robbery; we would hardly blame the automobile manufacturer for the robbery. But this is to be sharply distinguished from actually going out and advising governments 62 with the goal of improving their management of that which they should not be managing in the first place.

62 See text associated with notes 14-16 above.

109