The Effect of Perceived Similarity on Sequential Risk-Taking

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Effect of Perceived Similarity on Sequential Risk-Taking THE EFFECT OF PERCEIVED SIMILARITY ON SEQUENTIAL RISK-TAKING ELIZABETH C. WEBB* SUZANNE B. SHU * (corresponding author) Elizabeth C. Webb ([email protected]) is Assistant Professor of Marketing at Columbia Business School, Columbia University, 511 Uris Hall, New York, NY 10027, (212) 854-7864. Suzanne B. Shu ([email protected]) is Associate Professor of Marketing at The Anderson School of Management, University of California, 110 Westwood Plaza, Los Angeles, CA 90095, (310) 825-4818. Author Note This work is part of the first author’s dissertation. Acknowledgement The authors would like to thank Stephen Spiller, Marissa Sharif, Scott Shriver, Eric Johnson, Robert Zeithammer, Mariam Hambarchyan, Katelyn Wirtz, Ashley Culver, Melanie Argoff, Carly Lenniger, The BDM Lab group at UCLA Anderson, and seminar participants at Columbia University and Stanford University for their encouraging comments and support throughout the research process. 1 THE EFFECT OF PERCEIVED SIMILARITY ON SEQUENTIAL RISK-TAKING Abstract We examine how perceived similarity between sequential risks affects individuals’ risk-taking behavior. Specifically, in six studies we find that in sequential choice settings individuals exhibit significant positive state dependence in risk-taking: they are more likely to take a risk when it is similar to a previously taken risk than when it is dissimilar. For example, if an individual has previously taken a health/safety risk, that individual is more likely to take a second health/safety risk than a second risk that is in the financial domain. Since similarity between risks is malleable and can be determined by situational and contextual variables, we show that we can change subsequent risk-taking behavior in a predictable manner by manipulating similarity through framing. Finally, we establish that state dependent risk-taking behavior is driven by increased feelings of self-efficacy and self-signaling through the prior risk-taking experience. We further show that the effect of similarity on preferences is not moderated by the outcome received in the prior risk and holds controlling for individual-level and domain-specific heterogeneity. Taken together, our results demonstrate that the similarity structures that exist between risks have a significant effect on risk-taking preferences in dynamic choice settings. Keywords: risk, domain-specificity, sequential choice, similarity 2 INTRODUCTION Every day individuals encounter risks of different types and must decide whether or not to engage in those risks. What factors affect these decisions? Economic theory proposes that an individual’s risk attitude is generally stable. As a result, risk-taking should not be affected by how a risky prospect is framed or by how it fits among other past or future risks. An alternative approach is a psychological model in which risk-taking is driven by an affect-based assessment of the level of risk associated with a given choice. In this model, both risk perception and preference vary by domain such that the same individual can be risk-seeking in one domain but risk averse in another, ceteris paribus. In other words, the individual who likes to gamble at casinos (a financial risk) is not necessarily the same person who enjoys skydiving (a recreational risk). But can an individual’s risk preferences be further affected by the relationships between sequential risky prospects? For example, is an individual more or less likely to take a given risk dependent on how similar it is to a risk she has taken before? Broadly, the research at hand is about how current risk-taking intentions relate to prior risky choices. Research on sequential risk-taking has found that risk-taking increases when a choice is part of a combined set of sequential or simultaneous risks, rather than an isolated decision (Benartzi and Thaler 1999; Gneezy and Potters 1997; Haisley, Mostafa, and Loewenstein 2008; Moher and Koehler 2010; Read, Loewenstein, and Rabin 1999; Redelmeier and Tversky 1992; Thaler et al. 1997; Webb and Shu 2017; Wedell and Böckenholt 1994). However, most of this research has held similarity between the risks constant by focusing on identical risks. What happens if the risks in a decision sequence are not identical but rather represent varying degrees of similarity? The research presented here brings together several of these features of risk-taking—similarity, domain-specificity, sequential choice—to explore how individuals’ attitudes towards risk are affected by the similarity structures that exist between risks considered in a sequence. For example, imagine the risk of riding a bicycle without a helmet. An individual who remembers taking a similar risk before (such as riding in a car without a seatbelt) will be more likely to ride a bicycle without a helmet than if that same individual instead remembers taking a dissimilar risk (such as investing in a speculative stock). 3 Controlling for existing preferences, sequential dynamics, and individual-level and domain-specific heterogeneity, we manipulate similarity to show positive state dependence in risk-taking intentions. We incorporate the findings related to domain-specific risk-taking by examining risks of several different types (financial, recreational, social, health/safety, and ethical) and show that, while sequential aggregation can increase risk-taking likelihood generally, similarity between risks is an important moderator of the effect. While similarity determines which risks individuals are more inclined to take, it is also a variable that can be directly manipulated. Since similarity is malleable and can be affected by contextual factors, this ultimately means that the decision to take a given risk can be manipulated by changing similarity between that risk and a prior risk. For example, the risk of riding a motorcycle without a helmet can be framed as a recreational risk or as a health/safety risk by highlighting different facets of the activity (e.g., the possible adrenaline rush versus the freedom of not wearing a helmet). If framed as a recreational risk, then our theory predicts that individuals will feel more open to another recreational risk; however, if framed as a health/safety risk, our theory predicts that individuals will feel more open to another health/safety risk instead. Thus, holding the prior risk in a sequence constant, we can change subsequent risk-taking intentions for a current risk by manipulating its similarity with that prior risk. While we show positive state dependence in risk-taking and how to manipulate it, we are also interested in the process behind this effect. We propose that similarity between a current risk and a prior risk (1) increases feelings of self-efficacy through experience and familiarity for risks of the same type; and (2) signals to the individual that they prefer risks of a given type more than risks of other types. We show that this shift is occurring through risk attitude since risk perception (subjective beliefs about the level of risk inherent in the activity) does not change with differences in similarity. In other words, individuals do not believe that risks that are more similar to a prior risk are less risky than risks that are dissimilar to that prior risk. Taken together, our empirical results suggest that perceived similarity is an important determinant of risk-taking intentions and that these intentions can be affected by factors that change perceived similarity. 4 What value is this deeper understanding of risk to marketers? While psychological models of risk-taking account for risk type and have shown that risk attitude is highly dependent on the type of risk being considered, none have accounted for the potential malleability of risk type in affecting future behavior. If risk type can be manipulated through framing, this suggests that an individual’s likelihood of taking a risk (e.g., trying a new product, switching brands, not purchasing a warranty) can be increased or decreased by changing its perceived similarity to a prior risk. THEORETICAL BACKGROUND How does an individual decide to take a risk? First, the choice must be assessed to determine how risky it is. This assessment, risk perception, is a subjective judgment that represents the beliefs or feelings individuals have about the level of risk inherent in the prospect under consideration (Blais and E. Weber 2006; Holtgrave and E. Weber 1993; Mellers, Schwartz, and E. Weber 1997; Slovic, Fischoff, and Lichtenstein 1978; E. Weber and Hsee 1998; E. Weber, Blais, and Betz 2002). Risk perception has been shown to account for much of the variance in risk preferences across individuals (E. Weber and Hsee 1998; E. U. Weber and Milliman 1997; E. Weber, Blais, and Betz 2002). Risk perception by itself is not enough to determine whether a risk will be taken, however, since two individuals who perceive the same level of risk may still make different choices about that risk. Individual differences in preferences for risk- taking beyond risk perception can come from differences in risk attitude. Within the economics literature, risk attitude is a stable facet of behavior determined by an expected-utility function. In this model, individuals are consistently risk-seeking or risk averse across different types of risk. In accordance with this model, risk-taking behavior is not affected by context, framing, or shifting relationships between risks. Importantly, this means that the likelihood of taking a given risk is the same regardless of whether that risk is being considered in isolation or as part of a sequence, or if that risk is from the same domain or a different domain as another risk. Much research to date has suggested that models of consistent risk attitude are not descriptive of actual choice (Fox and Tversky 1998; Fox and See 2003; Kahneman and Tversky 1979; March and Shapira 1987; Payne 2005; Rabin and Thaler 2001; Tversky and Kahneman 1992). Within the psychology 5 literature, risk attitude can be affected by psychological factors wherein individual-level risk-taking is not stable across domains or contexts.
Recommended publications
  • Running Head: PSYCHOLOGY of RISK MANAGEMENT 1 The
    Running head: PSYCHOLOGY OF RISK MANAGEMENT 1 The Psychology of Risk Management Gaëlle Villejoubert and Frédéric Vallée-Tourangeau Kingston University Author Note Gaëlle Villejoubert, Frédéric Vallée-Tourangeau, School of Social Science, Kingston University, London. This is an Accepted Manuscript of a chapter published by Risk Books in Böcker, K. (Ed.), Rethinking Risk Measurement and Reporting: Uncertainty, Bayesian Analysis and Expert Judgement (Vol. I, pp. 405-435) on 8 November 2010, available online: https://riskbooks.com/rethinking-risk-measurement-and-reporting-volume-i-2. This manuscript may not exactly replicate the final version published in the book. It is not the copy of the record. Correspondence concerning this chapter should be addressed to Dr Gaëlle Villejoubert, School of Social Science, Kingston University, Penrhyn Road, Kingston upon Thames, KT1 2EE, UNITED KINGDOM. Email: [email protected]., fax: +44 (0)208 417 2388 Running head: PSYCHOLOGY OF RISK MANAGEMENT 2 The Psychology of Risk Management Risk lies at the heart of the most common banking decisions. Large banks have retail, commercial, and investment banking operations. The nature and magnitude of the risks, and potential returns, vary considerably across these different operations. A general characterisation of risk involves two dimensions: the extent of harm caused by an adverse outcome (e.g., a bank run, a large commercial client declaring bankruptcy, significant fluctuations in the availability of credit) and the likelihood that this adverse outcome will occur (Breakwell, 2007). For the past two decades, major investment firms have managed those risks by using complex mathematical models for measuring risk in various portfolios. Those models were used to quantify risk positions, often in the form of a Value-at-Risk (VaR), which corresponds to the maximum potential loss that could be expected with a 99% or 95% probability.
    [Show full text]
  • Heuristics & Biases Simplified
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Master of Behavioral and Decision Sciences Capstones Behavioral and Decision Sciences Program 8-9-2019 Heuristics & Biases Simplified: Easy ot Understand One-Pagers that Use Plain Language & Examples to Simplify Human Judgement and Decision-Making Concepts Brittany Gullone University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/mbds Part of the Social and Behavioral Sciences Commons Gullone, Brittany, "Heuristics & Biases Simplified: Easy to Understand One-Pagers that Use Plain Language & Examples to Simplify Human Judgement and Decision-Making Concepts" (2019). Master of Behavioral and Decision Sciences Capstones. 7. https://repository.upenn.edu/mbds/7 The final capstone research project for the Master of Behavioral and Decision Sciences is an independent study experience. The paper is expected to: • Present a position that is unique, original and directly applies to the student's experience; • Use primary sources or apply to a primary organization/agency; • Conform to the style and format of excellent academic writing; • Analyze empirical research data that is collected by the student or that has already been collected; and • Allow the student to demonstrate the competencies gained in the master’s program. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/mbds/7 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Heuristics & Biases Simplified: Easy ot Understand One-Pagers that Use Plain Language & Examples to Simplify Human Judgement and Decision-Making Concepts Abstract Behavioral Science is a new and quickly growing field of study that has found ways of capturing readers’ attention across a variety of industries. The popularity of this field has led to a wealth of terms, concepts, and materials that describe human behavior and decision making.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception, Heuristics, Cognitive Bias and the Psychology of Safety
    Perception, Heuristics, Cognitive Bias and the Psychology of Safety Helping People and Organisations Mature in Safety Development 2009 human dymensions Prepared by: Dr Robert Long Director Human Dymensions 10 Jens Place Kambah ACT 2902 Contact: Mobile: 0424-547 115 Email: [email protected] ABN: 34 123 347 080 human Perception, Heuristics, Cognitive Bias and the Psychology of Safety dymensions Introduction Managing safety is mostly dependent on judgment, perceptions and decision making. Whilst it is good and necessary to have legislation, standards and regulations in place, it is what humans decide to do with those regulations that determines whether they will be effective. Regulations of themselves do not make a safe workplace, it is when people comply with those regulations that their effectiveness is experienced. Similarly, education and training in themselves do not create safe behaviour, knowledge and information in themselves do not necessitate effective risk management. It is also good to have safety management systems in place but we need to understand that human interac- tions with regulations, knowledge and systems is just as important as the systems themselves. This paper explores the human aspect of risk and safety management and discusses key issues in understanding the psychological and cultural dimensions of safety management. How we make decisions, what we base our decisions on and, our behaviour, are all uniquely linked and interdependent. There is a view in safety and risk management which espouse that humans are the sum of their behaviours, this is the approach of Behaviour-Based Safety (BBS). There is another view which argues that human behaviour is evidence of thinking (cognition) and that behaviour is determined by right thinking, this is the approach of Cognitive Behavioural Theory (CBT).
    [Show full text]
  • The Perception of Risk
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 2002 The Perception of Risk Cass R. Sunstein Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Cass R. Sunstein, "The Perception of Risk," 115 Harvard Law Review 1119 (2002). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW THE LAWS OF FEAR THE PERCEPTION OF RISK. By Paul SIovic. 2oo0. London: Earthscan Publications Ltd. Pp. xxxvii, 473. £19.95. Reviewed by Cass R. Sunstein" "The nation is quickly buying up stocks of gas masks, shelves are being stripped of antibiotics,and bottled water may not be far behind. Many travelers have canceled trips by air and taken trains or cars instead, even across the country. New Yorkers fearfid of an attack on the subways insist on riding in cars on traffic-choked streets. Doctors in Boston report that patients with minor ailments like colds and sore throats have been calling out of fear that they may have been sickened by a toxic chemical or lethal germ introduced by terrorists. Meanwhile, business at McDonald's and Haagen-Dazs is thriving. What does this say about how people respond to potential threats to their health and lives?"1 "With the deaths of two people from shark attacks over the Labor Day weekend, the summerlong fascination with these fear-inducing creatures of the deep has turned into a near obsession as Americans wonder whether the oceans are safe for recreation and sport.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Risk Perception System for Obstacle Avoidance in Outdoor Muav Missions
    Cognitive risk perception system for obstacle avoidance in outdoor mUAV missions David Sanz Escuela Tecnica Superior de Ingenieros Industriales Universidad Politecnica de Madrid A thesis submitted for the degree of PhD in Automation and Robotics PhilosophiæDoctor (PhD) in Automation and Robotics. June, 2015 1. Reviewer: Dr. Ahmad Aamir 2. Reviewer: Dr. Oscar Reinoso 3. Reviewer: Dr. Angela´ Ribeiro 4. Reviewer:Dr. Claudio Rossi 5. Reviewer: Dr. David Travieso 6. Reserve reviewer: Dr. Ram´onBarber 7. Reserve reviewer: Dr. Gonzalo Pajares 8. International reviewer: Dr. Pablo Fernandez-Alcantarilla 9. International reviewer: Dr. Francisco Costela Day of the defense: Signature from head of PhD committee: ii Abstract Robotics has undergone a great revolution in the last decades. Nowadays this technology is able to perform really complex tasks with a high degree of accuracy and speed, however this is only true in precisely defined situations with fully controlled variables. Since the real world is dynamic, changing and unstructured, flexible and non context-dependent systems are required. The ability to understand situations, acknowledge changes and balance reactions is required by robots to successfully interact with their surroundings in a fully autonomous fashion. In fact, it is those very processes that define human interactions with the envi- ronment. Social relationships, driving or risk/incertitude management... in all these activities and systems, context understanding and adaptability are what allow human beings to survive: contrarily to the traditional robotics, people do not evaluate obstacles according to their position but according to the potential risk their presence imply. In this sense, human perception looks for information which goes beyond location, speed and dynamics (the usual data used in traditional obstacle avoidance systems).
    [Show full text]
  • A Heuristics Approach to Understanding Cancer Risk Perception: Contributions from Judgment and Decision-Making Research Ellen Peters, Ph.D
    A Heuristics Approach to Understanding Cancer Risk Perception: Contributions From Judgment and Decision-Making Research Ellen Peters, Ph.D. Decision Research, Eugene, Oregon and University of Oregon Kevin D. McCaul, Ph.D. North Dakota State University Michael Stefanek, Ph.D. and Wendy Nelson, Ph.D. National Cancer Institute ABSTRACT uncertainty, patient understanding of risk is a critical part of the Background: The likelihood judgments that people make decision-making process (3–5). For example, a man who elects about their risks for cancer have important implications. At the to screen for prostate cancer by having a prostate-specific anti- individual level, risk estimates guide protective actions, such as gen test would need to weigh the potential positive and negative cancer screening. However, at the extremes, exaggerated risk outcomes of the test (e.g., cancer detection, unnecessary anxiety judgments can also lead to anxiety that degrades quality of life from a detected cancer whose best treatment is watchful wait- or to aggressive self-protective actions that are unwarranted ing) with the likelihood of each outcome. At a policy level, risk given the objective risks. At the policy level, risk judgments may judgments may reflect societal perceptions of cancer prevention serve as an indicator of societal perceptions of the “war” and control efforts. For example, news reports describing ele- against cancer. Using risk judgments, the public expresses its vated rates of cancer in Long Island, NY, or Marin County, CA belief about whether we are winning. Purpose: We present theo- (so-called cancer clusters) may be interpreted to mean that we retical perspectives from judgment and decision making, illus- are losing the “war on cancer” even though the objective exis- trate how they can explain some of the existing empirical find- tence of these cancer clusters remains an open question (6).
    [Show full text]
  • Vol. 4 of Understanding and Preventing Violence
    MEASUREMENT AND ANALYSIS OF CRIME AND JUSTICE Fear of Crime in the United States: Avenues for Research and Policy by Mark Warr Fear of crime affects far more people in the United States than crime A itself, and there are sound reasons for treating crime and fear of crime as distinct social problems. After assessing the state of knowledge on B fear, this chapter considers whether public fear of crime can and S ought to be controlled, and the moral and practical implications of doing so. The discussion draws on the literatures of risk perception T and risk communication, as well as research on the etiology of fear R and public beliefs about crime. A final objective of the chapter is to identify the most pressing unanswered questions about fear con- A fronting investigators today. C T 451 Mark Warr is a Professor in the Department of Sociology at the University of Texas at Austin. VOLUME 4 FEAR OF CRIME IN THE UNITED STATES riminal events capture the attention of the general public in a way that Cfew other events can (cf. Skogan and Maxfield 1981). One reason is that crimes receive extraordinary emphasis in the mass media, from news coverage to feature films to television dramas to crime fiction (Graber 1980; Skogan and Maxfield 1981; Warr 1994). But even without this sort of amplification, crimes are intrinsically interesting events. As condensed and emblematic accounts of human conflict, they raise profound questions about the nature and sources of human motivation, the misfortune of fellow humans, the ability of the state to maintain social order, and, ultimately, the presence or absence of justice in human affairs.
    [Show full text]
  • White Paper Communicating Risk in the 21
    WHITE PAPER COMMUNICATING RISK IN THE 21ST CENTURY: The Case of Nanotechnology February 2010 By David M. Berube, Ph.D. With Brenton Faber, Ph.D. Dietram A. Scheufele, Ph.D. and Christopher L. Cummings, doctoral student Grant E. Gardner, Ph.D. Kelly N. Martin, doctoral candidate Michael S. Martin, PCOST assistant Nicholas M. Temple, doctoral student Illustration by Timothy Wickham An Independent Analysis Commissioned by the NNCO Any opinions, findings and conclusions or recommendations expressed are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of the NNCO. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This work was supported by a supplement to grant #0809470 from the National Science Foundation, NSF 06-595, Nanotechnology Interdisciplinary Research Team (NIRT): Intuitive Toxicology and Public Engagement. Logistical and additional support was received from North Carolina State University, the College of Humanities and Social Sciences (CHASS), and the Department of Communication. We especially appreciated the support of the Communication, Rhetoric and Digital Media (CRDM) doctoral program and the Public Communication of Science and Technology Project (PCOST). We thank the efforts of Vivian Ota Wang (National Human Genome Research Institute - National Institutes of Health of the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (NHGRI-NIH-DHHS) and NIH Agency Representative to the National Science and Technology Council (NSTC) and the National Nanotechnology Coordination Office (NNCO), and Stephen Zehr (National Science Foundation- Science, Technology, and Society (NSF-STS) both of whom are associated with the Nanotechnology Public Engagement and Communications Work Group (NPEC) of the NSTC as Chair and Working Group Member respectively. In addition, two colleagues read through the paper and offered their insights: A.
    [Show full text]
  • The Gambler's Fallacy Fallacy
    The gambler’s fallacy fallacy (fallacy) Marko Kovica and Silje Kristiansenb aZIPAR – Zurich Institute of Public Affairs Research, Lommisweg 12, 8048 Zurich, Switzerland; bNortheastern University, College of Arts, Media & Design, Boston, United States ARTICLE HISTORY Compiled June 20, 2017 ABSTRACT The gambler’s fallacy is the irrational belief that prior outcomes in a series of events affect the probability of a future outcome, even though the events in question are independent and identically distributed. In this paper, we argue that in the stan- dard account of the gambler’s fallacy, the gambler’s fallacy fallacy can arise: The irrational belief that all beliefs pertaining to the probabilities of sequences of out- comes constitute the gambler’s fallacy, when, in fact, they do not. Specifically, the odds of the probabilities of some sequences of outcomes can be epistemically ratio- nal in a given decision-making situation. Not only are such odds of probabilities of sequences of outcomes not the gambler’s fallacy, but they can be implemented as a simple heuristic for avoiding the gambler’s fallacy in risk-related decision-making. However, we have to be careful not to fall prey to a variant of the gambler’s fal- lacy, the gambler’s fallacy fallacy (fallacy), in which we do not calculate odds for the probabilities of sequences that matter, but rather simply believe that the raw probability for the occurrence of a sequence of outcomes is the probability for the last outcome in that sequence. KEYWORDS gambler’s fallacy; cognitive biases; cognitive heuristics; probability; risk perception 1. Introduction: Gamblers, these poor irrational devils Human cognition is systematically riddled with a specific category of errors, so-called cognitive heuristics or biases (Tversky and Kahneman 1974).
    [Show full text]
  • Thesis.Pdf (595.1Kb)
    How Does Contextual Information Affect our Understanding of Numerical Probabilities PSY-3900 Erik Y. Nerva Master Thesis in Psychology Faculty of Health Sciences Department of Psychology University of Tromsø Spring 2012 CONTEXTUAL INFORMATION AND RISK PERCEPTION 2 CONTEXTUAL INFORMATION AND RISK PERCEPTION 3 Acknowledgements First of all, I would like to extend my gratitude to my supervisor, associate professor Torstein Låg. His knowledge of the field has been highly appreciated. Furthermore, his ability to show enthusiasm towards the project has been inspiring and motivated me throughout the process. I also want to thank my classmates for the good social and supportive atmosphere throughout these two years. Finally, I would like to thank associate professor and coordinator for the Masters program, Tove Dahl, for a memorable two years and continuously striving to improve the Masters program. Her open-door policy and positive attitude has been much appreciated. Thank you. Erik Y. Nerva Tromsø 02.05.2012 CONTEXTUAL INFORMATION AND RISK PERCEPTION 4 CONTEXTUAL INFORMATION AND RISK PERCEPTION 5 Abstract Numerical probabilities representing health risks or treatment benefits are constantly communicated to the general public. These probabilities are often embedded in contextual information in the form of a personal patient narrative or newscasts. Previous research suggest that people’s perceptions of risk will be greater when probability information is communicated along with contextual information. In this study, we hypothesized that the presence of contextual information, in the form of a televised newscast, would increase the participant’s perception of risk of side effects of the swine flu vaccine. Participants (N = 75) were presented with information about the side effects of the swine flu vaccine.
    [Show full text]
  • Precautions Against What - the Availability Heuristic and Cross- Cultural Risk Perception Meador Lecture Series 2004-2005: Risk and the Law
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 2005 Precautions against What - The Availability Heuristic and Cross- Cultural Risk Perception Meador Lecture Series 2004-2005: Risk and the Law Cass R. Sunstein Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Cass R. Sunstein, "Precautions against What - The Availability Heuristic and Cross-Cultural Risk Perception Meador Lecture Series 2004-2005: Risk and the Law," 57 Alabama Law Review 75 (2005). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MEADOR LECTURE SERIES 2004-2005: RISK AND THE LAW PRECAUTIONS AGAINST WHAT? THE AVAILABILITY HEURISTIC AND CROSS-CULTURAL RISK PERCEPTION Cass R. Sunstein* ABSTRACT Because risks are on all sides of social situations, it is not possible to be globally "precautionary." Hence, the Precautionary Principle runs into serious conceptual difficulties; any precautions will themselves create haz- ards of one kind or another. When the principle gives guidance, it is often because of the availability heuristic, which can make some risks stand out as particularlysalient, regardless of their actual magnitude. The same heu- ristic helps to explain differences across groups, cultures, and even nations in the perception of risks, especially when linked with such social processes as cascades and group polarization. One difficulty is that what is available is sometimes a result of predispositions,cultural and otherwise.
    [Show full text]
  • Risk Analysis
    SUBJECT RISK ANALYSIS SESSION 8 Risk Perception RISK ANALYSIS Session 8 Risk Perception Case study In the 1960s, a rapid rise in nuclear technologies aroused unexpected panic in the public. Despite repeated affirmations from the scientific community that these technologies were indeed safe, the public feared both long-term dangers to the environment as well as immediate radioactive disasters. The disjunction between the scientific evidence about and public perception of these risks prompted scientists and social scientists to begin research on a crucial question: how do people formulate and respond to notions of risk? Early research on risk perception assumed that people assess risk in a rational manner, weighing information before making a decision. This approach assumes that providing people with more information will alter their perceptions of risk. Subsequent research has demonstrated that providing more information alone will not assuage people’s irrational fears and sometimes outlandish ideas about what is truly risky. The psychological approach to risk perception theory, championed by psychologist Paul Slovic, examines the particular heuristics and biases people invent to interpret the amount of risk in their environment. In a classic review article published in Science in 1987, Slovic summarized various social and cultural factors that lead to inconsistent evaluations of risk in the general public. Slovic emphasizes the essential way in which experts’ and laypeople’s views of risk differ. Experts judge risk in terms of quantitative assessments of morbidity and mortality. Yet most people’s perception of risk is far more complex, involving numerous psychological and cognitive processes. Slovic’s review demonstrates the complexity of the general public’s assessment of risk through its cogent appraisal of decades of research on risk perception theory.
    [Show full text]