Mathematical Wit and Mathematical Cognition Author's Affiliation
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also -
Forensic Pattern Recognition Evidence an Educational Module
Forensic Pattern Recognition Evidence An Educational Module Prepared by Simon A. Cole Professor, Department of Criminology, Law, and Society Director, Newkirk Center for Science and Society University of California, Irvine Alyse Berthental PhD Candidate, Department of Criminology, Law, and Society University of California, Irvine Jaclyn Seelagy Scholar, PULSE (Program on Understanding Law, Science, and Evidence) University of California, Los Angeles School of Law For Committee on Preparing the Next Generation of Policy Makers for Science-Based Decisions Committee on Science, Technology, and Law June 2016 The copyright in this module is owned by the authors of the module, and may be used subject to the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International Public License. By using or further adapting the educational module, you agree to comply with the terms of the license. The educational module is solely the product of the authors and others that have added modifications and is not necessarily endorsed or adopted by the National Academy of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine or the sponsors of this activity. Contents Introduction .......................................................................................................................... 1 Goals and Methods ..................................................................................................................... 1 Audience ..................................................................................................................................... -
Yesterday's Algorithm: Penrose on the Gödel Argument
Yesterday’s Algorithm: Penrose and the Gödel Argument §1. The Gödel Argument. Roger Penrose is justly famous for his work in physics and mathematics but he is notorious for his endorsement of the Gödel argument (see his 1989, 1994, 1997). This argument, first advanced by J. R. Lucas (in 1961), attempts to show that Gödel’s (first) incompleteness theorem can be seen to reveal that the human mind transcends all algorithmic models of it1. Penrose's version of the argument has been seen to fall victim to the original objections raised against Lucas (see Boolos (1990) and for a particularly intemperate review, Putnam (1994)). Yet I believe that more can and should be said about the argument. Only a brief review is necessary here although I wish to present the argument in a somewhat peculiar form. Let us suppose that the human cognitive abilities that underlie our propensities to acquire mathematical beliefs on the basis of what we call proofs can be given a classical cognitive psychological or computational explanation (henceforth I will often use ‘belief’ as short for ‘belief on the basis of proof’). These propensities are of at least two types: the ability to appreciate chains of logical reasoning but also the ability to recognise ‘elementary proofs’ or, it would perhaps be better to say, elementary truths, such as if a = b and b = c then a = c, without any need or, often, any possibility of proof in the first sense. On this supposition, these propensities are the realization of a certain definite algorithm or program somehow implemented by the neural hardware of the brain. -
Chapter 1 Elementary Logic
Principles of Mathematics (Math 2450) A®Ë@ Õæ Aë áÖ ß @.X.@ 2017-2018 ÈðB@ É®Ë@ Chapter 1 Elementary Logic The study of logic is the study of the principles and methods used in distinguishing valid argu- ments from those that are not valid. The aim of this chapter is to help the student to understand the principles and methods used in each step of a proof. The starting point in logic is the term statement (or proposition) which is used in a technical sense. We introduce a minimal amount of mathematical logic which lies behind the concept of proof. In mathematics and computer science, as well as in many places in everyday life, we face the problem of determining whether something is true or not. Often the decision is easy. If we were to say that 2 + 3 = 4, most people would immediately say that the statement was false. If we were to say 2 + 2 = 4, then undoubtedly the response would be \of course" or \everybody knows that". However, many statements are not so clear. A statement such as \the sum of the first n odd integers is equal to n2" in addition to meeting with a good deal of consternation, might be greeted with a response of \Is that really true?" or \why?" This natural response lies behind one of the most important concepts of mathematics, that of proof. 1.1 Statements and their connectives When we prove theorems in mathematics, we are demonstrating the truth of certain statements. We therefore need to start our discussion of logic with a look at statements, and at how we recognize certain statements as true or false. -
In Defence of a Princess Margaret Premise
Fabrice Pataut: “In Defence of a Princess Margaret Premise,” Introductory chapter to Truth, Objects, Infinity – New Perspectives on the Philosophy of Paul Benacerraf, Fabrice Pataut, editor. Springer International Publishing, Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol. 28, Switzerland, 2016, pp. xvii-xxxviii. ISBN 978-3-319-45978-3 ISSN 2214-9775 ISBN 978-3-319-45980-6 (eBook) ISSN 2214-9783 (electronic) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-45980-6 Library of Congress Control Number : 2016950889 © Springer International Publishing Swtizerland 2016 1 IN DEFENCE OF A PRINCESS MARGARET PREMISE Fabrice Pataut 1. Introductory remarks In their introduction to the volume Benacerraf and his Critics, Adam Morton and Stephen Stich remark that “[t]wo bits of methodology will stand out clearly in anyone who has talked philosophy with Paul Benacerraf”: (i) “[i]n philosophy you never prove anything; you just show its price,” and (ii) “[f]ormal arguments yield philosophical conclusions only with the help of hidden philosophical premises” (Morton and Stich 1996b: 5). The first bit will come to some as a disappointment and to others as a welcome display of suitable modesty. Frustration notwithstanding, the second bit suggests that, should one stick to modesty, one might after all prove something just in case one discloses the hidden premises of one’s chosen argument and pleads convincingly in their favor on independent grounds. I would like to argue that a philosophical premise may be uncovered — of the kind that Benacerraf has dubbed “Princess Margaret Premise” (PMP)1 — that helps us reach a philosophical conclusion to be drawn from an argument having a metamathematical result as one of its other premises, viz. -
Formal Proof : Understanding, Writing and Evaluating Proofs, February 2010
Formal Proof Understanding, writing and evaluating proofs David Meg´ıas Jimenez´ (coordinador) Robert Clariso´ Viladrosa Amb la col·laboracio´ de M. Antonia` Huertas Sanchez´ PID 00154272 The texts and images contained in this publication are subject –except where indicated to the contrary– to an Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs license (BY-NC-ND) v.3.0 Spain by Creative Commons. You may copy, publically distribute and transfer them as long as the author and source are credited (FUOC. Fundacion´ para la Universitat Oberta de Catalunya (Open University of Catalonia Foundation)), neither the work itself nor derived works may be used for commercial gain. The full terms of the license can be viewed at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/legalcode © CC-BY-NC-ND • PID 00154272 Formal Proof Table of contents Introduction ................................................... ....... 5 Goals ................................................... ................ 6 1. Defining formal proofs .......................................... 7 2. Anatomy of a formal proof ..................................... 10 3. Tool-supported proofs ........................................... 13 4. Planning formal proofs ......................................... 17 4.1. Identifying the problem . ..... 18 4.2. Reviewing the literature . ....... 18 4.3. Identifying the premises . ..... 19 4.4. Understanding the problem . ... 20 4.5. Formalising the problem . ..... 20 4.6. Selecting a proof strategy . ........ 21 4.7. Developingtheproof ................................ -
A Searchable Bibliography of Fallacies – 2016
A Searchable Bibliography of Fallacies – 2016 HANS V. HANSEN Department of Philosophy University of Windsor Windsor, ON CANADA N9B 3P4 [email protected] CAMERON FIORET Department of Philosophy University of Guelph Guelph, ON CANADA N1G 2W1 [email protected] This bibliography of literature on the fallacies is intended to be a resource for argumentation theorists. It incorporates and sup- plements the material in the bibliography in Hansen and Pinto’s Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings (1995), and now includes over 550 entries. The bibliography is here present- ed in electronic form which gives the researcher the advantage of being able to do a search by any word or phrase of interest. Moreover, all the entries have been classified under at least one of 45 categories indicated below. Using the code, entered as e.g., ‘[AM-E]’, one can select all the entries that have been des- ignated as being about the ambiguity fallacy, equivocation. Literature about fallacies falls into two broad classes. It is either about fallacies in general (fallacy theory, or views about fallacies) or about particular fallacies (e.g., equivocation, appeal to pity, etc.). The former category includes, among others, con- siderations of the importance of fallacies, the basis of fallacies, the teaching of fallacies, etc. These general views about fallacies often come from a particular theoretical orientation about how fallacies are best understood; for example, some view fallacies as epistemological mistakes, some as mistakes in disagreement resolution, others as frustrations of rhetorical practice and com- munication. Accordingly, we have attempted to classify the en- © Hans V. Hansen & Cameron Fioret. -
On Computer-Based Assessment of Mathematics
ON COMPUTER-BASED ASSESSMENT OF MATHEMATICS DANIEL ARTHUR PEAD, BA Thesis submitted to the University of Nottingham for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2010 Abstract This work explores some issues arising from the widespread use of computer based assessment of Mathematics in primary and secondary education. In particular, it considers the potential of computer based assessment for testing “process skills” and “problem solving”. This is discussed through a case study of the World Class Tests project which set out to test problem solving skills. The study also considers how on-screen “eAssessment” differs from conventional paper tests and how transferring established assessment tasks to the new media might change their difficulty, or even alter what they assess. Once source of evidence is a detailed comparison of the paper and computer versions of a commercially published test – nferNelson's Progress in Maths - including a new analysis of the publisher's own equating study. The other major aspect of the work is a design research exercise which starts by analysing tasks from Mathematics GCSE papers and proceeds to design, implement and trial a computer-based system for delivering and marking similar styles of tasks. This produces a number of insights into the design challenges of computer-based assessment, and also raises some questions about the design assumptions behind the original paper tests. One unanticipated finding was that, unlike younger pupils, some GCSE candidates expressed doubts about the idea of a computer-based examination. The study concludes that implementing a Mathematics test on a computer involves detailed decisions requiring expertise in both assessment and software design, particularly in the case of richer tasks targeting process skills. -
Fantasy & Science Fiction V023n04
13th Anniversary ALL STAR THE MAGAZINE 0 E Fantasy FANTAiy and Science Fictio SCIENCE The Journey of Joenes fiCTION a new novel by ROBERT SHFCfCtfY A Kind of Artistry BRIAN W. ALDISS 6 There Was an Old Woman Who Lived in a Shoe ROBERT F. YOUNG 28 24 Hours in a Princess’s Life> With 'Fe6gs DON WHITE 34 Inquest in Kansas {verse) ;/ HYACINTHE HILL 38 Measure My Love ' MILDRED CLINGERMAN 39 Science', Slow Burn ISAAC ASIMOV 52 Books AVRAM DAVIDSON 63 The Unfortunate Mr. Morlcy VANCE AANDAHL 68 Ferdinand Feghoot: LV GRENDEL BRIARTON 70 The Journey of Joenes {1st 6j 2 parts ) ROBERT SHECKLEY 71 ^ Editorial > /* 4 / • In this issue . Coming si/on 5 F&SE Marketplace ' 129 Cover by Ed Emsh {illustrating ^'The Journey of Joenes”) The Magasine of Fantasy and Sciffiice Fiction, Vclume 23, No. 4, Whole No. 137, Oct. 1962. P-ttblisked monthly by Mercury Press, Inc., at 40^ a copy. Annual subscription S4 50 in U. S. and Possessions, $5.00 in Canada and the Pan American Union; $5.50 m all other countries. Publicaiion office, IQ Ferry Street, Concord, N. //. Editorial and general mail should be sent to 347 East 53rd St., New York 22, N. Y. Second Class postage paid at Concord, N. H. Printed in U. S. A. © 2^62 by Mercury Press, Inc. Ail rights, including translations into other languages, reserved. Submissions mtist be accom- panied by stamped, self-addressed envelopes; the Publisher assumes no responsibility for return of unsolicited manuscripts. Joseph W. Forman, publisher Avram Davidson, executive editor Robert P. -
Denying the Antecedent - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
Denying the antecedent - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Help us provide free content to the world by • LearnLog more in /about create using Wikipediaaccount for research donating today ! • Article Discussion EditDenying this page History the antecedent From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Denying the antecedent is a formal fallacy, committed by reasoning in the form: If P , then Q . Navigation Not P . ● Main Page Therefore, not Q . ● Contents Arguments of this form are invalid (except in the rare cases where such an argument also ● Featured content instantiates some other, valid, form). Informally, this means that arguments of this form do ● Current events ● Random article not give good reason to establish their conclusions, even if their premises are true. Interaction The name denying the ● About Wikipedia antecedent derives from the premise "not P ", which denies the 9, 2008 ● Community portal "if" clause of the conditional premise.Lehman, v. on June ● Recent changes Carver One way into demonstrate archivedthe invalidity of this argument form is with a counterexample with ● Contact Wikipedia Cited true premises06-35176 but an obviously false conclusion. For example: ● Donate to No. If Queen Elizabeth is an American citizen, then she is a human being. Wikipedia ● Help Queen Elizabeth is not an American citizen. Therefore, Queen Elizabeth is not a human being. Search That argument is obviously bad, but arguments of the same form can sometimes seem superficially convincing, as in the following example imagined by Alan Turing in the article "Computing Machinery and Intelligence": “ If each man had a definite set of rules of conduct by which he regulated his life he would be no better than a machine. -
Xxxxxxxxxxxxxmxxxxxxxx
DOCUMENT RESUME ED 297 950 SE 049 425 AUTHOR Kaput, James J. TITLE Information Technology and Mathematics: Opening New Representational Windows. INSTITUTION Educational Technology Center, Cambridge, MA. SPONS AGENCY Office of Educational Research and Improvement (ED), Washington, DC. REPORT NO ETC-86-3 PUB DATE Apr 86 NOTE 28p. PUB TYPE Reports - Descriptive (141) -- Reports - Research/Technical (143) -- Collected Works - General (020) EDRS PRICE MFOI/PCO2 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS *Cognitive Development; *Cognitive Processes; Cognitive Structures; *Computer Uses in Education; Educational Policy; *Elementary School Mathematics; Elementary Secondary Education; Geometry; *Information Technology; Learning Processes; Mathematics Education; Microcomputers; Problem Solving; Research; *Secondary School Mathematics ABSTRACT Higher order thinking skills are inevitably developed or exercised relative to some discipline. The discipline may be formal or informal, may or may not be represented in a school curriculum, or relate to a wide variety of domains. Moreover, the development or exercise of thinking skills may take place at differing levels of generality. This paper is concerned with how new uses of information technology can profoundly influence the acquisition and application of higher order thinking skills in or near the domain of mathematics. It concentrates on aspects of mathematics that relate to its representational function based on the beliefs that (1) mathematics itself, as a tool of thought and communication, is essentially representational -
Observations on Sick Mathematics Andrew Aberdein
ESSAY 1 Observations on Sick Mathematics Andrew Aberdein And you claim to have discovered this . from observations on sick people? (Freud 1990: 13) This paper argues that new light may be shed on mathematical reason- ing in its non-pathological forms by careful observation of its patholo- gies. The first section explores the application to mathematics of recent work on fallacy theory, specifically the concept of an ‘argumentation scheme’: a characteristic pattern under which many similar inferential steps may be subsumed. Fallacies may then be understood as argumen- tation schemes used inappropriately. The next section demonstrates how some specific mathematical fallacies may be characterized in terms · Andrew Aberdein of argumentation schemes. The third section considers the phenomenon of correct answers which result from incorrect methods. This turns out to pose some deep questions concerning the nature of mathematical knowledge. In particular, it is argued that a satisfactory epistemology for mathematical practice must address the role of luck. Otherwise, we risk being unable to distinguish successful informal mathematical rea- soning from chance. We shall see that argumentation schemes may play a role in resolving this problem too.1 Mathematical errors occur in many different forms. In his classic short treatment of the topic, E.A. Maxwell distinguished the simple mistake, which may be caused by ‘a momentary aberration, a slip in writing, or the misreading of earlier work,’ from the howler, ‘an error which leads innocently to a correct result,’ and the fallacy, which ‘leads by guile to a wrong but plausible conclusion’ (Maxwell 1959: 9). We might gloss this preliminary typology of mathematical error as correlating the (in)correctness of the result to the (un)soundness of the method, as in Table 1.