Williams Georgetown 0076D 1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Williams Georgetown 0076D 1 WHAT ’S TRUTH GOT TO DO WITH IT? JOHN DEWEY AND MICHAEL OAKESHOTT ON NON - FOUNDATIONAL POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY WITHOUT NIHILISM A Doctoral Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Government. By Conor P. Williams, M.A. Washington, DC April 11, 2013 Copyright 2013 by Conor P. Williams All Rights Reserved ii WHAT ’S TRUTH GOT TO DO WITH IT? JOHN DEWEY AND MICHAEL OAKESHOTT ON NON - FOUNDATIONAL POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY WITHOUT NIHILISM Conor P. Williams, M.A. Thesis Advisor: Richard Boyd , PhD . ABSTRACT At the beginning of the twentieth century, philosophers were searching to find their role in an uncertain political world. Scant one hundred years after the universal aspirations of Enlightenment-era ethics, Nietzsche declared that moral ideals took their vitality from the stirrings—and strength—of the human will. Humans, in other words, are free—and able—to construct their own moral ideals on their own terms. How should politics be conducted in a world where certainty has been fundamentally shaken? Or, alternatively, if philosophy can no longer credibly offer substantive, fixed truths, what remains for it do? John Dewey and Michael Oakeshott both took these questions very seriously. Importantly, each argued that modern liberal pluralism could be defended without making recourse to metaphysically grounded absolutes. In their view, Western philosophers were in dire need of better reflection on the commitments implied by their particular historical traditions. In subsequent decades, many Western philosophers responded to the same theoretical conditions in a variety of ways. These can largely be grouped into two rough categories: 1) those who seek to reestablish monism and ethical consensus, and 2) those who celebrate epistemological uncertainty to such a degree that their work culminates in nihilism. I argue that Dewey and Oakeshott’s response to this situation represents a significant improvement on the last century of political philosophy. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This is, in so many ways, a project about doubt. At a variety of points during the process of writing it, I found myself infected by my theme. When I ran short of confidence, when my frustrations clouded my vision, my wife Gwennan saved me from myself. She is the best part of my life. Throughout my life, I have been fortunate to receive inspiration and encouragement from a great many thoughtful people. Karen and Doug Williams, A.J. Paulus, and Dr. Paul Franco were especially helpful in guiding me to think deeply about difficult things. This project would have been much less successful without the guidance from several key mentors. Dr. Richard Boyd repeatedly took extra time and interest in my work, even when it ranged into territory unfamiliar or unfriendly to his own. Dr. Joshua Mitchell urged me to build a project that aimed at more than finding and filling a niche in the literature—in other words, he asked me to write something that matters. Whatever the dissertation’s ultimate “cash value,” I have taken that objective as my lodestar and the project is better for it. Dr. E.J. Dionne has been a mentor, critic, and friend over the last several years. He has helped me resist the cynical downward pull that accompanies doctoral work. From time to time, his faith in my work exceeds my own, which is a truly exceptional trait in a professional mentor. Finally, I lack the space (and the memory) required to name and thank every person who had a hand in the project. Innumerable friends, colleagues, and even strangers helped me in more ways than I can name. That said, I have been especially grateful for the friendship of Matthew Sitman and Nathan Pippenger; the patience of Steve Hollingworth and Ann Griffith; and the ineffable enthusiasm of Owain and Carys Williams. -Conor P. Williams April 11, 2013 iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapter 1 Absolute or Nothing: The Search For New Modern Political Foundations 13 Chapter 2 Method, Science, and Politics: Deweyan Discourse and Oakeshottian Conversation 57 Chapter 3 A Contingent, Earthly Anchor: Turning to History for Political Foundations 96 Chapter 4 Balancing Uncertainty Across Theoretical Boundaries 144 Bibliography 183 v INTRODUCTION This project begins with a philosophical breakdown in the waning years of the nineteenth century, and thus, it begins with William James. Few early-twentieth century intellectuals were more thoroughly concerned with the state of philosophy than James. At the end of 1906, he gave a lecture at Boston’s Lowell Institute, where he spoke of a sort of crisis within the field: “Believing in philosophy myself devoutly, and believing also that a kind of new dawn is breaking upon us philosophers, I feel impelled, per fas aut nefas , to try to impart to you some news of the situation.” He went on to describe a fractured discipline, with warring camps separated by a wide, substantive gulf. “Empiricists” and “Rationalists” (or “Idealists”) were separated, he thought, by more than just casual philosophical differences—they disagreed as a matter of core epistemological principles. They posited radically distinct starting places for philosophical reflection and adopted mutually exclusive sets of postulates. This polarization hardly conduced to profitable debates within the field. 1 James was hardly the only philosopher to recognize that philosophy arrived in the twentieth century in uncertain condition. John Dewey and Michael Oakeshott both took epistemology extremely seriously—each argued that modern liberal pluralism could be defended without making recourse to metaphysically grounded absolutes. In their view, Western philosophers were in dire need of better reflection on the strengths and commitments of their historical tradition. In subsequent decades, many Western philosophers responded to the same 1 William James, Pragmatism in Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), 10, 13. Cf. 29, 97: In the rest of that introductory lecture, James set out to demonstrate that this situation was as unprofitable as it was unnecessary. “Tough-minded” empiricists were right to insist on the importance of facts, just as “tender-minded” rationalists were right to build their philosophical systems around principles—the problem lay in assuming that these options were truly binary. In ensuing lectures, he argued that our ideals consisted of whatever “conceivable effects of a practical kind” they implied. He demanded to know “What concrete difference will [a principle’s] being true make in anyone’s actual life?” 1 theoretical conditions in a variety of ways. These can largely be grouped into two rough categories: 1) those who seek to reestablish monism and ethical consensus, and 2) those who celebrate epistemological uncertainty to such a degree that their work culminates in a sort of subjectivistic nihilism. In the ensuing chapters, I argue that Dewey’s and Oakeshott’s response to this situation represents a significant improvement on the last century of epistemologically- driven political philosophy. This introduction is designed to give some context to the broader historical, political, and theoretical narratives that inform my argument. Both John Dewey and Michael Oakeshott began their careers during a period of shaky political and philosophical certainty. In the United States, this uncertainty took many forms, but it was most clearly marked by the outbreak of the Civil War. As Louis Menand put it, For the generation that lived through it, the Civil War was a terrible and traumatic experience. It tore a hole in their lives. To some of them, the war seemed not just a failure of democracy, but a failure of culture, a failure of ideas. As traumatic wars do…the Civil War discredited the beliefs and assumptions of the era that preceded it. Those beliefs had not prevented the country from going to war; they had not prepared it for the astonishing violence the war unleashed; they seemed absurdly obsolete in the new, postwar world. The Civil War swept away the slave civilization of the South, but it swept away almost the whole intellectual culture of the North along with it. It took nearly half a century for the United States to develop a culture to replace it, to find a set of ideas, and a way of thinking, that would help people cope with the conditions of modern life .2 The United States had fought other wars, but the Civil War conclusively disabused American pretensions about the stability of the principles at the nation’s core. It was a thorough intrusion of practical, prudential calculations upon territory once supposed to be ruled by principle. In terms of culture, the end of the war settled little. The culmination of hostilities only set the stage for debates over what, precisely, had been won. In his Gettysburg Address, President Lincoln 2 Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club (New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux, 2001), x, emphasis added. Cf. 440–42. 2 promised that the war’s end would eventually signify “a new birth of freedom”—it remained to be seen what that would mean. 3 Post-war changes only exacerbated the situation. Rapid technological development drove corresponding economic shifts and astonishing new political problems. Equally rapid industrialization and corresponding demographic and cultural trends proved equally challenging. For instance, new national (and international) economic forces challenged political institutions designed for a nation made up of largely self-sufficient agrarian communities. Railroad mileage increased ninefold from 1860 to 1920. Many growing industries consolidated into several corporations by taking advantage of outdated legal structures regulating their behavior. In 1894, American journalist Henry Demarest Lloyd wrote that insular corporate interests “assert the right, for their private profit, to regulate the consumption by the people of the necessaries of life, and to control production, not by the needs of humanity, but by the desires of a few for dividends.” He worried that existing moral language was being pressed into the service of new masters and for inegalitarian ends.
Recommended publications
  • Naturalism in the Philosophies of Dewey and Zhuangzi
    Naturalism in the Philosophies of Dewey and Zhuangzi: The Live Creature and the Crooked Tree by Christopher C. Kirby A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor in Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: John P. Anton Ph.D. Co-Major Professor: Martin Schönfeld Ph.D. Sidney Axinn Ph.D. Alexander Levine Ph.D. Date of Approval: December 12, 2008 Keywords: Pragmatism, Daoism, Metaphysics, Epistemology, Ethics © Copyright 2008 Christopher C. Kirby Dedication For P.J. – “Nature speaks louder than the call from the minaret.” (Inayat Khan, Bowl of Saki) Table of Contents List of Abbreviations ................................................................................................. ii Abstract ..................................................................................................................... iii Preface: West Meets East........................................................................................... 1 Dewey’s Encounter with China ............................................................................. 6 Chapter One: What is Naturalism? .......................................................................... 15 Naturalism and the Organic Point of View .......................................................... 16 Nature and the Language of Experience .............................................................. 22 Naturalistic Strategies in Philosophy ..................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Humble Protest a Literary Generation's Quest for The
    A HUMBLE PROTEST A LITERARY GENERATION’S QUEST FOR THE HEROIC SELF, 1917 – 1930 DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Jason A. Powell, M.A. * * * * * The Ohio State University 2008 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Steven Conn, Adviser Professor Paula Baker Professor David Steigerwald _____________________ Adviser Professor George Cotkin History Graduate Program Copyright by Jason Powell 2008 ABSTRACT Through the life and works of novelist John Dos Passos this project reexamines the inter-war cultural phenomenon that we call the Lost Generation. The Great War had destroyed traditional models of heroism for twenties intellectuals such as Ernest Hemingway, Edmund Wilson, Malcolm Cowley, E. E. Cummings, Hart Crane, F. Scott Fitzgerald, and John Dos Passos, compelling them to create a new understanding of what I call the “heroic self.” Through a modernist, experience based, epistemology these writers deemed that the relationship between the heroic individual and the world consisted of a dialectical tension between irony and romance. The ironic interpretation, the view that the world is an antagonistic force out to suppress individual vitality, drove these intellectuals to adopt the Freudian conception of heroism as a revolt against social oppression. The Lost Generation rebelled against these pernicious forces which they believed existed in the forms of militarism, patriotism, progressivism, and absolutism. The
    [Show full text]
  • The Johns Hopkins Metaphysical Club and Its Impact on the Development of the Philosophy and Methodology of Sciences in the Late 19Th-Century United States
    The Johns Hopkins Metaphysical Club and Its Impact on the Development of the Philosophy and Methodology of Sciences in the Late 19th-Century United States Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Jean-Marie Chevalier The Commens Working Papers Preprints, Research Reports & Scientific Communications Edited by Mats Bergman, Sami Paavola & João Queiroz No 2 Version 2 Published July 9, 2014 | Updated December 17, 2015 URL http://www.commens.org/papers/paper/pietarinen-ahti-veikko- chevalier-jean-marie-2014-johns-hopkins-metaphysical-club- and ISSN 2342-4532 License Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- ShareAlike The Johns Hopkins Metaphysical Club and Its Impact on the Development of the Philosophy and Methodology of Sciences in the Late 19th-Century United States Memorandum, 19 April 2014 - up-dated, with Appendices, April 2015 Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, in collaboration with Jean-Marie Chevalier [email protected] Helsinki Peirce Research Centre, University of Helsinki Abstract This memorandum documents some of the most noteworthy facts concerning the Metaphysical Club meetings, which were presided over by Charles Peirce, at Johns Hopkins University from October 1879 until March 1885. The Club, which started out as a circle consisting of Peirce‘s own students in his logic class, held the total of 43 meetings, with 110 presentations delivered, of which 33 were classified as principal papers. These presentations, as we document in this paper, testify the club‘s impact on the development of the methodology of sciences in the late 19th-century United States. Of particular interest is the close relation of the new and emerging scientific approaches to philosophical, methodological and logical issues discussed by the Club‘s members.
    [Show full text]
  • The Second Metaphysical Club and Its Impact on American Sciences
    The Second Metaphysical Club and its Impact on American Sciences Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen The Commens Working Papers Preprints, Research Reports & Scientific Communications Edited by Mats Bergman, Sami Paavola & João Queiroz Pub 140709-1314a URL http://www.commens.org/papers/paper/pietarinen-ahti- veikko-second-metaphysical-club-and-its-impact-american- sciences ISSN 2342-4532 License Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- ShareAlike The „Second‟ Metaphysical Club and Its Impact on the Development of American Sciences Memorandum, 19 April 2014 Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Helsinki Peirce Research Centre, University of Helsinki Abstract This memorandum documents some of the most noteworthy facts concerning the Metaphysical Club meetings, which were predominantly presided over by Charles Peirce, and which took place at Johns Hopkins University from October 1879 until March 1885. The Club held the total of 43 meetings, and 110 presentations, of which 33 were principal papers. These facts, some of which are highlighted in the document that follows, testify that the club had an enormous impact on the development of American sciences and methodology. Introduction Max Fisch estimated that no other graduate philosophy club has had a comparable impact on the progress of research in the US as Peirce‘s Metaphysical Club. What was it, who participated in it and what became of these people? A history of the Metaphysical Club is yet to be written; the current document highlights what strikes as some of the most noteworthy facts that belong to any such historiography. Of Peirce‘s students (counting those enrolled to any of his courses at JHU) the speakers were Ellery W. Davis, John Dewey, Fabian Franklin, Benjamin Ives Gilman, Joseph Jastrow, Christine Ladd (Franklin), Allan Marquand, Oscar H.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Decade Immediately Following the Second World War, Many Of
    ‘A Central Issue of Our Time’: Academic Freedom in Postwar American Thought A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Julian Tzara Nemeth August 2007 2 This thesis titled ‘A Central Issue of Our Time’: Academic Freedom in Postwar American Thought by JULIAN TZARA NEMETH has been approved for the Department of History and the College of Arts and Sciences by Kevin Mattson Professor of History Benjamin M. Ogles Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 Abstract NEMETH, JULIAN TZARA., M.A, August 2007, History ‘A Central Issue of Our Time’: Academic Freedom in Postwar American Thought (108 pp.) Director of Thesis: Kevin Mattson In the early years of the Cold War, more than one hundred American academics lost their jobs because university administrators suspected them of Communist Party membership. How did intellectuals respond to this crisis? Referring to contemporary books, articles, organizational statements, and correspondence, I argue that disputes over academic freedom helped shatter a tenuous liberal consensus, unite conservatives, and challenge defenses of professorial liberty among academia’s largest professional organization, the American Association of University Professors. Specifically, I show how Sidney Hook and Arthur Schlesinger Jr.’s dispute over academic freedom was representative of larger quarrels among liberals over McCarthyism. Conversely, I demonstrate that conservatives such as William Buckley Jr. and Russell Kirk overcame serious differences on academic freedom to present a united front against liberalism, in and outside of the academy. Finally, I show the difficulty an organization such as the AAUP encounters when defending professional values in a democratic society.
    [Show full text]
  • The Proud Decades America in War and Peace, 1941-1960 1St Edition Download Free
    THE PROUD DECADES AMERICA IN WAR AND PEACE, 1941-1960 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE John P Diggins | 9780393956566 | | | | | The Rise And Fall Of The American Left Diggins's interests ranged from the foundations of the United States to the postmodern world. Return to Book Page. Peter rated it it was amazing Jul 28, He was the author of more than a dozen books and thirty articles on widely varied subjects on American intellectual history. He earned a fellowship award from the Guggenheim Fellowship inbecame a resident scholar of the Rockefeller Foundation inand was nominated for the National book Award for History. To ask other readers questions about Ronald Reaganplease sign up. That was contrary to Diggins's personal experience of Reagan "standing for tear gas and police" [4] most likely in reference of the s Berkeley protests. Even if Reagan, like so many others, did The Proud Decades America in War and Peace fully envision exactly how communism would fall, he ended the cold war by creating what Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher insisted was the "essential trust" that would be necessary to allow the peaceful exit of the Soviet Union from history. Published February 17th by W. An obituary reported that Diggins "was "critical of the anticapitalist Left for seeing in the abolition of property an end to oppression" but also "critical of the antigovernment Right for seeing in the elimination of political 1941-1960 1st edition the end of tyranny and the restoration of liberty. Ask Seller a Question. Kristin-Leigh rated it did not like it Oct 02, Community Reviews.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuity and Change in the United States' Soviet Policy During The
    CONTINUITY AND CHANGE IN THE UNITED STATES’ SOVIET POLICY DURING THE CARTER AND REAGAN ADMINISTRATIONS Ronnie Hugh Odom, Jr. A Thesis Submitted to the University of North Carolina Wilmington in Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Department of History University of North Carolina Wilmington 2007 Approved by Advisory Committee _____________________________ ______________________________ _____________________________ Chair Accepted by _____________________________ Dean, Graduate School TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT....................................................................................................................... iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS............................................................................................... iv DEDICATION.....................................................................................................................v INTRODUCTION ...............................................................................................................1 CHAPTER ONE ................................................................................................................10 CHAPTER TWO ...............................................................................................................26 CHAPTER THREE ...........................................................................................................43 CHAPTER FOUR..............................................................................................................70 CHAPTER FIVE
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    BIBLIOGRAPHY This bibliography contains only works cited in the foregoing pages. To date. the most complete bibliography of both John Dewey's writings and writings about him is Milton Halsey Thomas' John Dewey: A Centennial Bibliography (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, (962). An exceJlent and com­ prehensive bibliography of Dewey's works arranged in twelve categories is contained in Guide to the Works of John Dewey edited by Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1970). For a chronological arrangement of Dewey's writings. a fairly comprehensive bibliography is also available in The Philosophy of John Dewey edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp (New York: Tudor Publishing Company. 2d ed .. 195\). Most recently, Jo Ann Boydston and Kathleen Poulos have provided an in­ dispensable aid to scholars of Dewey's thought in their Checklist of Writings About John Dewey, 1887-1973 (Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, (974). Baker, Melvin C. Foundations of John Dewey's Educational Theory. New York: King's Crown Press, Columbia University, 1955. Barnes, Harry Elmer, ed. An Introduction to the History of Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948. Berkeley, George. The Principles of Human Knowledge. La Salle: Open Court Publishing Co., 1940. Bernstein, Richard J. John Dewey. New York: Washington Square Press. 1966. ---, ed. On Experience, Nature, and Freedom. New York: Liberal Arts Press. 1960. Blewett. John, ed. John Dewey: His Thought and Influence. New York: Fordham University Press, 1960. Boydston, 10 Ann, ed. Guide to the Works of John Dewey. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1970. Brickman, William W.
    [Show full text]
  • Dewey with Foucault Against Weber Colin Koopman 194
    TI,e History and Critiqne of Modernity 195 the philosophical projects of pragmatism and genealogy into the mold that shapes the thought of most other participants on both sides of the moder­ nity debates. This mold can in many instances be traced back to the work of 11] The History and Critique of Modernity: influential sociologist, political economist, and philosopher Max Weber. We­ Dewey with Foucault against Weber berian concepts dominate contemporary critical thinking about modernity, most notably in the form of Weber's claims that modernity is characterized Colin Koopman above all by a grand process of value-sphere differentiation that gives rise to bureaucratized and rationalized separate spheres of society. One unfortunate residue of the subtle dominance of these Weberian concepts in contemporary debates over modernity is that many thinkers who operated largely outside of these concepts cannot be brought into these debates without filtering their Interpreting and Criticizing Modernity thought through this conceptual prism. In the case of Dewey and Foucault, In bringing the philosophical traditions of pragmatism and genealogy to their contributions to our understanding of the history and critique of mo­ bear upon contemporary debates regarding modernity, the work of both John dernity are widely misunderstood due to being filtered through Weberian Dewey and Michel Foucault has been subjected to misinterpretations that concepts that simply were not central in Dewey's or Foucault's thinking. portray both traditions in a way that depletes them of the full force of their The extraordinary complexity of Weber's thought helps explain why his critical insight. This is unfortunate in part because it has led to a failure to interpretation of modernity has proven capacious enough to provide fuel engage with pragmatism and genealogy in the terms in which they offered for both pro-modern optimists and anti-modern pessimists.
    [Show full text]
  • Power, Dissent, and the Contest of Intellectual Virtues in the 1950S
    The Anxiety of Irrelevance: Power, Dissent, and the Contest of Intellectual Virtues in the 1950s Allon Brann Senior Thesis April 2010 Advisor: Professor William Leach Second Reader: Professor Casey Blake 1 Acknowledgments If there is one thing about this essay that most satisfies me, it is that the process of writing it felt like a fitting conclusion to my undergraduate career. In conceiving of my project, I wanted to draw out the issues that most challenged me over four years of study, and to try to interrogate them, side by side, one last time. I want to say at the outset, then, that I believe each one of my extraordinary teachers at Columbia has contributed to this project. There has been no greater intellectual pleasure over the last four years than discovering unforeseen connections between the different texts and problems that I had the opportunity to investigate with each of them. There are, of course, a few whom I must identify here individually. Professor William Leach guided our seminar with great patience and taught me much about good historical writing. In addition to serving as my second reader for this essay, Professor Casey Blake laid the groundwork for my exploration of American intellectual history. He introduced me to many of the figures who have most inspired—and at times, troubled—me in my study of the past, and with whom I hope to continue to engage long after the completion of this project. I am grateful, as well, to Professor Ross Posnock, whose course pushed me to question the role of the thinker in American society, past and present.
    [Show full text]
  • (Southern Illinois University Press) 1976 - 1983
    John Dewey The Middle Works, 1899 – 1924 Carbondale/Edwardsville (Southern Illinois University Press) 1976 - 1983 J. Dewey, MW I: Volume 1: 1899-1901 ⋅ The School and Society ⋅ “Consciousness“ and Experience ⋅ Psychology and Social Practice ⋅ Some Stages of Logical Thought ⋅ Principles of Mental Development as Illustrated in Early Infancy ⋅ Mental Development ⋅ Group IV. Historical Development of Inventions and Occupations ⋅ General Introduction to Groups V and VI ⋅ The Place of Manual Training in the Elementary Course of Study ⋅ Rezension: Josiah Royce, Gifford Lectures, First Series: The Four Historical Conceptions of Being ⋅ The Educational Situation ⋅ The University Elementary School ⋅ William James’s „Principles of Psychology“ J. Dewey, MW II: Volume 2: 1902-1903 ⋅ Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality ⋅ Interpretation of Savage Mind ⋅ Academic Freedom ⋅ The University of Chicago School of Education ⋅ Bulletin of Information: The University of Chicago School of Education ⋅ The School as Social Centre ⋅ In Remembrance, Francis W. Parker ⋅ In Memoriam: Colonel Francis Wayland Parker ⋅ Discussion of „What Our Schools Owe to Child Study“ by Theodore B. Noss ⋅ Memorandum to President Harper on Coeducation ⋅ Rezeption: Lightner Witmer, Analytical Psychology. A Practical Manual ⋅ Rezeption: Josiah Royce, The World and the Individual, Second Series: Nature, man, and the Moral Order ⋅ Contributions to „Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology“ ⋅ The Child and the Curriculum ⋅ Studies in Logical Theory J. Dewey, MW III: Volume 3: 1903-1906 ⋅ Logical Conditions of a Scientific Treatment of Morality ⋅ Ethics ⋅ Psychological Method in Ethics ⋅ Notes upon Logical Topics ⋅ Philosophy and American National Life ⋅ The Terms "Conscious" and "Consciousness" ⋅ Beliefs and Existences [Beliefs and Realities] ⋅ Reality as Experience ⋅ The Experimental Theory of Knowledge ⋅ Experience and Objective Idealism ⋅ The St.
    [Show full text]
  • A Chilling of Discourse
    Saint Louis University Law Journal Volume 50 Number 2 A Tribute to the Honorable Michael A. Article 13 Wolff (Winter 2006) 2006 A Chilling of Discourse David Barnhizer Cleveland State University, Cleveland-Marshall College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/lj Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation David Barnhizer, A Chilling of Discourse, 50 St. Louis U. L.J. (2006). Available at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/lj/vol50/iss2/13 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Saint Louis University Law Journal by an authorized editor of Scholarship Commons. For more information, please contact Susie Lee. SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW A CHILLING OF DISCOURSE DAVID BARNHIZER* I. INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................... 362 II. MULTICULTURALISM AND FRAGMENTATION ....................................... 365 III. LOSS OF OBJECTIVITY AND INTELLECTUAL INTEGRITY ....................... 370 IV. THE EFFECTS OF CHILLING ON THE INTEGRITY OF THE SCHOLAR .............................................................................................. 381 V. CHALLENGING “SOFT” REPRESSION ..................................................... 386 VI. CHILLING OF DISCOURSE THROUGH CONTROL OF ALLOWABLE SPEECH ............................................................................ 391 VII. CHILLING THROUGH INTOLERANCE AND THE SCHOLARSHIP OF RAGE .......................................................................
    [Show full text]