Encounter: the Thought of Martin Buber He Once Again Became a Professor, Teaching Social Philosophy at the Hebrew University Until a Few Years Before His Death

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Encounter: the Thought of Martin Buber He Once Again Became a Professor, Teaching Social Philosophy at the Hebrew University Until a Few Years Before His Death ENCOUNTER: THE THOUGHT OF MARTIN BUBER February 8, 1978, marked the 100th anniversary of the birth of Martin Buber, the Jewish thinker whose name has become synonymous with the terms “dialogue” and “I and Thou,” and whose central ideas—far from being truly understood—have become popularized if not bowdlerized in, or by, the minds of many. With Coffee Houses being called “I and Thou,” and Encounter Groups being featured attractions of Single Resorts, it seems especially important to give the thought of the foremost propounder of a philosophy of encounter its just due. The following pages constitute an attempt to trace the influences that led to the development of this philosophy, to present its premises and goals, and to give at least an indication of its validity by pointing out the principal areas to which it applies. Martin Buber was born in Vienna in 1878 and died in Jerusalem in 1965. Since his parents were divorced when he was a very young child, he was raised in the unusually cultured household of his paternal grandparents in Lemberg, then Austrian Galicia. In addition to being a rich merchant and landowner and a secularly widely educated man, Solomon Buber was a renowned Midrash scholar. His grandson was, therefore, from early childhood on, exposed to the learned discussions of famous visitors to the Buber household. And with German, Yiddish, Hebrew and Polish spoken at home and in school, the boy grew up equally steeped in Jewish and European culture. During his university studies in Germany, Switzerland, Italy and Austria, his wide-ranging fields of concentration included languages, art and literature, politics, sociology, psychology, education, mythology, philosophy, comparative religion, and theology. He was later to write and lecture on all of those subjects, and his output, spanning sixty years, was enormous. Yet he did not wish to __________________ Published in JUDAISM: A Quarterly Journal of Jewish Life and Thought, Vol. 27, No. 2, Spring Issue, 1978. Encounters in Modern Jewish Thought specialize in any one of these diverse fields, for he saw them all as interrelated. Actually, the term “interrelated” could almost serve as a one-word characterization of Buber’s entire thought. It epitomizes his foremost concern which determined all of his thinking and his every activity: to establish relations between two or more entities that may, on the surface, seem unrelated; to create a mutuality of interests, or a meeting of minds and a sense of communality where it had not seemed likely; to achieve unity out of diversity through an encounter of, and by, the different. What he wished, therefore, to do—and what he largely succeeded in doing—was to develop a philosophical anthropology (a term borrowed from his teachers, Wilhelm Dilthey and Max Scheler), by which he meant a view of man1 in his totality as a many-faceted yet entirely integrated human being. Along the way to creating such an anthropological philosophy, he became, among other things, a journalist, editor and publisher, an early Zionist ideologue, and a professor of Jewish philosophy and ethics as well as of the history of religions at the University of Frankfurt/Main. In the 1920s he started to translate the Bible from Hebrew into German, a labor of love which he shared first with Franz Rosenzweig, and then continued alone after the latter’s death in 1929. He completed the gigantic project thirty-two years later, in Jerusalem. With the coming of Hitler, Buber lost his position at the University in Frankfurt. But he soon became involved in reviving a singular institution that had been conceived of, and was for, a time, guided by Franz Rosenzweig, though it had not survived its founder’s death: the Freies Jüdisches Lehrhaus, a house of intensive Jewish studies where adults pursued learning for the sake of learning, not for the sake of earning. During this period, Buber also developed what might best be described as “consciousness-raising” resource material for adult Jewish studies, a task of immeasurable import for the shattered psyche of German Jewry, and he became instrumental in the training of teachers for Jewish schools which had to be hurriedly established after all “Aryan” schools were closed to Jewish students. He continued this spiritual rescue-work until 1938, when he emigrated to Palestine, where __________________ 1 To avoid stylistic awkwardness, “man” will be used throughout this article in generic sense and, as such encompasses woman. [E.J.] ~ xlvi ~ Encounter: The Thought of Martin Buber he once again became a professor, teaching social philosophy at the Hebrew University until a few years before his death. At the same time, he wrote much for publication and went on extended lecture tours in Europe and America. Though it was Judaism and its classical literature that nourished him throughout his life, he also synthesized in his own person and writings several other cultural sources. Both in content and style, much of his work reflects his early and profound interest in mysticism, though, in his later years, he emphatically denied being a mystic (partly because he refused, on principle, to be typecast, and partly because his personal development had taken a different direction). But he could not deny being a poet. In the Vienna of his youth, “to live meant to be immersed in art, and to think meant to be immersed in poetry” (Maringer). The effect of this total immersion stayed with him for life. Even in his most theoretical writings, Buber, the poet, occasionally gets in the way of Buber, the thinker. Moreover, his romantically complex style, at times creatively beautiful, at times badly overwritten, tends to obscure his message. The reader may become intoxicated with the mere sound of it all, or he may share the frustration of no less than a Socrates who once chided a poet for his inability to explain what he had said so beautifully. Yet, though Buber often chooses to be poetic rather than precise, and though he surely neither was, nor probably ever wished to be, a systematic thinker, he has created a philosophy of life, something that one might almost call a “how-to” blueprint for living. This blueprint is presented largely in phenomenological terms and not as an abstractly reasoned discourse. That is, the author tends to describe some personal experience instead of offering a logical argument in support of some philosophical assertion. He may well have derived his ad hoc, illustrative method from Rabbinic literature and from Ḥasidic sources. For Martin Buber all but “discovered” Ḥasidism. Observing its latter- day adherents and their way of life during his boyhood in Galicia, he was so enthralled with what he saw and heard that, years later, when he was in search of spiritual roots, he returned there to study the teachings of Ḥasidism in depth, and to collect, and later translate, its rich source material for publication in the West. His findings exerted a lasting influence upon his entire outlook upon life. ~ xlvii ~ Encounters in Modern Jewish Thought These Findings have been severely criticized by Buber’s erstwhile colleague at the Hebrew University, Gershom Scholem. Scholem, probably today’s world-authority on Jewish mysticism and its offspring, Ḥasidism, accuses Buber of arbitrariness (if not limited knowledge) in his selections of Ḥasidic source material, and of presenting these selections in a highly one-sided and idealized manner. Worse, Scholem feels that Buber, in a “strange mixture of oversimplification, error and truth,” has reshaped the Ḥasidic outlook upon life in general, and upon religious life in particular, so as to conform to his—Buber’s—own. This criticism cannot be dismissed lightly by any serious student of Ḥasidism. But for us, here, it is of no immediate significance, especially since Buber himself seems to have regarded it as rather irrelevant. This, it seems, is because these two men speak a basically different language, and take a basically different approach to their work. Scholem argues as a “pure” scholar, something Buber did not claim to be, at least not in the narrowly defined way that insists on objectivity and demands impeccable attention to detail. Buber’s mind reached for the stars, and was not really concerned with the tiny asterisks that must festoon the lower margin of any academically respectable page. For Scholem, Ḥasidism is a “historical phenomenon” and, as such, an object of his detached research. For Buber, Ḥasidism is “the greatest phenomenon we know in the history of the spirit … a society which lives by its faith” and, as such, it constitutes an answer to his own religious search.2 When he started out on this search as a young man, he was dissatisfied with the spiritlessness of formal religion as he knew it in the cities and among the intelligentsia of the West. At first, he was looking only for that meaning of Judaism which, he felt, lay buried somewhere in Eastern Europe, waiting to be unearthed—and to be unearthed by him. What he found surpassed his expectations. It nearly overwhelmed him in its creative richness of heart and mind, its profound insights into human nature, its emotional warmth—all indispensable elements for __________________ 2 Eventually, though, Buber came to display a more critical attitude toward this “greatest phenomenon in history,” particularly vis-à-vis the “Zaddikism” (exploitation by unscrupulous “leaders”) into which the movement had, in his view, here or there deteriorated. ~ xlviii ~ Encounter: The Thought of Martin Buber that renewal of Judaism which he fervently sought. But he saw in Ḥasidism a significance that transcends the limits of Judaism. “Ḥasidic truth,” he wrote, is, or must become, “vitally important” for all religion, and for all of life.
Recommended publications
  • The Existentialism of Martin Buber and Implications for Education
    This dissertation has been microfilmed exactly as received 69-4919 KINER, Edward David, 1939- THE EXISTENTIALISM OF MARTIN BUBER AND IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATION. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1968 Education, general University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan THE EXISTENTIALISM OF MARTIN BUBER AND IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATION DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Edward David Kiner, B.A., M.A. ####*### The Ohio State University 1968 Approved by Adviser College of Education This thesis is dedicated to significant others, to warm, vital, concerned people Who have meant much to me and have helped me achieve my self, To people whose lives and beings have manifested "glimpses" of the Eternal Thou, To my wife, Sharyn, and my children, Seth and Debra. VITA February 14* 1939 Born - Cleveland, Ohio 1961......... B.A. Western Reserve University April, 1965..... M.A. Hebrew Union College Jewish Institute of Religion June, 1965...... Ordained a Rabbi 1965-1968........ Assistant Rabbi, Temple Israel, Columbus, Ohio 1967-1968...... Director of Religious Education, Columbus, Ohio FIELDS OF STUDY Major Field: Philosophy of Education Studies in Philosophy of Education, Dr. Everett J. Kircher Studies in Curriculum, Dr. Alexander Frazier Studies in Philosophy, Dr. Marvin Fox ill TABLE OF CONTENTS Page DEDICATION............................................. ii VITA ................................................... iii INTRODUCTION............................ 1 Chapter I. AN INTRODUCTION TO MARTIN BUBER'S THOUGHT....... 6 Philosophical Anthropology I And Thou Martin Buber and Hasidism Buber and Existentialism Conclusion II. EPISTEMOLOGY . 30 Truth Past and Present I-It Knowledge Thinking Philosophy I-Thou Knowledge Complemented by I-It Living Truth Buber as an Ebdstentialist-Intuitionist Implications for Education A Major Problem Education, Inclusion, and the Problem of Criterion Conclusion III.
    [Show full text]
  • The Foundations of Martin Buber's Authenticity
    University of Rhode Island DigitalCommons@URI Open Access Master's Theses 1974 Wirklichkeit and Verantwortung: The Foundations of Martin Buber's Authenticity James Patrick Glasson University of Rhode Island Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/theses Recommended Citation Glasson, James Patrick, "Wirklichkeit and Verantwortung: The Foundations of Martin Buber's Authenticity" (1974). Open Access Master's Theses. Paper 1537. https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/theses/1537 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Access Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WIRKLlg RKEI T AND YEfl ANTWORTUNGi i:£1HF: FOUNDATIONS OF rv1.:.a..R rfI N BUBER'S AUTHENTICI TY BY .,TAMES PA1fRICK GLASSON A THESIS SUBMIT'rED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTEROF ARTS IN PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITYOF RHODEISLA ND 1974 THESIS ABSTRACT This study will investigate the foundations cf Ma-rtin ­ Buber's authenticity. 1l1he problem of the foundations of authenticity arises in Jean-Paul Sartre who makes contra­ dictory claims when he says on the one hand there are no objective ethical values while on the other says "we ought to be authentic". The questions are 1 , Can authenticity be separated from objective values and still impose an obliga­ tion? And what are the foundations for saying "we ought to be authentic"? In the first section Buber's notion of Wirklich keit · (actuality) is examined and will be shown. to provide some legitimate foundation for authenticity oy implying an obliga.tion in reference to what man "ought to be".
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Buber and Immanuel Kant on Mutual Respect and the Liberal State
    Martin Buber and Immanuel Kant on Mutual Respect and the Liberal State Steven M. DeLue Miami University Buber’s and Kant’s views as to how to achieve mutual respect are intertwined, contrary to the way each would likely see the other’s position. To this end, the author discussed each writer’s view of mutual respect and shows how the deficiencies in each are made up for in the arguments of the other. The author concludes by suggesting that a conception of liberal civil society, at its best and most democratic, embodied both Buber’s and Kant’s views of mutual respect. I. Introduction: Buber and Kant on Toleration and Mutual Respect Toleration, often considered a central value in a liberal regime that is committed to provide to each citizen fundamental rights, can ironically be liberalism’s undoing. Toleration suggests a “live and let” live attitude toward difference. People who practice toleration learn to ignore what they distrust or do not understand. And what people distrust or ignore, they may over time begin to fear and later, as fear grows, to hate. And when this happens, toleration itself becomes the source of illiberal attitudes toward difference. Since rights are in part protected by sympathetic rights- regarding attitudes, the mindset emanating from toleration can make it difficult to secure the rights that liberalism promises. In consequence, toleration must be buttressed by mutual respect, which directs people to communicate with each other in such a way that they create spaces in society for difference to thrive and for the rights of others, no matter how different, to be preserved (DeLue, 2002, 16-18).
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations for Ethics
    SECTION I Foundations for Ethics Change happens whether we want it or not. ▸ Introduction ealth care is in a constant state of change and challenge, which is likely to continue into its future. Therefore, this quote from the ancient philosopher, Heraclitus, rings true Hfor healthcare administrators (HCAs). In this introduction, consider an example of how change can affect care and its ethics. For example, the rapid growth of technology promises more efficient and effective care along with the ability to treat health conditions and improve outcomes. Of course, technology’s impressive outcomes will also bring challenges for health administrators in the areas of finance, staffing, and patient demands. How does this climate of change affect the HCA’s ability to pro- vide both fiscally sound and ethics- based health care? First, HCAs need to continue providing an environment where patients receive both appropriate and compassionate care. In addition, they must create, adapt, and support the complex healthcare system structure that responds to change. As stewards of current and future resources, HCAs are required to protect these resources and ensure that they are used ethically. These serious responsibilities can only increase in this epoch of change. To address these concerns, HCAs must also be prepared to go beyond patient care. They must respond to the business needs of health care with respect to the patient, staff members, organization, © Panuwat Dangsungnoen/EyeEm/Getty Images Dangsungnoen/EyeEm/Getty © Panuwat and the community. This challenge requires HCAs to have a base in ethics and apply their professional knowledge and skills. In addition, these challenges mandate a deeper application of ethics through appropriate behaviors that maintain both personal integrity and that of their organizations.
    [Show full text]
  • Becoming Dialogue; Martin Buber's Concept of Turning to the Other As Educational Praxis
    BECOMING DIALOGUE; MARTIN BUBER'S CONCEPT OF TURNING TO THE OTHER AS EDUCATIONAL PRAXIS by Charles Scott Bachelor of Home Economics, University of British Columbia, 1983 DISSERTATION SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY In the Faculty of Education © Charles Scott 2011 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY Spring 2011 All rights reserved. However, in accordance with the Copyright Act of Canada, this work may be reproduced, without authorization, under the conditions for Fair Dealing. Therefore, limited reproduction of this work for the purposes of private study, research, criticism, review and news reporting is likely to be in accordance with the law, particularly if cited appropriately. APPROVAL Name: Charles Scott Degree: Doctor of Philosophy Title of Thesis: Becoming dialogue; Martin Buber’s Concept of Turning to the Other as Educational Praxis Examining Committee: Chair: Dr. Robin Brayne Director, Graduate Programs, Faculty of Education ___________________________________________ Dr. Carolyn Mamchur, Professor Senior Supervisor ___________________________________________ Dr. Sean Blenkinsop, Assistant Professor Supervisor ___________________________________________ Dr. Celeste Snowber, Associate Professor [Internal - External] Examiner __________________________________________ Dr. Maurice Friedman, Professor Emeritus, San Diego State University [External] Examiner Date Defended/Approved: ___________________________________________ ii Declaration of Partial Copyright Licence The author, whose copyright is declared on the title page of this work, has granted to Simon Fraser University the right to lend this thesis, project or extended essay to users of the Simon Fraser University Library, and to make partial or single copies only for such users or in response to a request from the library of any other university, or other educational institution, on its own behalf or for one of its users.
    [Show full text]
  • Spirit Pedagogical Relations
    INSTITUTE OF EDUCATION UNIVERSITY OF LONDON SPIRIT IN PEDAGOGICAL RELATIONS: A STUDY OF CONSTRAINTS AND POSSIBILITIES IRENE E. SIMON This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) 2006 I HEREBY DECLARE THAT, EXCEPT WHERE EXPLICIT ATTRIBUTION IS MADE, THE WORK PRESENTED IN THIS THESIS IS ENTIRELY MY OWN. WORD COUNT (EXCLUSIVE OF APPENDICES AND REFERENCES): 71,824 WORDS SPIRIT IN PEDAGOGICAL RELATIONS A STUDY OF CONSTRAINTS AND POSSmILITIES CONTENTS PAGE Abstract 2 Acknowledgements 3 Introduction 4 Organisation of the Thesis 19 Part 1 SPIRIT AND PEDAGOGY 22 Chapter 1 Definitions and standpoints 24 Chapter 2 Importance of the pedagogical relation 54 Chapter 3 Philosophical perspectives on spirit 71 i. Spirit in the I-Thou Philosophy of Martin Buber 72 ii. Emmanuel Levinas' Ethics of the Other 89 Chapter 4 John Macmurray's New Form of the Personal 110 Part 2 FACTORS UNDERMINING SPIRIT IN PEDAGOGY 126 Chapter 5 Culture of efficiency and technocratic consciousness 127 Chapter 6 Intensification of teachers' work 140 Part 3 RECONSTRUCTING SPIRIT IN PEDAGOGY 147 Chapter 7 Two Empirical Exemplifications 149 Chapter 8 Case study of Sarah 158 Chapter 9 Case study of Bethany 185 CONCLUSIONS AND RECOMMENDATIONS 201 REFERENCES 211 ApPENDICES 224 1 ABSTRACT This study explores the possibilities for Spirit as a key term and value position in the development of pedagogical relationships in schools. It begins with an examination of the nature of Spirit from different standpoints and assesses its wider connections to the spiritual, religious and moral aspects of the human condition. This preliminary analysis lays the basic foundations from which to develop a greater understanding of the importance of these connections in pedagogy.
    [Show full text]
  • Fides Quaerens Intellectum: Reflections Towards an Explorative
    International Journal of Systematic Theology Volume 8 Number 1 January 2006 Fides Quaerens Intellectum: Reflections towards an Explorative Theology1 HANS G. ULRICH* Translated by Brian Brock2 Abstract: The postmodern critique has rendered traditional justifications of the practice of research incredible. Further, the status of theological research, in which ‘the discovery of new facts’ or the like is at best ambiguous as an aim, must be under question. This article argues that the aim of theological research is to discover what life lived as if theological claims were true might look like. What is theological research? New and old questions In the tangle of scientific discussions, when research emphases are being established and research plans implemented, the question regularly recurs of what is to be considered research. But how earnestly and in what respect do we ask what the ‘practice of research’ means or what are the ways to research within which the different disciplines move and exist – when we no longer talk as if there is a monolithic ‘logic of research’ or a coherent theory of research? Scientific theory to date has hardly begun a (public) discourse in which the formulation of questions and theories has been tested by correspondence or coherence criterion. The description of this understanding of science has been described by Paul Feyerabend, who held up for inspection the science of pluralism as his method.3 But above all, it is Jean-François Lyotard who has successfully * Theologische Fakultät, Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg, Kochstrasse 6, D – 91054 Erlangen, Germany. 1 Originally published as Hans Georg Ulrich, ‘Fides quaerens intellectum: Überlegungen zu einer explorativen Theologie’, in Karl F.
    [Show full text]
  • EXCAVATING the IMAGINATION: the ARABIC AFTERLIFE of ARISTOTLE's PHANTASIA by Jessica L. Radin a Thesis Submitted in Conformity
    EXCAVATING THE IMAGINATION: THE ARABIC AFTERLIFE OF ARISTOTLE’S PHANTASIA By Jessica L. Radin A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of the Study of Religion University of Toronto @Copyright by Jessica L. Radin 2018 EXCAVATING THE IMAGINATION: THE ARABIC AFTERLIFE OF ARISTOTLE’S PHANTASIA Jessica L. Radin Doctor of Philosophy Department for the Study of Religion University of Toronto 2018 ABSTRACT : This dissertation focuses on the afterlife of Aristotle’s work on the imagination, specifically in the work of al-Farabi, Ibn Rushd, and Maimonides. Drawing on previous scholarship that has investigated the philosophical and psychological role of the imagination in Aristotle, this dissertation considers the role that Aristotle’s Rhetoric had to play in later Arabic readings of Aristotle. This dissertation demonstrates that it wasthe rich life of Aristotle’s Rhetoric in the Arabic world that lead to a slow-burning association of imagination and politics. For al-Farabi, Ibn Rushd, and Maimonides, the imagination is the psychological feature of human beings that make us susceptible to persuasive speech. Since the images of imagination in human beings are restrained and directed by the rational faculty, they can also be directed, although not restrained, by the power of persuasive speech. The imagination allows human beings to imagine the world differently from the way it is, but at the same time it is not intrinsically capable of ascertaining which future or change is good. But human reason, with its deliberative powers, allows us to distinguish between persuasion based on emotional triggers and habitual desires and the truly remarkable innovations that can stem only from the partnership between imagination and reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Review Essay Leo Strauss on Maimonides
    Journal of Jewish Thought & Philosophy �4 (�0�6) �49–�6� brill.com/jjtp Review Essay ∵ Leo Strauss on Maimonides Raymond L. Weiss University of Wisconsin—Milwaukee [email protected] Kenneth Hart Green Leo Strauss and the Rediscovery of Maimonides. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013. 224 pages. Hardcover. ISBN: 978-0-226-30701-5. $35.00. Kenneth Hart Green, ed. Leo Strauss on Maimonides: The Complete Writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013. 696 pages. Hardcover. ISBN: 978-0-226-77677-4. $48.00. Leo Strauss is perhaps best known in this country as a political philosopher. He was also part of the remarkable German-Jewish renaissance of the twentieth century, which is comparable in a way to the golden age of medieval Spanish Jewry. Strauss, along with other thinkers (such as Gershom Scholem, Franz Rosenzweig, Martin Buber, and Hermann Cohen) squarely confronted the grave challenge that modern philosophy and the Enlightenment posed to the Jewish tradition. He is distinguished from the others by his contention that, ultimately, an unbridgeable gulf separates philosophy from the Torah or the Jewish tradition. Whatever Athens and Jerusalem may have in common, the conflict between them cannot finally be overcome. Strauss is also differen- tiated from his peers by his experience of the power of Heidegger’s thought; although he was by no means overwhelmed by existentialism (or historicism), he knew that they had to be confronted. That Strauss found in a medieval thinker, Maimonides, a guide for grappling with these issues is the thesis of Kenneth Hart Green’s work on Strauss and © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���6 | doi �0.��63/�477�85X-��34��7� 150 Weiss Maimonides.
    [Show full text]
  • Title of Thesis Or Dissertation, Worded
    TALES OF THE HASIDIM: MARTIN BUBER’S UNIVERSAL VISION OF ECSTATIC JOY AND SPIRITUAL WHOLENESS by CHARLES DAVID HANNA A THESIS Presented to the Folklore Program and the Graduate School of the University of Oregon in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts March 2017 THESIS APPROVAL PAGE Student: Charles David Hanna Title: Tales of the Hasidim: Martin Buber’s Universal Vision of Ecstatic Joy and Spiritual Wholeness This thesis has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Folklore degree in the Folklore Program by: Dr. Dorothee Ostmeier Chairperson Dr. Carol Silverman Member Scott L. Pratt Dean of the Graduate School Original approval signatures are on file with the University of Oregon Graduate School. Degree awarded March 2017 ii © 2017 Charles David Hanna iii THESIS ABSTRACT Charles David Hanna Master of Arts Folklore Program March 2017 Title: Tales of the Hasidim: Martin Buber’s Universal Vision of Ecstatic Joy and Spiritual Wholeness I will examine Martin Buber’s Tales of the Hasidim, and the limits of his concepts of “ecstatic joy” and “spiritual wholeness.” To Buber, Hasidic legends present the possibility of overcoming tensions between the quotidian present and the messianic future, divisions of sacred and profane, divine and self. I argue that Buber does not present clear instructions on how to achieve this unity, so I turn to his other writings on Hasidism in order to trace his definition of “ecstatic joy” and “spiritual wholeness.” While Buber accurately depicts the Zaddik-Hasidim relationship, he downplays the importance of Jewish Law (Halacha) in facilitating the goal of ecstatic joy and spiritual wholeness which he posits as the essence of Hasidism.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics and Politics in the Thought of Martin Buber and Albert Camus
    Ethics and Politics in the Thought of Martin Buber and Albert Camus by Merom Kalie A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto © Copyright by Merom Kalie 2015 Ethics and Politics in the Thought of Martin Buber and Albert Camus Merom Kalie, Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science, University of Toronto, 2015 Abstract The dissertation provides a discussion and comparison of the ideas of Martin Buber and Albert Camus regarding human connectedness and solidarity, ethics and politics. The aim of the dissertation is to examine the ways in which these thinkers dealt with the possible tension between human solidarity and connectedness on the one hand, and the need for ethical restraints on the other. The dissertation begins with a presentation and comparison of certain aspects of Buber’s and Camus’ respective biographies. It then examines and compares the thinkers’ views regarding human relationship, especially given the loss of the traditional existential and moral anchors in the wake of modernity. At the centre of the comparison stands the difference between Buber, a believer who understood connectedness and dialogue between human beings and with God to be a primordial and inherent need that could and should be fulfilled; and Camus, who was secular in his personal beliefs, and discussed a concept of solidarity which is largely based on rebellion against oppression and shared human experience in the face of the absurd – the bold acknowledgement of human beings’ inability to fully achieve harmony and meaning. ii The second part of the dissertation discusses the conceptual ethical mechanisms the two thinkers developed in order to prevent connectedness or solidarity from devolving into destructive social and political behaviour.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: the Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin
    ABSTRACT Augustinian Auden: The Influence of Augustine of Hippo on W. H. Auden Stephen J. Schuler, Ph.D. Mentor: Richard Rankin Russell, Ph.D. It is widely acknowledged that W. H. Auden became a Christian in about 1940, but relatively little critical attention has been paid to Auden‟s theology, much less to the particular theological sources of Auden‟s faith. Auden read widely in theology, and one of his earliest and most important theological influences on his poetry and prose is Saint Augustine of Hippo. This dissertation explains the Augustinian origin of several crucial but often misunderstood features of Auden‟s work. They are, briefly, the nature of evil as privation of good; the affirmation of all existence, and especially the physical world and the human body, as intrinsically good; the difficult aspiration to the fusion of eros and agape in the concept of Christian charity; and the status of poetry as subject to both aesthetic and moral criteria. Auden had already been attracted to similar ideas in Lawrence, Blake, Freud, and Marx, but those thinkers‟ common insistence on the importance of physical existence took on new significance with Auden‟s acceptance of the Incarnation as an historical reality. For both Auden and Augustine, the Incarnation was proof that the physical world is redeemable. Auden recognized that if neither the physical world nor the human body are intrinsically evil, then the physical desires of the body, such as eros, the self-interested survival instinct, cannot in themselves be intrinsically evil. The conflict between eros and agape, or altruistic love, is not a Manichean struggle of darkness against light, but a struggle for appropriate placement in a hierarchy of values, and Auden derived several ideas about Christian charity from Augustine.
    [Show full text]