History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century Author(S): Raymond Clare Archibald Source: the American Mathematical Monthly, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century Author(S): Raymond Clare Archibald Source: the American Mathematical Monthly, Vol History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century Author(s): Raymond Clare Archibald Source: The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 56, No. 1, Part 2: Outline of the History of Mathematics (Jan., 1949), pp. 35-56 Published by: Mathematical Association of America Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2304570 Accessed: 21-09-2015 13:00 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Mathematical Association of America is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Mathematical Monthly. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 146.186.253.206 on Mon, 21 Sep 2015 13:00:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS AFTER THE SIXTEENTH CENTURY A. THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY The seventeenthcentury is especially outstanding in the historyof mathe- matics. It saw FERMAT lay foundationsfor modern number theory,DESCARTES formulatealgebraic geometry,PASCAL and DESARGUES open new fieldsfor pure geometry,KEPLER discover laws of heavenly bodies, GALILEO GALILEI initiate experimentalscience, HUYGENS make notable contributionsin the theory of probabilityand other fields,NEWTON create new worlds with calculus, curves, and physical observations,LEIBNIZ contributenotably in applications of the cal- culus and in mathematical notations,and NAPIER reveal a new method of com- putation. One cannot help being struck by the fact that in this century,with a single exception, all of these creators in mathematics were to be found in the north,where supremacy reigned to the end of the nineteenthcentury, in prac- tically all fields. While NAPIER, KEPLER, and GALILEO each lived many years in the sixteenth century,practically all of their importantresults to which we shall referwere obtained or announced in the seventeenth. It may be well to consider firstthe contributionsof these men. JOHNNAPIER [169] was a Scot, spent most of his life at Merchiston Castle near Edinburgh, and took an active part in the political and religious contro- versiesof the day. As BALL expressesit [1 ]: "The business of his lifewas to show that the Pope was Antichrist,but his favorite amusement was the study of mathematicsand science." In connectionwith the historyof mathematicshe is usually thought of only as the great inventor of logarithms; but the "rule of circularparts" (a mnemonicfor readily reproducing the formulaeused in solving right spherical triangles),the four formulae (known as 'NAPIER'S analogies") for solving general spherical triangles, and the calculating rods [170], called 'NAPIER'S Rods," formultiplying, dividing and taking of square roots,were also products of his genius. NAPIER seems to have had the idea of logarithms in mind as early as 1594, but it was not until 1614 that he published his researches in a "descriptionof the admirable canon of logarithms" [171]. Besides explain- ing his logarithms,he gives a table of the logarithms of natural sines from 0 to 90? foreach minute.The base of these logarithmsis qlld, whereq = (1-10-7), d=(1+' 10-7)10-7. Hence qld;(e-1(j-.j0-14) e-1. Thus it is wholly incor- rect to referto NAPERIAN logarithmsas natural logarithms [172]. While, fromthe time of ARCHIMEDES on to the time of NAPIER, there were numerousinstances of the recognitionof such a relation as am a-a= n, the law of exponents was in no sense a common idea, and it was not till later that the notion of a logarithmas an exponent became general. In NAPIER'S system the logarithmof 101 (not unity) was zero, although NAPIER recognized that a sys- tem with the logarithmof unity taken as zero was more desirable. It was ef- fected by his friend,the English mathematician,HENRY BRIGGS, whose tables 35 This content downloaded from 146.186.253.206 on Mon, 21 Sep 2015 13:00:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 36 OUTLINE OF THE HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS of the logarithmsof numbersfrom 1 to 20,000, and from90,000 to 100,000, to 14 places [173], were published in 1624, seven years afterNAPIER'S death. The finalpart of a great new table to 20 places of decimals has recentlyappeared in England [174] in partial (though belated) celebrationof the tercentenaryof the discovery of logarithms. In Italy NAPIER'S wonderfuldiscovery was taken up enthusiasticallyby BONAVENTURACAVALIERI, a pupil of GALILEO and professor of mathematicsat the Universityof Bologna forthe last 18 years of his life [175]; we shall presentlyhave somethingto say about his work. In Germany KEPLER'S zeal and reputationsoon broughtthem into vogue there. Let us now consider some of the contributionsmade by the second man of our group JOHANNKEPLER [176], mathematician,mystic, one of the founders of modern astronomyand an exceptional genius, outstandingas a brilliantcal- culator and patient investigator.In 1601 at Prague he became the assistant of the remarkable Danish astronomical observer TYGE BRAHE [176], who died a little later. The vast body of accurate observationsof the planets which Kepler thus inheritedled him in 1609 and 1619 to formulatethe followinglaws: 1. All the planets move round the sun in elliptic orbits with the sun at one focus; II. The line joining the planet to the sun sweeps out equal areas in equal intervals of time; III. For all planets the square of the time of one complete revolution is proportionalto the cube of the mean distance fromthe sun. Purely as a thrillingintellectual experience,without any imaginable prac- tical application, APOLLONIUS of Perga, and otherGreeks, developed a marvell- ous body of knowledgewith regardto conic sections. Then suddenly, 1800 years later, to a KEPLER this knowledgehad most illuminatingpractical applications. KEPLER'S contributionsto the infinitesimalcalculus included findingvol- umes of surfacesof revolutionsof conics about lines (93 differentsolids including the torus); deriving,in effect,the value of f sin tdt,and other integrals; and in solving maximum-minimumproblems concerning cylinders, cones, and wine barrels.Of the fourknown star polyhedraKEPLER discoveredtwo, the othertwo being found centurieslater (1809) by Louis POINSOT.Star polygons and prob- lems of fillinga plane and space by regularfigures were studied by KEPLER. He discovered how to determinewhether a conic is a hyperbola,ellipse, parabola, or circle when given a vertex, the axis through it, and an arbitrarytangent with its point of contact. In one of his works, which consists rather in the enunciation of certain general principles,illustrated by a few cases, than in a systematicexposition, he laid down what has been called a Principle of Conti- nuity,and gives as an example the statementthat a parabola is at once the limit- ing case of an ellipse and of a hyperbola. He illustratedthe same doctrine by referenceto fociof conics; he explained also that parallel lines should be regarded as meetingat infinity.KEPLER contributedto the simplificationof computations and published a volume of logarithms(1624-1625). The last memberof our group, GALILEO GALILEI [1771,one of the most inter- This content downloaded from 146.186.253.206 on Mon, 21 Sep 2015 13:00:32 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS AFTER THE SIXTEENTH CENTURY 37 esting figuresin the historyof science, was the founderof the science of dy- namics. His work in astronomywe shall not consider. A native of Pisa, he is said to have carried on experimentsfrom the leaning tower there and to have arrived at the law that the distance of descent of a falling body was propor- tional to the square of the time, in accordance with the well-knownlaw that S = igt2. GALILEOwas the firstto realize that, neglectingair resistance,the path of a projectile is a parabola. He speculated interestinglyon laws involvingmo- mentum. He suggested that arches of bridges should be built in the form of cycloids [178], and by weighingpieces of paper he is believed to have found that the area of a cycloid is less than three times that of its generatingcircle. From 1609 on, he constructedtelescopes. Anothermathematician who lived many years in the sixteenthcentury, al- though his outstanding publication appeared in the seventeenthcentury, was the Englishman THOMAS HARRIOT [179], who is of special interest to Amer- icans since he was sent in 1585 to survey and map Virginia,now North Caro- lina. He died in 1621; one of his works published in 1631, Artis Analyticae Praxis, deals with algebraic equations of the first,second, third, and fourth degrees. It is more analytic than any algebra that preceded it, and marks an advance both in symbolismand notation, though negative and imaginaryroots are rejected. It was potentin bringinganalytic methodsinto generaluse. Harriot was the firstto use the signs > and < to representis greater than and is less than. When he denoted the unknown quantity by a, he representeda2 by aa, a3 by aaa, and so on. This is a distinct improvementon Vieta's notation. In unpublished manuscripts,attributed to HARRIOT, there is a table of binomial coefficientsworked out in the form of a PASCAL triangle [180]. It was more than thirtyyears afterHARRIOT'S death that PASCAL is known to have used this triangle. MORLEY stated that the manuscriptscontained a well-formedanalyt- ical geometry,but D. E. SMITH found that the manuscriptin question was not in HARRIOT's handwriting. HARRIOT'Sposthumous work appeared in the same year, 1631, as the first edition of the Clavis Mathematicaeof WILLIAM OUGHTRED [181], a work on arithmeticand algebra. After NAPIER'S Descriptio in 1614, this was the most influentialmathematical publication in Great Britain, in the firsthalf of the seventeenth century.
Recommended publications
  • Jewish Mathematicians in German-Speaking Academic Culture
    Opening of the exhibition Transcending Tradition: Jewish Mathematicians in German-Speaking Academic Culture Tel Aviv, 14 November 2011 Introduction to the Exhibition Moritz Epple Ladies and Gentlemen, Mathematics is a science that strives for universality. Humans have known how to calculate as long as they have known how to write, and mathematical knowledge has crossed boundaries between cultures and periods. Nevertheless, the historical conditions under which mathematics is pursued do change. Our exhibition is devoted to a period of dramatic changes in the culture of mathematics. Let me begin with a look back to summer 1904, when the International Congress of Mathematicians convened for the third time. The first of these congresses had been held in Zürich in 1897, the second in Paris in 1900. Now it was being organized in Germany for the first time, this time in the small city of Heidelberg in Germany’s south-west. 2 The congress was dedicated to the famous 19th-century mathematician Carl Gustav Jacobi, who had lived and worked in Königsberg. A commemorative talk on Jacobi was given by Leo Königsberger, the local organizer of the congress. The Göttingen mathematician Hermann Minkowski spoke about his recent work on the “Geometry of Numbers”. Arthur Schoenflies, who also worked in Göttingen and who a few years later would become the driving force behind Frankfurt’s new mathematical institute, gave a talk about perfect sets, thereby advancing the equally young theory of infinite sets. The Heidelberg scholar Moritz Cantor presented new results on the history of mathematics, and Max Simon, a specialist for mathematics education, discussed the mathematics of the Egyptians.
    [Show full text]
  • History and Epistemology in Mathematics Education – Fulvia Furinghetti
    HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS – History and Epistemology in Mathematics Education – Fulvia Furinghetti HISTORY AND EPISTEMOLOGY IN MATHEMATICS EDUCATION Fulvia Furinghetti Università di Genova, Genoa, Italy Keywords: history of mathematics, original sources, epistemology, mathematics education, mathematics, teaching, learning, teachers, students, training Contents 1. Introduction 2. The pioneer period in the studies on the introduction of history in mathematics education 2.1. The Scenario 2.2. Pioneer Reflections on the Use of History in Mathematics Education 2.3. A Pioneer Experiment of Introducing History in the Mathematics Classroom 3. Convergences and Divergences between Historical Conceptual Developments and Classroom Learning in Mathematics. Epistemological Assumptions about the Relation between Students’ Understanding and History of Mathematics 4. International Cooperation in the Studies on the Use of History in Mathematics Education 5. History of Mathematics in Mathematics Education: Why, How, for Whom, When? 5.1. Stream A: History for promoting mathematics 5. 2. Stream B: History of Mathematics for Constructing Mathematical Knowledge 6. History of Mathematics and Teachers 6.1. The Role of History of Mathematics in Teacher Education 6.2. An Example of Realization 6.3. Resources, Prescriptions, Opportunities at Teachers’ Disposal for Introducing History of Mathematics in the Classroom 7. Conclusions and Perspectives Acknowledgements Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch UNESCO – EOLSS Summary Since longtime SAMPLEmathematics educators have CHAPTERSshown interest in the use of history of mathematics in mathematics teaching. In many countries curricula mention the need of introducing a historical dimension in mathematics teaching. This chapter discusses some interesting reasons put forwards by the supporters of this use and their epistemological assumptions. The initial part of the chapter provides a short account of the setting in which the first discussions and the first experiments concerning the use of history in mathematics teaching took place.
    [Show full text]
  • 6A. Mathematics
    19-th Century ROMANTIC AGE Mathematics Collected and edited by Prof. Zvi Kam, Weizmann Institute, Israel The 19th century is called “Romantic” because of the romantic trend in literature, music and arts opposing the rationalism of the 18th century. The romanticism adored individualism, folklore and nationalism and distanced itself from the universality of humanism and human spirit. Coming back to nature replaced the superiority of logics and reasoning human brain. In Literature: England-Lord byron, Percy Bysshe Shelly Germany –Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Johann Christoph Friedrich von Schiller, Immanuel Kant. France – Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Alexandre Dumas (The Hunchback from Notre Dam), Victor Hugo (Les Miserable). Russia – Alexander Pushkin. Poland – Adam Mickiewicz (Pan Thaddeus) America – Fennimore Cooper (The last Mohican), Herman Melville (Moby Dick) In Music: Germany – Schumann, Mendelsohn, Brahms, Wagner. France – Berlioz, Offenbach, Meyerbeer, Massenet, Lalo, Ravel. Italy – Bellini, Donizetti, Rossini, Puccini, Verdi, Paganini. Hungary – List. Czech – Dvorak, Smetana. Poland – Chopin, Wieniawski. Russia – Mussorgsky. Finland – Sibelius. America – Gershwin. Painters: England – Turner, Constable. France – Delacroix. Spain – Goya. Economics: 1846 - The American Elias Howe Jr. builds the general purpose sawing machine, launching the clothing industry. 1848 – The communist manifest by Karl Marks & Friedrich Engels is published. Describes struggle between classes and replacement of Capitalism by Communism. But in the sciences, the Romantic era was very “practical”, and established in all fields the infrastructure for the modern sciences. In Mathematics – Differential and Integral Calculus, Logarithms. Theory of functions, defined over Euclidian spaces, developed the field of differential equations, the quantitative basis of physics. Matrix Algebra developed formalism for transformations in space and time, both orthonormal and distortive, preparing the way to Einstein’s relativity.
    [Show full text]
  • A Concise History of Mathematics the Beginnings 3
    A CONCISE HISTORY OF A CONCISE HISTORY MATHEMATICS STRUIK OF MATHEMATICS DIRK J. STRUIK Professor Mathematics, BELL of Massachussetts Institute of Technology i Professor Struik has achieved the seemingly impossible task of compress- ing the history of mathematics into less than three hundred pages. By stressing the unfolding of a few main ideas and by minimizing references to other develop- ments, the author has been able to fol- low Egyptian, Babylonian, Chinese, Indian, Greek, Arabian, and Western mathematics from the earliest records to the beginning of the present century. He has based his account of nineteenth cen- tury advances on persons and schools rather than on subjects as the treatment by subjects has already been used in existing books. Important mathema- ticians whose work is analysed in detail are Euclid, Archimedes, Diophantos, Hammurabi, Bernoulli, Fermat, Euler, Newton, Leibniz, Laplace, Lagrange, Gauss, Jacobi, Riemann, Cremona, Betti, and others. Among the 47 illustra- tions arc portraits of many of these great figures. Each chapter is followed by a select bibliography. CHARLES WILSON A CONCISE HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS by DIRK. J. STRUIK Professor of Mathematics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology LONDON G. BELL AND SONS LTD '954 Copyright by Dover Publications, Inc., U.S.A. FOR RUTH Printed in Great Britain by Butler & Tanner Ltd., Frame and London CONTENTS Introduction xi The Beginnings 1 The Ancient Orient 13 Greece 39 The Orient after the Decline of Greek Society 83 The Beginnings in Western Europe 98 The
    [Show full text]
  • Geometric Algebra”, and What Has It Been in Historiography?
    Roskilde University What is “geometric algebra”, and what has it been in historiography? Høyrup, Jens Publication date: 2016 Document Version Other version Citation for published version (APA): Høyrup, J. (2016). What is “geometric algebra”, and what has it been in historiography?. Paper presented at Histoire de l’historiographie de l’algèbre , Paris, France. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain. • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 25. Sep. 2021 What is “geometric algebra”, and what has it been in historiography? Jens Høyrup Roskilde University Section for Philosophy and Science Studies [email protected] http://ruc.dk/~jensh Contribution to the session Histoire de l’historiographie de l’algèbre Séminaire Histoire et Philosophie des Mathématiques CNRS, SPHERE, & projet ERC SAW Université Paris Diderot, 11 janvier 2016 PREPRINT 15 January 2016 Abstract Following the lead of Hans Georg Zeuthen (not that of Tannery, as often claimed), many historians of mathematics since the outgoing nineteenth century have referred to “geometric algebra” as a constituent of ancient Greek theoretical geometry.
    [Show full text]
  • Back to the Future – a Journey from Current Education Reforms To
    Back to the future – a journey from current education reforms to reformations in the past Ysette Weiss Johannes Gutenberg-Universität, Mainz, Germany Abstract Learning from history does not automatically mean that history prevents us from repeating mistakes. We cannot see what happens in the future, even with the most profound knowledge of the past. Although it is not possible to make such causal connections, the study of structural components, which recur and make up patterns, can certainly contribute to sharpening political judgement. How can the teaching of the history of mathematics education then help to support an understanding of possible courses of individual actions without indoctrination through the political or even ideologically influenced production of time references? The paper presents the concept of a lecture course in mathematics education, held at the University of Mainz. We take as a point of departure the everyday experience of our prospective mathematics teacher with various current education reforms and present seemingly similar processes during former reforms. Here we limit ourselves to reforms during the 19th and 20th century. The history of mathematics education as a scientific discipline The history of mathematics education as a scientific discipline with specialised conferences and journals emerged mainly in this millennium. First becoming internationally visible at ICME 10 in 2004, in Copenhagen, as a Topic Study Group and by the founding the international Journal for the History of Mathematics Education in 2007, it attracts new interest today as a subject for international meetings, e.g. at the ICME, HPM, CERME and ESU conferences. Since 2009, the International Conference on the History of Mathematics Education (ICHME) has regularly taken place every two years in different countries: in Iceland (2009), Portugal (2011), Sweden (2013), Italy (2015), The Netherlands (2017), France (2019), and Germany (2021).
    [Show full text]
  • 11 01Kitcher.Pdf (2.293Mb Application/Pdf)
    ----- Philip Kitcher and William Aspray ----- An Opinionated Introduction Each of the essays that follow could be sent forth as an orphan, with only the most perfunctory comment, to make its own solitary way in the world, and some of them would undoubtedly do well. However, we believe that there are important reasons for setting them side by side, that each gains from the company of the others. In our judgment, the present volume offers a representation of the current state of history and philosophy of mathematics. Hence we have felt encouraged-perhaps foolhardily-to offer perspectives on the past, the present, and the future. This introduc­ tion attempts to sketch the history of the philosophy of mathematics in the last century and the recent history of the history of mathematics. We then endeavor to relate the individual studies not only to one another, but also to the traditions of work in the history of mathematics and in the philosophy of mathematics. We conclude with some speculations about the present trends and possible futures. Quite plainly, any effort of this kind must embody the authors' ideas, perspectives, and, maybe, prejudices about what kinds of researches are important. So we have rejected the plain title "Introduction" and announced our essay for what it is-an opinionated introduction. 1. Philosophy of Mathematics: A Brief and Biased History Philosophers of mathematics may argue about many things, but, until recently, there has been remarkable agreement concerning when their discipline began. Prevailing orthodoxy takes the history of the philosophy of mathematics to start with Frege. It was Frege who posed the problems with which philosophers of mathematics have struggled ever since, Frege who developed modern logic and used it to undertake rigorous explora­ tion of the foundations of mathematics, Frege who charted the main philosophical options that his successors were to explore.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is “Geometric Algebra”, and What Has It Been in Historiography?
    What is “geometric algebra”, and what has it been in historiography? Jens Høyrup Roskilde University Section for Philosophy and Science Studies [email protected] http://ruc.dk/~jensh Contribution to the session Histoire de l’historiographie de l’algèbre Séminaire Histoire et Philosophie des Mathématiques CNRS, SPHERE, & projet ERC SAW Université Paris Diderot, 11 janvier 2016 PREPRINT 15 January 2016 Abstract Following the lead of Hans Georg Zeuthen (not that of Tannery, as often claimed), many historians of mathematics since the outgoing nineteenth century have referred to “geometric algebra” as a constituent of ancient Greek theoretical geometry. In the 1930s, Otto Neugebauer added that this geometric algebra was indeed a translation of a Babylonian numerical algebra, necessitated by the discovery of irrational ratios. Then, beginning in 1969, the notion was attacked, first by Árpád Szabó, Michael Mahoney and Sabetai Unguru. In particular the views of the latter have since been accepted as the “new orthodoxy”. As analysis of the writings of the actors involved shows, these have rarely read each other’s works with much care. That already holds for many of those who have claimed inspiration from Zeuthen, but those who have criticized the idea have felt even less obliged to show that they knew what they spoke about. The paper deals with this relationship between the participants in the debate. It is not intended to discuss who is right when it comes to analysis of the historical material. Contents Before “geometric algebra” ................................... 1 When did it start? Tannery or Zeuthen? ......................... 4 Further on, first phase: Thomas Heath and Moritz Cantor ..........
    [Show full text]
  • Algebra and Geometry in Elementary and Secondary School
    ALGEBRA AND GEOMETRY IN ELEMENTARY AND SECONDARY SCHOOL Frantiˇsek KURINAˇ Christian SIEBENEICHER Univerzita Hradec Kr´alov´e Universit¨at Bielefeld Rokitansk´eho62 Fakult¨at fur¨ Mathematik 500 03, Hradec Kr´alov´e D 33 501 Bielefeld Czech Republic Germany e{mail: [email protected] e{mail: [email protected]{bielefeld.de Abstracts FrantiˇsekKuˇrina:Geometry in Secondary School Geometry as a part of mathematics generally appears as a finished area of science, well orga- nized with axioms, definitions, theorems and proofs | as to be seen in Euclid's Elements or Hilbert's Grundlagen der Geometrie. As a subject of school{mathematics, howewer, geome- try should be treated in its nascend state | as mathematics coming to life. In our workshop we present and comment an ample collection of problems serving that purpose. In particular we consider the relation between geometry and algebra where computations with numbers, vectors etc. provide a natural method for solving geometric problems with the intent to shift that way from \Mathematics for experts" to \Mathematics for all". The participants of the workshop will have the opportunity to work exemplarily in their own ways to get a feeling what is necessary for teaching geometry. Christian Siebeneicher: Algebra in elementary school | In Search of a Lost Art Commonly in mathematics{education the mathematics part of elementary school arithmetic seems to be a well understood and finished subject. For two particular (different) points of view see chapter 22 on algebra in Richard P. Feynman, The Feynman Lectures on Phy- sics, vol. 1, 1963, and Liping Ma, Knowing and Teaching Elementary Mathematics, 1999.
    [Show full text]
  • Revisiting Hilbert's “Non-Ignorabimus”
    Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 9 | Issue 1 January 2019 From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert’s “Non- Ignorabimus” Andrea Reichenberger Paderborn University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the History of Philosophy Commons, Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, and the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Reichenberger, A. "From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert’s “Non-Ignorabimus”," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 9 Issue 1 (January 2019), pages 49-80. DOI: 10.5642/ jhummath.201901.05 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol9/iss1/5 ©2019 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert’s “Non-Ignorabimus” Cover Page Footnote I am especially grateful to Prof. Dr. Volker Peckhaus, Paderborn University, Germany, who accompanied the project from the outset. Further, I want to thank the anonymous reviewer for highly useful comments and suggestions. I cannot express enough thanks to Prof. Gabriel Finkelstein for proof-reading the manuscript.
    [Show full text]
  • Revisiting Hilbert's “Non-Ignorabimus”
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Claremont Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 9 | Issue 1 January 2019 From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert’s “Non- Ignorabimus” Andrea Reichenberger Paderborn University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the History of Philosophy Commons, Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, and the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Reichenberger, A. "From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert’s “Non-Ignorabimus”," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 9 Issue 1 (January 2019), pages 49-80. DOI: 10.5642/ jhummath.201901.05 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol9/iss1/5 ©2019 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert’s “Non-Ignorabimus” Cover Page Footnote I am especially grateful to Prof. Dr. Volker Peckhaus, Paderborn University, Germany, who accompanied the project from the outset. Further, I want to thank the anonymous reviewer for highly useful comments and suggestions.
    [Show full text]
  • Carl Friedrich Gauss (1777-1855)
    CARL FRIEDRICH GAUSS (1777-1855) KARIN REICH Contents 1. Brunswick 1777-1795 2. GÄottingen1795-1798 3. Brunswick 1798-1807 4. GÄottingen1807-1855 4.1. Colleagues at the university 4.2. Astronomy and mathematics 4.3. Surveying and mathematics 4.4. Physics and mathematics 5. Gauss as a teacher 1. Brunswick 1777-1795 Gauss was born in Brunswick (Braunschweig), which was then a resi- dential town. It was the largest town in the princedom Braunschweig- WolfenbÄuttel. There were about 30 thousand inhabitants, a court, a theater and high schools such as the Collegium Carolinum, which was founded in 1745. There is only one source for Gauss as a child, that is Gauss himself together with Wolfgang Sartorius of Waltershausen (1809-1876). Sar- torius had studied science under Gauss since 1830 and became a scien- tist in geophysics. In 1847 Sartorius was promoted professor of geology at the university of GÄottingen,where he also was director of the min- eralogical and palaeontological collections. During Gauss' late years, Sartorius became a close friend to him. One year after Gauss' death, in 1855, Sartorius published a memorial.1 1Wolfgang Sartorius von Waltershausen: Gauss zum GedÄachtniss. Leipzig 1856; Wiesbaden 1965, Vaduz 1980. English translation by Helen W. Gauss: A Memorial. Colorado, 1966. 75 76 KARIN REICH One ¯nds there all those the nice stories about the wonder boy who was able to calculate before learning how to speak. Sartorius is also the source for the best known story about Gauss: the teacher in the elementary school wanted to keep a special group of pupils busy for a while; so he asked them to add up the numbers from 1 to 100.
    [Show full text]