Idealism in Medieval Philosophy: the Case Ofjohannes Scottus Eriugena

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Idealism in Medieval Philosophy: the Case Ofjohannes Scottus Eriugena Medieval Philosophy and Theology 8 (1999), 53-82. Printed in the United States of America. r Copyright © 2000 Cambridge University Press 1057-0608 Idealism in Medieval Philosophy: The Case ofJohannes Scottus Eriugena DERMOT MORAN University College Dublin In this article I wish to re-examine the vexed issue of the possibility of ideal­ ism in ancient and medieval philosophy with particular reference to the case. of Johannes Scottus Eriugena (c. 800-c. 877), the Irish Neoplatonic Chris­ tian philosopher- Both Bernard Williams and Myles Burnyeat have argued that idealism never emerged (and for Burnyeat, could not have emerged) as a genuine philosophical position in antiquity, a claim that has had wide currency in recent years, and now constitutes something of an orthodoxy.! Richard Sorabji (instancing Gregory of Nyssa) and Werner Beierwaltes (citing Proclus and Eriugena), and E)j6lfur !qalar Emilsson (discussing Plotinus), on the other hand, have all argued that idealism is to be found in the Neoplatonic tradition, a tradition neglected by Burnyeat.2 Similarly, in a Earlier versions of this paper have been read at the University of Connecticut at Storrs (1992), Columbia University (1992), The XX World Congress of Philoso­ phy in Moscow (1993), the Thomas Institut, Cologne (1997), the Ruhr-Universitat Bochum (1997), and at the University of Notre Dame (1999). I am grateful for the comments of members of the seminars in these institutions, especially Stephen Brown, Andreas Speer, Theo Kobusch, Philip Quinn, Stephen Gersh, and Ernan McMullin. 1. Myles Burnyeat, "Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed," Philosophical Review 91 (1982): 3-40, repro in Godfrey Vesey, ed., Idealism-Past and Present (Cambridge: Cambridge U .P., 1982), pp. 19-50. Hereafter this essay will be cited in the version printed in Vesey, ed. 2. Richard Sorabji, "Gregory of Nyssa: The Origins of Idealism," in Time, Creation and Continuum. Theories in Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages (London: Duckworth, 1983), pp. 287-96; Werner Beierwaltes, Denken des Einen. Studien zur neuplatonischen Philosophie and ihrer Wirkungsgeschichte (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1985). See also Beierwaltes, "Die Wiederentdeckung des Eriugena im Deutschen Idealismus," in Platonismus und Idealismus (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1972), pp. 188-201, and his "Zur Wirkungsgeschichte Eriugenas im Deutschen Idealismus und I danach. Eine kurze, unsystematische Nachlese," in Eriugena. Grundziige seines Denkens (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1994), pp. 313-330. EY.i6lfur ~alar Emilsson, "Cognition and its Object," in Lloyd P. Gerson, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1996), pp. 217-49, esp. pp. 245-49. But see, Lloyd P. Gerson, Plotinus (London: Routledge, 1994), p. 227, n.3, who maintains that Plotinus is not an idealiSt. 53 ... 54 DERMOT MORAN IDEALISM IN MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY 55 1989. study, I.argue~ not o~ly that idealism was a genuine possibility in late and in this sense, intellection precedes being. The result is a system far c~assIcal. and m medIeval phIlos.ophy, but that that the ninth-century Carolin­ removed from the supposed realism of the ancients. gIan phIlos?pher Johannes E~lUg~na ~resents a striking example of an ex­ tremely radIcal, almost fantastICal, Ideahsm.3 Of course, the whole discussion ?epends. e~tirely o~ what is meant by 'idealism'. Burnyeat uses Berkeley's MYLES BURNYEAT'S OBJECTION ImmaterIalIsm as hIS standard for idealism, and it is this decision,col1pled with his failure to acknowledge the legacy of German idealism which pre­ vents him from seeing the classical and medieval roots of id~alism more In his influential article, first published in 1982 in Philosophical Review, Myles broadly understood. Burnyeat has argued that Contrary to Burnyeat, I wish to argue that an idealism based on a developed concept of subjectivity and a thinking through of the implica­ Idealism, whether we mean by that Berkeley's own doctrine that esse est tions of divine immateriality was not only possible in the Middle Ages but percipi or a more vaguely conceived thesis to the effect that everything found actual and sophisticated expression in Johannes Scottus Eriugena. is in some substantial sense mental or spiritual, is one of the very few Eriugena's extreme intellectualist immaterialism differs from modern major philosophical positions which did not receive its first formulation idealism in that it is motivated not so much by epistemological consideration in antiquity. (Vesey, p. 19) of sceptical arguments concerning the existence of the external world, but by theological consideration of the consequences of the doctrine of divine In support of this claim Burnyeat cites Bernard Williams's survey article creation. How is the relation of creation to creator to be understood? reviewing the Greek contribution to philosophy, which likewise asserts that Burnyeat charges that the Greek (including the Neoplatonic) concept of idealism, understood as "the monism of mind, which holds that nothing creation always involved an imposition of form on matter (Vesey, p. 31), ultimately exists except minds and their experiences" was not found in the whereas it seems to me that one of the most obvious concerns of the Greek ancient world.5 For Burnyeat, all dassical Greek philosophy was primarily Patristic writers was to articulate a concept of creation which avoided the realist: the Greeks had an unquestioned, "in built assumption of realism" form/matter paradigm. These Greek authors developed a new paradigm­ (Vesey, p. 33). With the possible exception of Gorgias, all ancient Greek creation as self-expression or self-manifestation, creation as theophany. Simi­ philosophers supposedly agreed that larly, as we shall see, Eriugena, who mediates this Greek Christian tradition in the Latin West, understands divine creation as a kind of self-creation [t]here is a reality of some sort confronting us; we are in touch with itself understood as a kind of eternal self-intellection or self-thinking. God'~ something, even if this something, reality, is not at all what we think it first act is His self-constitution as manifest being, an act which coincides to be. Greek philosophy does not know the problem of proving in a with the overflowing or outgoing of the divine nature in the creation of all general way the existence of an external world. That problem is a modern invention. (Vesey, pp. 32-33) things. God's self-expression is also His self-manifestation in the world of causes and effects, and this is understood by Eriugena to be a necessary part In particular Burnyeat rejects the view that Platonism is an idealism, of the divine unfolding. In the tradition of Eriugena, as later in Eckhart's and he maintains that George Berkeley was both anachronistic and "utterly Parisian Lectures, being understood as form is the product of a kind of mistaken" when, in his late work Siris §311 (1744), he interpreted Plato, on self-consciousness or self-reflection. The very nature of reality is ap­ the strength of a passage in Theaetetus 160b, as an idealist who denied, in proached through the paradigm of reflexive self-consciousness, often ex­ Berkeley'S own words, "an absolute actual existence of sensible or corporeal presse~ i~ te~ms of .the. inne~ relations between the Persons of the Trinity, things" (Vesey, pp. 19-20).6 Burnyeat agues against Berkeley that Plato is and thIS IS .dIrectly mime WIth the German Idealist tradition, specifically ~egel. 4 ThIS Neoplatonic Christian idealism expressly emphasises the para­ dIgm of self-knowing or self-awareness as the founding, thetic, cosmic act. God's self-understanding is the prime mover in the creation of the universe 5. Bernard Williams, "Philosophy," in M. I. Finley, ed., The Legacy of Greece. A , New Appraisal (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), pp. 204-5. Burnyeat acknowledges Williams's influence, Vesey, p. 19, n.!. 3. Dermot Moran, The Philosophy ofJohn Scottus Enugena. A Study of Idealism in 6. For a discussion of Berkeley's Sins in relation to Plotinus, see N. Baladi, the MzddleAges (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1989). "Plotin et Berkeley: Temoignage de la Sins," Revue Internationale de Philosophie 91 4. See B.eierwaltes, "Das Problem des absoluten SelbstbewuBtseins beiJohan­ (1970): 338-47, and "Plotin et l'immathialisme de Berkeley: Temoignage de la nes Scotus Ern~gena," in Beierwaltes, ed., Platonismus in der Philosophie des Mittelalters Sins," in Atti del Convegno internazionale suI tema Plotino e il Neoplatonismo in Oriente e (Darmstadt: Wlssenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1969), pp. 484-516. in Occidente (Rome: Ateneo Press 1974), pp. 597-604. -----,--- ; 56 DERMOT MORAN IDEALISM IN MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY 57 not presenting his own views in the passage but is merely offering a reductio (B274).7 Kant dismissed Berkeley's immaterialism as a subjective or dogmatic ad absurdum of the view that perception is knowledge. idealism which inevitably resulted from attempting to understand space Burnyeat's article, though provocative and richly suggestive, is prob­ and time as things in themselves.8 In place of subjective idealism (which lematic in many ways. In particular, his frame of reference is limited and his is really a kind of naIve realism) Kant offered his critical or transcendental conclusion is overstated. Part of Burnyeat' s problem is that he assumes that idealism. Kant then is, to a certain extent, agreeing with Burnyeat in seeing realist and idealist are oppositional terms. While Burnyeat is undoubtedly the essence of this kind of idealism as connected with the conception of correct that the ancients, by and large, were realists in the sense that they spatial properties as belonging to things as they are in themselves. But did not repudiate the existence of external things, nevertheless, their pecu­ Kant's transcendental idealism is a corrective to this view, and sees spatial liar kind of realism is not necessarily opposed to idealism, if by idealism we properties as belonging to things as they appear.
Recommended publications
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Timothy Williamson: Publications in reverse chronological order In preparation [a] ‘Knowledge, credence, and strength of belief’, invited for Amy Flowerree and Baron Reed (eds.), The Epistemic. [b] ‘Blackburn against moral realism’, for Paul Bloomfield and David Copp (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism, Oxford University Press. [c] ‘Non-modal normativity and norms of belief’, for Ilkka Niiniluoto and Sami Pihlstrom (eds.), volume on normativity, Acta Philosophica Fennica (2020). [d] ‘The KK principle and rotational symmetry’, invited for Analytic Philosophy. [e] ‘Chakrabarti and the Nyāya on knowability’. To appear [a] Suppose and Tell: The Semantics and Heuristics of Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020. [b] (with Paul Boghossian) Debating the A Priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020. [c] ‘Edgington on possible knowledge of unknown truth’, in J. Hawthorne and L. Walters (eds.), Conditionals, Probability, and Paradox: Themes from the Philosophy of Dorothy Edgington, Oxford: Oxford University Press. [d] ‘Justifications, excuses, and skeptical scenarios’, in J. Dutant and F. Dorsch (eds.), The New Evil Demon, Oxford University Press. [e] ‘The counterfactual-based approach to modal epistemology’, in Otávio Bueno and Scott Shalkowski (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Modality, London: Routledge. [f] ‘More Oxonian scepticism about the a priori’, in Dylan Dodd and Elia Zardini (eds.), The A Priori: Its Significance, Grounds, and Extent, Oxford University Press. [g] ‘Reply to Casullo’s defence of the significance of the a priori – a posteriori distinction’, in Dylan Dodd and Elia Zardini (eds.), The A Priori: Its Significance, Grounds, and Extent, Oxford University Press. [h] ‘Introduction’ to Khaled Qutb, Summary of The Philosophy of Philosophy (in Arabic), Cairo: Academic Bookshop.
    [Show full text]
  • KNOWLEDGE ACCORDING to IDEALISM Idealism As a Philosophy
    KNOWLEDGE ACCORDING TO IDEALISM Idealism as a philosophy had its greatest impact during the nineteenth century. It is a philosophical approach that has as its central tenet that ideas are the only true reality, the only thing worth knowing. In a search for truth, beauty, and justice that is enduring and everlasting; the focus is on conscious reasoning in the mind. The main tenant of idealism is that ideas and knowledge are the truest reality. Many things in the world change, but ideas and knowledge are enduring. Idealism was often referred to as “idea-ism”. Idealists believe that ideas can change lives. The most important part of a person is the mind. It is to be nourished and developed. Etymologically Its origin is: from Greek idea “form, shape” from weid- also the origin of the “his” in his-tor “wise, learned” underlying English “history.” In Latin this root became videre “to see” and related words. It is the same root in Sanskrit veda “knowledge as in the Rig-Veda. The stem entered Germanic as witan “know,” seen in Modern German wissen “to know” and in English “wisdom” and “twit,” a shortened form of Middle English atwite derived from æt “at” +witen “reproach.” In short Idealism is a philosophical position which adheres to the view that nothing exists except as it is an idea in the mind of man or the mind of God. The idealist believes that the universe has intelligence and a will; that all material things are explainable in terms of a mind standing behind them. PHILOSOPHICAL RATIONALE OF IDEALISM a) The Universe (Ontology or Metaphysics) To the idealist, the nature of the universe is mind; it is an idea.
    [Show full text]
  • Gillian K. Russell
    Gillian K. Russell Dianoia Institute of Philosophy (cell) +1 (858) 205{2834 Locked Bag 4115 MDC [email protected] Fitzroy, Victoria 3065 https://www.gillianrussell.net Australia Current Employment Professor of Philosophy Dianoia Institute at ACU in Melbourne 2020| 1 Arch´eProfessorial Fellow ( 5 th time) University of St Andrews, Scotland 2019{2023 Employment and Education History Alumni Distinguished Professor University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill 2019{2020 Professor of Philosophy University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill 2015{19 Associate Professor in Philosophy Washington University in St Louis 2011{2015 Assistant Professor in Philosophy Washington University in St Louis 2004{2011 Killam Postdoctoral Fellow University of Alberta 2005 Ph.D. in Philosophy Princeton University 2004 M.A. in Philosophy Princeton University 2002 M.A. in German and Philosophy University of St Andrews, Scotland 1999 Areas of Specialisation Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Logic, Epistemology Areas of Competence Logic, History of Analytic Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Science and Mathematics Books { Truth in Virtue of Meaning: a defence of the analytic/synthetic distinction (Oxford, 2008) { The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language, with Delia Graff Fara (eds.) (Routledge, 2011) { New Waves in Philosophical Logic, with Greg Restall (eds.) (Palgrave MacMillan, 2012) Accepted and Published Papers { \Social Spheres" forthcoming in Feminist Philosophy and Formal Logic Audrey Yap and Roy Cook (eds) { \Logic: A Feminist Approach" forthcoming in Philosophy for Girls: An invitation to the life of thought, M. Shew and K. Garchar (eds) (Oxford University Press, 2020) { \Waismann's Papers on the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction" in Friedrich Waismann: The Open Texture of Analytic Philosophy, D.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics of Soul and Self in Plotinus Gwenaëlle Aubry
    Metaphysics of soul and self in Plotinus Gwenaëlle Aubry To cite this version: Gwenaëlle Aubry. Metaphysics of soul and self in Plotinus. P. Remes; S. Slaveva-Griffin. The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism, pp.310-323, 2014. hal-02387195 HAL Id: hal-02387195 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02387195 Submitted on 29 Nov 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. 20 Metaphysics of soul and self in Plotinus Gwenaëlle Aubry One of the great singularities of the philosophy of Plotinus consists in thinking of the self1 for its own sake and, in particular, in producing a concept of it diff erent from that of soul.2 Th is philosophical breakthrough is inseparable from the discovery of immedi- ate refl exivity, that is, the subject’s ability to apprehend itself independently of its rela- tion to an object or to another subject.3 In Plotinus, however, this refl exivity occurs only in an interrogative form, which can be read, in particular, in Enn. I.1[53] and Enn. VI.4[22]. In other words, it does not, as in Descartes, assume the form of an intuition by means of which the subject, grasping itself as consciousness, would, at the same time, have an evident revelation of its essence.
    [Show full text]
  • Plotinus and the Artistic Imagination John S
    Roger Williams University DOCS@RWU School of Architecture, Art, and Historic School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications Preservation 2015 Plotinus and the Artistic Imagination John S. Hendrix Roger Williams University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp Part of the Architecture Commons Recommended Citation Hendrix, John S., "Plotinus and the Artistic Imagination" (2015). School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications. Paper 31. http://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp/31 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation at DOCS@RWU. It has been accepted for inclusion in School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DOCS@RWU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Plotinus and the Artistic Imagination John Hendrix In the thought of Plotinus, the imagination is responsible for the apprehen- sion of the activity of Intellect. If creativity in the arts involves an exercise of the imagination, the image-making power that links sense perception to noet- ic thought and the nous poietikos , the poetic or creative intellect, then the arts exercise the apprehension of intellectual activity and unconscious thought. According to John Dillon in “Plotinus and the Transcendental Imag- ination,” 1 Plotinus’ conception of the imagination led to the formulation of the imagination as a basis of artistic creativity. In Plotinus, imagination operates on several different levels: it produces images in sense perception, it synthesizes images in dianoetic thought, and it produces images in correspondence with the articulation through logos of noetic thought.
    [Show full text]
  • An Anthology of Philosophical Studies
    Introduction AN ANTHOLOGY OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES Edited by PATRICIA HANNA ADRIANNE L. MCEVOY PENELOPE VOUTSINA ATINER 2006 1 An Anthology of Philosophical Studies 2 Introduction Athens Institute for Education and Research 2006 An Anthology of Philosophical Studies Edited by Patricia Hanna Adrianne L. McEvoy Penelope Voutsina 3 An Anthology of Philosophical Studies PUBLISHED BY ATHENS INSTITUTE FOR EDUCATION AND RESEARCH 14 Solomou Street, 10683 Athens, Greece Tel. +30 210 36.34.210 Fax +30 210.36.34.209 Email: [email protected] URL: www.atiner.gr This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of the Athens Institute for Education and Research. First Published: 2006 ISBN: 978-960-6672-11-8 Typeset, printed and binding by Theta Co. 4 Introduction Table of Contents List of Contributors i Introduction 1 Voutsina, P. PART I EPISTEMOLOGY 1. Imagination in Descartes’ Skepticism 7 Scholl, A. 2. Descartes on Sensations and Ideas of Sensations 17 Cunning, D. 3. The Myth of Hume’s Compatibilism 33 Morris, E.W. 4. From Contextualism to Skepticism 43 Wilburn, R. 5. The Puzzle of Self-Knowledge 51 Voutsina, P. 6. Unconfined Rationality: A Normative yet Realistic Model of 59 Inference Morado, R. and Savion, L. PART II METAPHYSICS AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 7. Language as Community Property: What’s Wrong with 75 Chomsky’s Individualism? Hanna, P. 8. What do Concepts Consist of? The Role of Geometric and 93 Proprioceptive Information in Categorization Dellantonio, S. and Pastore, L.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Plato a Perfect Idealist?
    IOSR Journal Of Humanities And Social Science (IOSR-JHSS) Volume 19, Issue 3, Ver. V (Mar. 2014), PP 22-25 e-ISSN: 2279-0837, p-ISSN: 2279-0845. www.iosrjournals.org Is Plato a Perfect Idealist? Dr. Shanjendu Nath M. A., M. Phil., Ph.D. Associate Professor Rabindrasadan Girls’ College, Karimganj, Assam, India. Abstract: Idealism is a philosophy that emphasizes on mind. According to this theory, mind is primary and objective world is nothing but an idea of our mind. Thus this theory believes that the primary thing that exists is spiritual and material world is secondary. This theory effectively begins with the thought of Greek philosopher Plato. But it is Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) who used the term ‘idealism’ when he referred Plato in his philosophy. Plato in his book ‘The Republic’ very clearly stated many aspects of thought and all these he discussed from the idealistic point of view. According to Plato, objective world is not a real world. It is the world of Ideas which is real. This world of Ideas is imperishable, immutable and eternal. These ideas do not exist in our mind or in the mind of God but exist by itself and independent of any mind. He also said that among the Ideas, the Idea of Good is the supreme Idea. These eternal ideas are not perceived by our sense organs but by our rational self. Thus Plato believes the existence of two worlds – material world and the world of Ideas. In this article I shall try to explore Plato’s idealism, its origin, locus etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought
    THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT by MELISSA M. SHEW A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School ofthe University ofOregon in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy September 2008 11 University of Oregon Graduate School Confirmation of Approval and Acceptance of Dissertation prepared by: Melissa Shew Title: "The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought" This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree in the Department ofPhilosophy by: Peter Warnek, Chairperson, Philosophy John Lysaker, Member, Philosophy Ted Toadvine, Member, Philosophy James Crosswhite, Outside Member, English and Richard Linton, Vice President for Research and Graduate Studies/Dean ofthe Graduate School for the University of Oregon. September 6, 2008 Original approval signatures are on file with the Graduate School and the University of Oregon Libraries. 111 An Abstract of the Dissertation of Melissa M. Shew for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy to be taken September 2008 Title: THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT Approved: Dr. Peter Warnek This dissertation engages three facets of Greek philosophy: 1) the phenomenon of tyche (chance, fortune, happening, or luck) in Aristotle's Physics, Nicomachean Ethics, and Poetics; 2) how tyche infonns Socrates' own philosophical practice in the Platonic dialogues; and 3) how engaging tyche in these Greek texts challenges established interpretations of Greek thought in contemporary scholarship and discussion. I argue that the complex status of tyche in Aristotle's texts, when combined with its appearance in the Platonic dialogues and the framework of Greek myth and poetry (poiesis), underscores the seriousness with which the Greeks consider the role of chance in human life.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Western and Indian Theories of Consciousness Confronted a Comparative Overview of Continental and Analytic Philosophy with Advaita Vedanta and Madhyamaka Buddhism
    Western and Indian theories of consciousness confronted A comparative overview of continental and analytic philosophy with Advaita Vedanta and Madhyamaka Buddhism Michele Cossellu Termin: HT13 Kurs: RKT140 Degree Project, Bachelor of Arts, Religious Studies, 15hec Nivå: Kandidat Handledare: Katarina Planck Western and Indian theories of consciousness confronted A comparative overview of continental and analytic philosophy with Advaita Vedanta and Madhyamaka Buddhism Abstract The burgeoning field of cognitive studies in the West is motivated by a renewed interest in conscious experience, which arose in the postmodern zeitgeist in response to the positivist, scientific ideal of objectivity. This work presents a historical overview of Western philosophy from its dawn, focusing on the evolution of key concepts in metaphysics, ontology and epistemology, to arrive at the examination of modern theories on consciousness. The monist systems of pre-Socratic philosophers, the empiricism and rationalism of the Humanism, Kant’s critique and the post-Kantian split of traditions in the analytic and continental branches are surveyed. A summary of the key historical concepts of consciousness in the continental tradition, and especially in German idealism and phenomenology is presented. Modern physicalist theories of mind based on epistemological realism, in the analytic tradition are sketched, and critical aspects of the realist viewpoint discussed. The reintroduction of the phenomenal perspective in philosophy of mind, is argued, represents an important turning point in analytic philosophy. In the second part, the philosophic-religious traditions of Advaita Vedanta and Mahayana Buddhism, in its Madhyamaka branch, are presented, and their respective notions of self, mind and reality confronted. The concept of consciousness as an ontological substance is, in Buddhism, deconstructed through the analysis of impermanence and interdependent origination of phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Robert L
    Contemporary Civilization (Ideas and Institutions Section XII: The osP t-Enlightenment Period of Western Man) 1958 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Robert L. Bloom Gettysburg College Basil L. Crapster Gettysburg College Harold A. Dunkelberger Gettysburg College See next page for additional authors Follow this and additional works at: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/contemporary_sec12 Part of the European Languages and Societies Commons, History Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Share feedback about the accessibility of this item. Bloom, Robert L. et al. "5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism. Pt XII: The osP t-Enlightenment Period." Ideas and Institutions of Western Man (Gettysburg College, 1958), 53-69. This is the publisher's version of the work. This publication appears in Gettysburg College's institutional repository by permission of the copyright owner for personal use, not for redistribution. Cupola permanent link: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/ contemporary_sec12/5 This open access book chapter is brought to you by The uC pola: Scholarship at Gettysburg College. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of The uC pola. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Abstract The ideas of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) are significant enough to be compared to a watershed in Western thought. In his mind were gathered up the major interests of the Enlightenment: science, epistemology, and ethics; and all of these were given a new direction which he himself described as another Copernican revolution. As Copernicus had shown that the earth revolved around the sun, rather than the sun around the earth, so Kant showed that the knowing subject played an active and creative role in the production of his world picture, rather than the static and passive role which the early Enlightenment had assigned him.
    [Show full text]
  • Can Reason Establish the Goals of Action? Assessing Interpretations of Aristotle’S Theory of Agency
    CAN REASON ESTABLISH THE GOALS OF ACTION? ASSESSING INTERPRETATIONS OF ARISTOTLE’S THEORY OF AGENCY ¿PUEDE LA RAZÓN ESTABLECER LOS FINES DE LA ACCIÓN? UNA EVALUACIÓN DE LAS INTERPRETACIONES DE LA TEORÍA DE LA ACCIÓN DE ARISTÓTELES JUAN PABLO BERMÚDEZ* Universidad Externado de Colombia. [email protected] RECIBIDO EL 12 DICIEMBRE DE 2016, APROBADO EL 5 DE MAYO DE 2017 RESUMEN ABSTRACT La interpretación de la teoría de la acción Scholarship on Aristotle’s theory of de Aristóteles ha tendido recientemente action has recently tended towards hacia una postura intelectualista, según la an intellectualist position, according to cual la razón está a cargo de establecer los which reason is in charge of establishing fi nes de las acciones. Un resurgimiento del the ends of actions. A resurgence of anti-intelectualismo, según el cual establecer anti-intellectualism, according to which los fi nes es tarea del carácter y no de la establishing ends is a task of character razón, ha puesto esta postura bajo crítica. and not of reason, has placed this position Este ensayo sostiene que ninguna de las under criticism.. This paper argues that dos interpretaciones puede dar cuenta neither of the two interpretations can suficiente de las complejidades de la suffi ciently account for the complexities teoría de Aristóteles, y sugiere un camino of Aristotle’s theory, and suggests an intermedio que combina las fortalezas de intermediate path that combines the ambas, evitando a la vez sus difi cultades. strengths of both while avoiding their El problema crucial del intelectualismo difficulties. The crucial problem for es que Aristóteles asevera explícitamente intellectualism is that Aristotle asserts que la razón no puede establecer los fi nes explicitly that reason cannot establish the de la acción.
    [Show full text]