The Rationalists: Spinoza and Leibniz PHIL10086 2020-21

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Rationalists: Spinoza and Leibniz PHIL10086 2020-21 The Rationalists: Spinoza and Leibniz PHIL10086 2020-21 Course Organiser Pauline Phemister Dugald Stewart Building, room 6.04 Tel: 0131 651 3747 Email: [email protected] Course Secretary Anne-Marie Cowe PPLS Undergraduate Teaching Office Dugald Stewart Building, room G.06 Tel: 0131 650 3961 Email: [email protected] Times and Locations Semester 1 Information about class timing and format will be on the LEARN page for the course. Assessment Mid-term essay (30%) to be submitted by 12 noon on Thursday 22nd October. Word limit: 1,500 words Final essay (70%) to be submitted by 12 noon on Thursday 10th December. Word limit: 3,000 words Participation (5%) judged by seminar attendance and Learn Discussion Board participation Course Aims and Objectives The course will introduce students to the philosophical systems of the Dutch philosopher, Benedict de Spinoza and the German thinker, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Responding critically to, but still working within the framework of, Cartesian dualism, Spinoza and Leibniz respectively transformed the Cartesian philosophy in two radically different directions, resulting in (i) Spinoza’s absolute monism and, in critical response also to Spinoza, (ii) the dynamic, pluralist philosophical system of Leibniz. In this course, we will compare and assess the philosophical arguments that led each philosopher to hold similar but also radically divergent views on the nature of reality, mind and body, God, and the ethical life. Lecture/Seminar Content: Provisional Outline Week 1: Introduction and Substance (Spinoza) Essential Reading: Spinoza, Ethics 1, Definitions 1-8, Axioms 1-7, Ethics 2, Postulates 1-4 (located immediately before Ethics 2, Proposition 14) Spinoza, Ethics 1, Proposition 5 and Demonstration Melamed, Yitzak (2017). 'The Building Blocks of Spinoza's Metaphysics: Substance, Attributes, and Modes'. In Michael Della Rocca, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza (OUP), pp. 84-114 Recommended further reading: John Cottingham, The Rationalists, chapter 3; Week 2: Proofs of God’s existence (Spinoza) Essential reading: Spinoza, Ethics 1, proposition 11 and demonstrations Phemister, Pauline (2006). The Rationalists: Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz (Routledge), chapter 4, pp. 80-91 Lin, Martin ‘Spinoza’s Arguments for the Existence of God’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75:2 (2007), 269-297 Website Mapping Spinoza’s Ethics website: http://ethica.bc.edu/#/ Week 3: Spinoza’s Monism and Determinism (Spinoza) Essential reading: Spinoza, Ethics 1, proposition 14 demonstration and all the propositions and their demonstrations that are included in the proof. Spinoza, Ethics I, Proposition 5 and demonstration (the no-shared attribute thesis) Don Garrett, ‘Ethics IP5: Shared Attributes and the Basis of Spinoza’s Monism’, in J. A. Cover and Mark Kulstad, eds. Central Themes in Early Modern Philosophy, pp.69-108 Phemister, The Rationalists: Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, chapter 4, pp. 91-99 Spinoza, Ethics I, propositions 26-33, including demonstrations of the component propositions. Website Mapping Spinoza’s Ethics website: http://ethica.bc.edu/#/ Recommended further reading: Koistinen, Olli (2003). ‘Spinoza’s Proof of Necessitarianism’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(2), 283-310 Lecture 4: Mind and Body (Spinoza) Essential reading: Spinoza, Ethics 2, up to and including Ethics 2, proposition 47 Della Rocca, Michael (2008). Spinoza (Routledge), chapter 3 Steinberg, Diane (2009). ‘Knowledge in Spinoza’s Ethics’. In Olli Koistinen, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza’s ‘Ethics’ (CUP), chapter 7 Recommended further reading: Wilson, Margaret (2006). ‘Spinoza’s Theory of Knowledge’. In Don Garrett, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza (CUP), chapter 3 Website Mapping Spinoza’s Ethics website: http://ethica.bc.edu/#/ Lecture 5: Freedom: the intellectual love of God (Spinoza) Essential reading: Spinoza, Ethics 3, proposition 35 and Scholium, Ethics 4, proposition 46, plus all other propositions, corollaries and scholia, excluding their demonstrations, in Ethics 3 and 4. Spinoza, Ethics 5, paying particular attention to Ethics 5, proposition 32 and all propositions that discuss eternity or the eternal part of the mind. Steven Nadler (2018). ‘The Intellectual Love of God’. In The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza. Ed. by M. Della Rocca, (OUP), pp. 295-313 Nadler, Steven (2006). Spinoza’s Ethics: An Introduction (CUP), chapter 9 Website Mapping Spinoza’s Ethics website: http://ethica.bc.edu/#/ Recommended further reading Susan James, ‘Power and Difference: Spinoza’s Conception of Freedom’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 4:3 (1996), 207-228 : Lecture 6: Substances (Leibniz) Essential reading: Leibniz, Monadology, §§ 1-30; 63-70 Leibniz, Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas Leibniz, Discourse on Metaphysics, §§ 8-15; Leibniz, Correspondence with de Volder, Leibniz to de Volder 20 June 1703 Leibniz, 'On the Correction of Metaphysics and the Concept of Substance', Acta Eruditorum, March 1694. In Loemker, L, Philosophical Papers and Letters, 432-434. Phemister, Pauline (2001). ‘Corporeal Substances and the Discourse on Metaphysics’, Studia Leibnitiana, 33(1), 68-85 Wilson, Catherine (1989). Leibniz’s Metaphysics: a comparative and historical study, chapter 3 Essential Video Alonzi, Adam, The Life of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=jib3WN5Wpps Recommended further reading: Anthony Savile, Routledge Guidebook to Leibniz and the ‘Monadology’, chapters 3 and 4 Lecture 7: Perfection and God (Leibniz) Essential reading: Leibniz, Monadology, §§ 31-59 [ 31-39 PSR] [40-52 God] [53-59 BPW] Leibniz, ‘Whether the world increases in perfection (1694-1696?)’. In Lloyd Strickland, ed., The Shorter Leibniz Texts: A Collection of New Translations (Continuum, 2006), 196-197. Look, Brandon C. (2011) ‘Grounding the Principle of Sufficient Reason: Leibnizian Rationalism and the Humean Challenge’. In Fraenkel, C., Perinetti, D., & Smith, J.E.H., eds. The Rationalists: Between Tradition and Innovation (Springer) Blumenfeld , David (1994). ‘Perfection and Happiness in the Best Possible World’. In Nicholas Jolley, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz (Cambridge, CUP), 382-410 Recommended further reading: Voltaire, Candide Rodriguez-Peyrera, Gonzalo (2018). ‘The Principles of Contradiction, Sufficient Reason, and Identity of Indiscernibles’. In Antognazza, Rosa, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Leibniz Phemister, Pauline and Lloyd Strickland (2015). ‘Leibniz’s Monadological Positive Aesthetics’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23(6), 1214- 1234 Strickland, Lloyd (2006). ‘Leibniz on Whether the World Increases in Perfection’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 14(1), 51-68. Look, Brandon C. (2018). ‘Arguments for the Existence of God’. In Antognazza, Rosa, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Leibniz Lecture 8: Bodies (Leibniz) Essential reading: Leibniz, Monadology, §§ 60-77; Leibniz, On Body and Force, Against the Cartesians Leibniz, From the letters to Johann Bernoulli Leibniz, Notes on Some Comments by Michel Angelo Fardella Phemister, Pauline (2005). Leibniz and the Natural World (Springer), chapter 4. Phemister, Pauline (2015). ‘The Souls of Seeds’. In Adrian Nita (ed.), Leibniz’s Metaphysics and Adoption of Substantial Forms, Dordrecht: Springer, 125 – 141. Essential Podcast Were my atoms once your atoms? https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/w3cszv5r Recommended further reading: Nachtomy, Ohad (2011). ‘Leibniz on Artificial and Natural Machines; Or, What it Means to Remain a Machine to the Least of Its Parts’, in J. E. H. Smith and O. Nachtomy, eds. Machines of Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz chapter 4 Phemister, Pauline (2011). ‘Monads and Machines’, in J. E. H. Smith and Ohad Nachtomy, eds. Machines of Nature and Corporeal Substances in Leibniz, chapter 3 Lecture 9: Pre-established harmony (Leibniz) Essential Reading: Leibniz, A Specimen of Dynamics, part 2 Leibniz, A Brief Demonstration of a Notable Error of Descartes and others concerning a natural law. In Loemker, L (1959), G.W. Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters (Reidel), 296-298 Leibniz, Monadology, §§ 78-90 Leibniz, Correspondence with Arnauld, Leibniz to Arnauld, 9 October 1687 Leibniz, Postscript of a letter to Basnage de Beauval (1696) Phemister, Pauline (2011). ‘Are Mind-Body Relations Natural and Intelligible? Some Early Modern Perspectives’, in Keith Allen and Tom Stoneham, eds., Causation and Modern Philosophy (2011, London: Routledge) Phemister, Pauline (2003). ‘Exploring Leibniz’s Kingdoms: A Philosophical Analysis of Nature and Grace’, Ecothology, 7(2), 126-145 Recommended further reading: Leibniz, New System of the Nature and Communication of Substances, and of the union of the Soul and Body Phemister, Pauline (2005). Leibniz and the Natural World: activity, passivity and corporeal substances in Leibniz’s philosophy, chapter 9; Lecture 10 Rational Freedom and Contingency Essential reading: Leibniz, Discourse on Metaphysics, section 13 Leibniz, Monadology, sections 60-62 Leibniz, On Freedom and Possibility; Leibniz, Remarks on Arnauld’s Letter about My Proposition That the Individual Notion of Each Person Includes Once and for all Everything That Will Ever Happen to Him Leibniz, On Freedom Leibniz, Letter to Coste, On Human Freedom (19 December 1707) Leibniz, Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas Spinoza, Ethics 1, propositions 16-33, Ethics 2, proposition 7 Phemister, Pauline (1991). ‘Leibniz, Freedom of Will and Rationality’, Studia Leibnitiana, 23, 25-38 Lois Frankel,
Recommended publications
  • STEWART, DUGALD, 1753-1828. Dugald Stewart Letter to Olinthus Gregory, 1804
    STEWART, DUGALD, 1753-1828. Dugald Stewart Letter to Olinthus Gregory, 1804 Emory University Pitts Theology Library 1531 Dickey Drive, Suite 560 Atlanta, GA 30322 404-727-4166 Descriptive Summary Creator: Stewart, Dugald, 1753-1828. Title: Dugald Stewart Letter to Olinthus Gregory, 1804 Call Number: Manuscript Collection No. 266 Extent: 0.01 cubic ft. (1 folder) Abstract: Consists of one handwritten letter addressed to Mr. Olinthus Gregory in Woolwich, from Dugald Stewart in Edinburgh. Language: Materials entirely in English. Administrative Information Restrictions on Access Unrestricted access. Terms Governing Use and Reproduction All requests subject to limitations noted in departmental policies on reproduction. Citation [after identification of item(s)], Dugald Stewart Letter to Olinthus Gregory, Archives and Manuscript Dept., Pitts Theology Library, Emory University. Processing Processed by Courtney Williams, 2003. Collection Description Biographical Note Dugald Stewart was born on November 22, 1753 in Edinburgh, Scotland. At the age of 13, he studied at the University of Edinburgh where his father was the chair of the mathematics department. He eventually taught in the mathematics department with his father, then took over as chair after his father’s death. In 1785, he was made the professor of moral philosophy at the University of Edinburgh. Emory Libraries provides copies of its finding aids for use only in research and private study. Copies supplied may not be copied for others or otherwise distributed without prior consent of the holding repository. Dugald Stewart Letter to Olinthus Gregory, 1804 Manuscript Collection No. 266 Stewart’s chief concern was to formulate a philosophy of the mind through the use of the inductive method of Sr.
    [Show full text]
  • Objective Beauty and Subjective Dissent in Leibniz’S Aesthetics
    Zlom1_2018_Sestava 1 23.3.18 11:39 Stránka 67 Carlos Portales OBJECTIVE BEAUTY AND SUBJECTIVE DISSENT IN LEIBNIZ’S AESTHETICS CARLOS PORTALES According to the classical view, beauty is grounded on the universe’s objective harmony, defined by the formula of unity in variety. Concurrently, nature’s beauty is univocal and independent of subjective judgement. In this paper I will argue that, although Leibniz’s view coincides with this formula, his philosophy offers an explanation for subjective dissent in aesthetic judgements about nature. I will show that the acceptance of divergences on aesthetic value are the result of a conception of harmony that includes qualitative variety and dissonance. I. INTRODUCTION Leibniz’s aesthetics fall within the Pythagorean tradition in so far as he agrees that the beauty of the universe is an objective value grounded on the harmony of the cosmos. In this view, harmony is a property of systems, defined as unity in variety, which is univocal and indifferent to subjective judgement. In this paper I argue that, despite Leibniz’s complete adherence to this formula, his interpretation explains and justifies the subjective dissent in aesthetic judgements. I show that the possibility of valid divergences regarding the aesthetic value of nature is the result of a Leibnizian conception of the universe’s harmony, which includes qualitative variety and dissonance. The secondary objective of this paper is to present some aspects of the underrepresented views of Leibniz on beauty and aesthetics in general. Even though aesthetics as a discipline was baptized by a Leibnizian philosopher – namely, Alexander Baumgarten –, few papers and book chapters explain Leibniz’s own views on the topic.
    [Show full text]
  • Locke-Stewart-Mill: Philosophy of Science at Dartmouth College, 1771
    INTERNATIONAL STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, VOL. 15, NO. 2, 2001 Locke–Stewart–Mill: philosophy of science at Dartmouth College, 1771–1854 DAVID K. NARTONIS Boston, USA American colleges began to teach Locke’s philosophy of science early in the 18th century. Many religious people, however, rejected the theological implications of Locke’s philosophy and in 1769 Princeton College initiated a popular reaction against it. That year, a new president dropped Locke’s text from the curriculum and replaced it with a book by Scottish professor, Thomas Reid (1710–1796). Teaching from Reid’s book, the new president attempted to reverse Locke’s effect on the American view of science by insisting that the study of nature is an essentially religious enterprise, consisting entirely of the collection, classi cation, and generalization of facts, with no room for conjectural theories (Bozeman, 1977, pp. 5, 7, 23–28, 45, 54–61; Laudan, 1970, pp. 103–131). This reactionary movement, often called Baconianism after the 17th century English philosopher, Francis Bacon, spread from Princeton to a large sector of American Protestantism and has had a long life in religious movements such as Fundamentalism and Creation Science (Noll, 1985, 1995). Because this long-lived reaction against Locke enjoyed wide popularity in the early national period, it might be thought that Princeton was typical of American colleges at the time. But, in fact, few colleges joined Princeton in rejecting Locke or adopting Reid. As an illustration of the way most American colleges dealt with Locke’s religious implications, this paper tells the story of the philosophy of science at Dartmouth College from its founding in 1771 until 1854.
    [Show full text]
  • Paganelli HOPE Adam Smith and the Scottish Enlightenment With
    Recent Engagements with Adam Smith and the Scottish Enlightenment by Maria Pia Paganelli CHOPE Working Paper No. 2015-06 June 2015 Recent Engagements with Adam Smith and the Scottish Enlightenment Maria Pia Paganelli Trinity University [email protected] Forthcoming, History of Political Economy, 2015 Abstract Recent literature on Adam Smith and other 18th Scottish thinkers shows an engaged conversation between the Scots and today’s scholars in the sciences that deal with humans—social sciences, humanities, as well as neuroscience and evolutionary psychology. We share with the 18th century Scots preoccupations about understanding human beings, human nature, sociability, moral development, our ability to understand nature and its possible creator, and about the possibilities to use our knowledge to improve our surrounding and standards of living. As our disciplines evolve, the studies of Smith and Scottish Enlightenment evolve with them. Smith and the Scots remain our interlocutors. Keywords: adam smith, david hume, scottish enlightenment, recent literature JLE: A1; A12; A13; A14; B1; B3; B30; B31; B4; B40; B41; C9; C90 1 Forthcoming, History of Political Economy, 2015 Recent Engagements with Adam Smith and the Scottish Enlightenment 1 Maria Pia Paganelli David Levy once told me: “Adam Smith is still our colleague. He's not in the office but he's down the hall.” Recent literature on Adam Smith and the Scottish Enlightenment shows Levy right. At the time of writing, searching Econlit peer review journal articles for “Adam Smith” in the abstract gives 480 results since year 2000. Opening the search to Proquest gives 1870 results since 2000 (see Appendix 2 to get a rough sense of the size of recent literature).
    [Show full text]
  • Records of the Scottish Church History Society
    THE LESLIE CONTROVERSY, 1805 By IAN D. L. CLARK, M.A. IN the Spring of the year r805, after a violent struggle between rival factions in Edinburgh, John Leslie was appointed to the Chair of Mathe­ matics in the university, and the Moderate Party in the Church of Scotland sustained its first major defeat for more than fifty years. Historians have rightly interpreted this incident as a landmark in the story of the eventual decline and fall of the Moderates as an ecclesiastical party, and perhaps rather more controversially as a triumph for liberal and enlightened opinion in Scotland; but they have, I think, failed to understand the deeper significance of what was happening. Ecclesiastical and secular politics played an important part in the struggle, but what was really at stake was "moderatism" as a theological and ecclesiological system. In the arguments put forward by the opposing parties two radically different religious positions came into conflict. The whole framework of r8th century "rational" religion was shaken by Leslie's supporters, and many of the presuppositions upon which Moderatism had hitherto rested were destroyed. At the same time the opponents of the Moderate Party profited from the disastrous way in which the Moderate leaders handled the case. Thus from the point of view both of church politics and of theology Leslie's appointment was to have a considerable and direct influence. If this claim seems extravagant, consider some of the issues at stake. Not only did the Moderates become involved in an unusually bitter contest with their traditional evangelical opponents, but for the first time they forfeited the good opinion of the educated and professional classes in Edinburgh, and what was perhaps even more significant, they lost the support of several of the most prominent government officers in Scotland.
    [Show full text]
  • Scottish Political Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: the Case of Adam Ferguson
    Scottish Political Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: The Case of Adam Ferguson By Fania Oz-Salzberger Thesis submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Oxford Wolfson College Trinity Term, 1991 For Eli Abstract Fania Oz-Saizberger Submitted for the Wolf son College degree of D.Phil. Oxford Trinity Term, 1991 Scottish Political Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: The Case of Adam Ferguson This thesis examines the reception of the works of Adam Ferguson, a major thinker of the Scottish Enlightenment, by a range of German readers in the late eighteenth century. It provides a survey of Ferguson's main political ideas, and argues that many of his prominent German readers did not come to terms with them. The thesis contrasts the political realities and concerns of Ferguson's Scotland with the profoundly different political concerns of his German readers, and their often vague and inaccurate ideas of Scotland, and of the British constitution. Their documented responses to Ferguson's works are brought as evidence for a cumulative and complex case of misreception. The terms in which Ferguson expressed his political ideas can be fruitfully analyzed as a political language, a vocabulary of recognizable and mutually complementing political terms. After a close examination of this particular vocabulary, the thesis proceeds to show in detail how Ferguson's German translators, commentators, reviewers and readers unwittingly dismantled this vocabulary, lost or ignored its republican and activist elements, and sometimes shifted it into other vocabularies which were far removed from the author's political intentions. However, the differences between the individual readers are emphasized, not only with respect to their varied intellectual backgrounds and works, but also touching on their personal profiles as readers and thinkers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Watch-Tower in Carlyle's Sartor Resartus
    Studies in Scottish Literature Volume 29 | Issue 1 Article 12 1996 "A Strange Apartment": The aW tch-Tower in Carlyle's Sartor Resartus Ralph Jessop Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/ssl Part of the English Language and Literature Commons Recommended Citation Jessop, Ralph (1996) ""A Strange Apartment": The aW tch-Tower in Carlyle's Sartor Resartus," Studies in Scottish Literature: Vol. 29: Iss. 1. Available at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/ssl/vol29/iss1/12 This Article is brought to you by the Scottish Literature Collections at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Studies in Scottish Literature by an authorized editor of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ralph Jessop "A Strange Apartment": The Watch-Tower in Carlyle's Sartor Resartus What if many a so-called Fact were little better than a Fiction; if here we had no direct Camera-obscura Picture of the Professor's History; but only some more or less fantastic adumbration, symbolically, perhaps significantly enough, shadowing forth the same I [... 1 Could it be expeeted, indeed, that a man so known for im­ penetrable reticence as TeufelsdrOckh, would all at once frankly unlock his private citadel to an English Editor and a German Hofrath; and not rather deceptively in­ lock both Editor and Hofrath, in the labyrinthic tortuosities and covered ways of said citadel (having enticed them thither), to see, in his half-devilish way, how the fools would look?l Sartor Resartus teems with wit, irony, fun, either in the guise of, or gently mocking from beneath, its seriousness and downright difficulty.
    [Show full text]
  • The Anthropological Imagination of the Scottish Enlightenment A
    University of California Los Angeles Reasoning with Savages: The Anthropological Imagination of the Scottish Enlightenment A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in History by Randall Joseph Holt 2016 © Copyright by Randall Joseph Holt 2016 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Reasoning with Savages: The Anthropological Imagination of the Scottish Enlightenment by Randall Joseph Holt Doctor of Philosophy in History University of California, Los Angeles, 2016 Professor Peter Hanns Reill, Chair This project examines the origins and history of early anthropological thought in the philosophy of the Scottish Enlightenment during the last half of the eighteenth century. The aim of this investigation is to set into historical context the intense interest in tribal societies exhibited in the writings of the leading members of the Scottish intelligentsia. Increasing contact with and awareness of non- European societies in the eighteenth century raised the problem of accounting for both the diversities and uniformities existing among the world’s peoples and their societies. After midcentury many enlightened moral theorists drew upon the methods and epistemologies of the new natural sciences to reestablish the moral sciences on natural historical foundations. Human and social development were ii understood as analogous to generative theories posited in the vitalist life sciences of epigenesis, which was instrumental, most notably, in the stadial or “four-stages” theory of progress articulated by Adam Smith. Reinterpreting the Scottish Enlightenment in the context of vitalist thought offers greater insight into what is perhaps its preeminent idea, that of “spontaneous order.” The theorization of moral and social systems as products of human nature allowed for a far-reaching revision of the human sciences and the systems of thought upon which they were based, including natural law theory.
    [Show full text]
  • From Francis Hutcheson to James Mccosh: Irish Presbyterians and the Scottish Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century
    From Francis Hutcheson to James McCosh: Irish Presbyterians and Defining the Scottish Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century Holmes, A. R. (2014). From Francis Hutcheson to James McCosh: Irish Presbyterians and Defining the Scottish Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century. History of European Ideas, 40(5), 622-643. https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2013.851991 Published in: History of European Ideas Document Version: Peer reviewed version Queen's University Belfast - Research Portal: Link to publication record in Queen's University Belfast Research Portal Publisher rights Copyright 2013 Taylor & Francis. This is an accepted manuscript of an article published by Taylor & Francis Group in History of European Ideas on 8/11/2013, available online: http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/01916599.2013.851991. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Queen's University Belfast Research Portal is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The Research Portal is Queen's institutional repository that provides access to Queen's research output. Every effort has been made to ensure that content in the Research Portal does not infringe any person's rights, or applicable UK laws. If you discover content in the Research Portal that you believe breaches copyright or violates any law, please contact [email protected]. Download date:02. Oct. 2021 From Francis Hutcheson to James McCosh: Irish Presbyterians and defining the Scottish Philosophy in the nineteenth century Dr Andrew R.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bibliography of Scottish Common Sense Philosophy
    SCOTTISH COMMON SENSE PHILOSOPHY Sources and Origins Volume 5 Edited and Introduced by James Fieser University of Tennessee at Martin THOEMMES Scottish Common Sense Philosophy: Sources and Origins A BIBLIOGRAPHY OF SCOTTISH Edited and Introduced by James Fieser University of Tennessee at Martin, USA COMMON SENSE PHILOSOPHY Volume 1 James Oswald, An Appeal to Common Sense in Behalf of Religion (1766–1772) Volume 2 James Beattie, An Essay on the Nature and Immutability of Truth (1770) Volumes 3 and 4 Early Responses to Reid, Oswald, Beattie and Stewart Volume 5 A Bibliography of Scottish Common Sense Philosophy Edited with a Preface by James Fieser University of Tennessee at Martin THOEMMES PRESS First published by Thoemmes Press, 2000 Thoemmes Press 11 Great George Street Bristol BS1 5RR, England Thoemmes Press US Office CONTENTS 22883 Quicksilver Drive Sterling, Virginia 20166, USA Editor’s Preface vii http://www.thoemmes.com 1. John Abercrombie (1780–1844) 1 2. James Beattie (1735–1803) 10 Scottish Common Sense Philosophy: Sources and Origins 5 Volumes : ISBN 1 85506 825 7 3. Thomas Brown (1778–1820) 34 4. George Campbell (1719–1796) 41 © James Fieser, 2000 5. James Dunbar (1742–1798) 56 6. David Fordyce (1711–1751) 58 7. Alexander Gerard (1728–1795) 62 8. William Hamilton (1788–1856) 66 9. Henry Home, Lord Kames (1696–1782) 78 10. James Oswald (1703–1793) 97 11. Thomas Reid (1710–1796) 102 British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data 12. Dugald Stewart (1753–1828) 123 A CIP record of this title is available from the British Library All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any way or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the written permission of the copyright holder.
    [Show full text]
  • Information About Class Timing and Format Will Be on the LEARN Page for the Course
    PHILOSOPHY AND THE ENVIRONMENT 2020-21 PHIL 10064 (MA Honours) Course Organiser Pauline Phemister Dugald Stewart Building, room 6.04 Tel: 0131 651 3747 Email: [email protected] Course Secretary Anne-Marie Cowe PPLS Undergraduate Teaching Office Dugald Stewart Building, room G.06 Tel: 0131 650 3961 Email: [email protected] Times and Locations Semester 2 Information about class timing and format will be on the LEARN page for the course. Assessment Mid-term essay (30%) to be submitted by 12 noon on Thursday 25th February 2021. Word limit: 1,500 words Final essay (65%) to be submitted by 12 noon on Thursday 15th April 2021. Word limit: 3,000 words Participation (5%) will be assessed by seminar attendance and Learn Discussion Board participation Course Outline In this course, we examine the deep ecological philosophy of Arne Naess that takes its inspiration from the monist philosophy of Benedict de Spinoza and will contrast with the ecophilosophy of Phemister inspired by the pluralist philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. We will explore issues of interconnectedness of living and nonliving entities, the relational identities of living beings, Naess’s notions of Self- realisation and Wide-identification, as well as questions concerning intrinsic, instrumental, relational, moral, aesthetic and spiritual values. We will also consider moral and aesthetic issues relating to bio- and onto-egalitarianism, biodiversity and variety, progress and the ideal of perfection. Lecture/Seminar Content: Provisional Outline Week 1 Shallow and Deep Ecology Movements, Ecophilosophy and Ecosophy Core Reading Naess, Ecology, Community and Lifestyle, pp. 21-47 Naess (1973). ‘The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary’, Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 16:1-4, 95-100.
    [Show full text]
  • Life of Adam Smith
    Life of Adam Smith John Rae Life of Adam Smith By JOHN RAE London MACMILLAN & CO. AND NEW YORK 1895 PREFACE The fullest account we possess of the life of Adam Smith is still the memoir which Dugald Stewart read to the Royal Society of Edinburgh on two evenings of the winter of 1793, and which he subsequently published as a separate work, with many additional illustrative notes, in 1810. Later biographers have made few, if any, fresh contributions to the subject. But in the century that has elapsed since Stewart wrote, many particulars about Smith and a number of his letters have incidentally and by very scattered channels found their way into print. It will be allowed to be generally desirable, in view of the continued if not even increasing importance of Smith, to obtain as complete a view of his career and work as it is still in our power to recover; and it appeared not unlikely that some useful contribution to this end might result if all those particulars and letters to which I have alluded were collected together, and if they were supplemented by such unpublished letters and information as it still remained possible to procure. In this last part of my task I have been greatly assisted by the Senatus of the University of Glasgow, who have most kindly supplied me with an extract of every passage in the College records bearing on Smith; by the Council of the Royal Society of Edinburgh, who have granted me every facility for using the Hume Correspondence, which is in their custody; and by the Senatus of the University of Edinburgh for a similar courtesy with regard to the Carlyle Correspondence and the David Laing MSS.
    [Show full text]