PB Cover Template 2016.Indd

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PB Cover Template 2016.Indd Reviews 297 from shallow criticisms and vindicates his legit- continues and responds seriously to the works of imate claims to pre-eminence at the bar of both both Arendt and Baudrillard. Naming anything, the scholarly judgement and public opinion. A and in this case, evil as it is, demands existential lengthy bibliography at the end of the book adds honesty in an atmosphere which does not want value to the book. to discuss this ancient problem of evil which the N Hariharan Russian philosopher Nikolai Berdyaev felt was Madurai unsolvable. Neiman’s book’s praxis lies in its very existence: if we neglect the study of evil, geno- Evil In Modern Thought: cides and terrorism will continue. Neiman, unlike An Alternative History of most career philosophers, discusses terrorism in Philosophy detail near the end of her book. The book under Susan Neiman review has established the urgency of studying evil if one wants to truly comprehend what the Princeton University Press, 41 Wil- liam Street, Princeton, New Jersey philosopher-turned-novelist, Iris Murdoch had 08540. usa. www.press.princeton.edu. called the ‘Sovereignty of the Good’ (See Iris Mur- 2015. xxii + 382 pp. pb. $24.95. doch, The Sovereignty of Good (London: Routledge, isbn 9780691168500. 1967)), which is the telos of all history, including Neiman’s own reading of the history of philoso- annah Arendt wrote about evil being so phy as we find here. Neiman does not write on evil banal that one does not recognise it when to exalt in it but to show how the sovereign nature Hit is encountered in its esse (See Hannah Arendt, of the good has been repeatedly apparently dis- Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of placed by the existence of evil. Evil is no privatio Evil (New York: Penguin, 1963). Arendt is central boni or simulation vide Jean Baudrillard; it is very to any study of evil today and in her Afterword in much a happening phenomenon. This reviewer this revised edition of her book originally pub- has discussed about evil in Subhasis Chattopa- lished in 2002, Neiman re-evaluates Arendt. We dhyay, ‘Prolegomenon to the Study of Evil’, Pra- will have the opportunity to speak of Arendt at buddha Bharata, 118/4 (April 2013), 278–81, 293. the end of this review. Neiman has done successfully what no other Jean Baudrillard sees evil as an intractable contemporary philosopher has the temerity to virus which has infected the cosmos: do: she has shown how the history of philosophy In a society which seeks—by prophylactic meas- demands new (mis)readings qua responses since ures, by annihilating its own natural referents, evil is inherent in the esse of the idea of the being by whitewashing violence, by exterminating all in the here and the now. Except Arendt and Bau- germs and all of the accursed share, by perform- drillard and to some extent Giorgio Agamben, ing cosmetic surgery on the negative—to con- contemporary philosophers have been silent on cern itself solely with quantified management the problem of evil. Neiman says: and with the discourse of the Good, in a society The picture of modern philosophy as cen- where it is no longer possible to speak Evil, Evil tered in epistemology and driven by the desire to has metamorphosed into all the viral and ter- ground our representations is so tenacious that roristic forms that obsess us (Jean Baudrillard, some philosophers are prepared to bite the bul- The Transparency of Evil: Essays on Extreme Phe- let and declare the effort simply wasted. Rorty, nomena, trans. James Benedict (London: Verso, for example, finds it easier to reject modern phil- 2002), 81). osophy altogether than to reject the standard Susan Neiman’s book makes it possible once accounts of its history. His narrative is more po- again to speak of evil explicitly; and thus seek lemical than most, but it’s a polemical version of ways to annihilate it. Her act of including the the story told in most philosophy departments word ‘evil’ in the title of the book is the begin- in the second half of the twentieth century. ... ning of her cultural work as a philosopher who What began as metaphysics—the description of PB January 2016 287 298 Prabuddha Bharata the basic structure of reality—ended as episte- Why is it that some of the best minds of this and mology: the attempt to ground the foundations the last centuries avoid the issue of Hitler? Why of our knowledge (5–6). do philosophy courses stress the abstract over the Empirical research bears out the truth of her practical lived experience of the individual in the important thesis that the larger thematic study of here and the now? Evil, that is ‘absolute wrongdo- the problem of evil took a backseat in professional ing that leaves no room for account or expiation’ discourses of philosophy during the last century (3), apparently defies all analyses. Thus, the reality and even in this century professional philosophers and the inexplicability of evil forces an otherwise shy away from discussing the problem of evil since rigorous Alvin Plantinga to lose himself in the jug- contemporary philosophy has engaged itself with glery of logic while justifying the truth of evil and a ‘timeless matters’ like ‘Goodness, truth, and beauty’ benign God. Neiman’s concern in this book is not (xvii). Yet ‘Every time we make the judgment this God per se but rather the reality and inevitability ought not to have happened, we are stepping onto of evil in all its forms and particularly, for example, a path that leads straight to the problem of evil. ... why David Hume needs to be reread to under- For it involves questions more natural, urgent, and stand evil—Neiman reads Immanuel Kant and pervasive than the skeptical epistemological quan- then through him judges Hume and how the latter daries said to drive modern philosophy’ (5). Nei- had effected the current course of philosophy and man is bold enough to attack Richard Rorty; a fact emasculated the academic domain or the study of that will ensure that she remains a prophetic and philosophy. The section ‘The Impotence of Rea- therefore a marginalised voice within mainstream son: David Hume’ in the second chapter is a tour philosophy. Martha Nussbaum, in her magnum de force in itself that should be made compulsory opus The Fragility of Goodness, for instance, keeps reading in all philosophy syllabi. This reviewer has defining what Aristotle thought about the good life scoured the internet and called up professional (See Martha C Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness philosophers asking them whether they have read (London: Cambridge University, 2001)). She, like Neiman’s contentions regarding Hume vis-à-vis Neiman, is a Jew; but she simply cannot face the Immanuel Kant elsewhere. None has. This chapter spectre of Hitler. Yet she is venerated globally as is sufficient reason for us to consider Neiman as the philosopher of Cosmopolitanism. How does one of the greatest philosophers alive. reviving Cosmopolitanism from the detritus of the Philosophers are notoriously bad stylists, but philosophy of the Cynics help one prevent the re- Neiman’s style is cosy and jargon-free: currence of the rise of another Hitler escapes this The question could be raised during a conver- reviewer. Nussbaum nowhere attacks Rorty or A J sational lull in a good salon: would you live Ayer—if she did so, she would not have been known your life over, if given the chance? Eighteenth- universally as a humanist. Neiman errs on the side century thinkers took a rest from more serious of being a rigorous scholar and pays for her rigour business by discussing it. Few of them were en- by remaining relatively yet undeservedly unknown. tirely clear about the form of the question. Were In this book Neiman shows us how the Hitler they seeking an empirical survey, or a normative event should have been tackled by professional claim? Were they asking whether people in gen- philosophers and what exactly needs to be done eral, and any one of us in particular, would in to prevent mass genocides of the nature com- fact repeat their lives over—or whether it would, mitted by the Nazis. Neiman studies the Lisbon on balance, be reasonable to do so? (206). earthquake and discusses Leibnitz and then cor- This is how Neiman begins writing on Ni- rectly points out the epistemic retreat enacted etzsche in the section ‘Eternal Choices: Nietzsche by contemporary thinkers—this statement too on Redemption’ in the third chapter. Anyone fa- has ensured that she remains an academic par- miliar with Nietzsche will know from the title iah. She is the only voice writing today asking the that Neiman is going to scrutinise Nietzsche in a right questions: what happened to philosophis- way he has not been evaluated before: one should ing which dealt with the hard questions of life? read this section for the scope of Neiman’s own 288 PB January 2016 Reviews 299 readings in philosophy and ancient Greek drama Reason: Rereading Kant (See Susan Neiman, The and for her power to connect philosophers as Unity of Reason: Rereading Kant (New York: Ox- disparate as Voltaire and Hegel with Nietzsche ford University, 1997)) had established her as a keeping in mind her stated aim in this book. She moral philosopher and this book secures her place never forgets to point out how all major Contin- as the only philosopher writing now worth reading, ental philosophers were writing willy-nilly on the both for the truth about the history of philosophy problem of evil.
Recommended publications
  • An Interpretation of Kant's Political Philosophy in Light of His Critical-Regulative Method
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 11-2011 Politics, history, critique: An interpretation of Kant's political philosophy in light of his critical-regulative method. Dilek Huseyinzadegan DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Huseyinzadegan, Dilek, "Politics, history, critique: An interpretation of Kant's political philosophy in light of his critical-regulative method." (2011). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 110. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/110 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. POLITICS, HISTORY, CRITIQUE: AN INTERPRETATION OF KANT’S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY IN LIGHT OF HIS CRITICAL-REGULATIVE METHOD A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October 2011 By Dilek Huseyinzadegan Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois Acknowledgements This dissertation would not have been possible without the help and support of many people. The Department of Philosophy at DePaul University provided a doctoral scholarship for eight years of graduate study. I thank the faculty for their help and support throughout this process, especially my dissertation director Avery Goldman, whose approach to Kant and his method inspired this project in the first place, my committee members Elizabeth Millàn, Kevin Thompson, and Rick Lee, whose graduate seminars gave rise to numerous fruitful discussions on German Idealism and Romanticism, history and politics, and critical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Problem of Evil' in the Context of The
    The ‘Problem of Evil’ in the Context of the French Enlightenment: Bayle, Leibniz, Voltaire, de Sade “The very masterpiece of philosophy would be to develop the means Providence employs to arrive at the ends she designs for man, and from this construction to deduce some rules of conduct acquainting this wretched two‐footed individual with the manner wherein he must proceed along life’s thorny way, forewarned of the strange caprices of that fatality they denominate by twenty different titles, and all unavailingly, for it has not yet been scanned nor defined.” ‐Marquis de Sade, Justine, or Good Conduct Well Chastised (1791) “The fact that the world contains neither justice nor meaning threatens our ability both to act in the world and to understand it. The demand that the world be intelligible is a demand of practical and of theoretical reason, the ground of thought that philosophy is called to provide. The question of whether [the problem of evil] is an ethical or metaphysical problem is as unimportant as it is undecidable, for in some moments it’s hard to view as a philosophical problem at all. Stated with the right degree of generality, it is but unhappy description: this is our world. If that isn’t even a question, no wonder philosophy has been unable to give it an answer. Yet for most of its history, philosophy has been moved to try, and its repeated attempts to formulate the problem of evil are as important as its attempts to respond to it.” ‐Susan Neiman, Evil in Modern Thought – An Alternative History of Philosophy (2002) Claudine Lhost (Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy with Honours) This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of Murdoch University, Perth, Western Australia in 2012 1 I declare that this thesis is my own account of my research and contains as its main content work which has not previously been submitted for a degree at any tertiary education institution.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHICAL PRACTICE474 Journal of the APPA
    PHILOSOPHICAL PRACTICE474 Journal of the APPA Volume 4 Number 2 July 2009 Occasional Piece Editor Lou Marinoff Buddha, Freud, Kohlberg and The Middle Way Todd Eklof Associate Editor Seamus Carey Articles Reviews Editor Troy Camplin Would Socrates be Diagnosed as Mentally Ill? Peter B. Raabe Managing Editor Philosophers, Ethics and Emotions Lauren Tillinghast Lydia B. Amir William James on ‘Immortality’ Technical Consultant Michael Grosso Greg Goode Supervision and Case Notes in Philosophical Counselling Practice Legal Consultant Kate Mehuron Thomas Griffith Reviews Moral Clarity Jeremy Bendik-Keymer Against Happiness: In Praise of Melancholy Reinhard Zaiser Save the World on Your Own Time Nancy Matchett The Veil of Isis: an Essay on the History of the Idea of Nature Jason van Boom www.appa.edu Nemo Veritatem Regit ISSN 1742-8181 Nobody Governs Truth Philosophical Practice, July 2009, 4.2: 475-7 475 Book Review Susan Neiman, Moral Clarity, a Guide for Grown-up Idealists (Harcourt, New York: 2008), ISBN 978-0-15-101197-1 (hardcover). REVIEWED BY JEREMY BENDIK-KEYMER LEMOYNE LOLLEGE, SYRACUSE, NY For Susan Neiman, there are two fundamental distinctions that structure the world: the distinc- tion between is and ought, and the distinction between the innocent and the unjust. Moral Clarity is an attempt to develop a Kantian-inspired response to contemporary politics in America and to life in global capitalism that is shaped by these two distinctions. In the process, Neiman provides a rereading of Abraham—disabusing us of Kierkegaard’s version—a defense of the Enlightenment, a reading of Odysseus as a modern hero, and a clear and helpful addition to virtue ethics: focus on heroes.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz, Evil, and the Best of All Possible Worlds
    17 FALSE OPTIMISM? LEIBNIZ, EVIL, AND THE BEST OF ALL POSSIBLE WORLDS LLOYD STRICKLAND University of Wales, Lampeter Abstract. Leibniz’s claim that this is the best of all possible worlds has been sub- ject to numerous criticisms, both from his contemporaries and ours. In this paper I investigate a cluster of such criticisms based on the existence, abundance or character of worldly evil. As several Leibniz-inspired versions of optimism have been advanced in recent years, the aim of my investigation is to assess not just how Leibniz’s brand of optimism fares against these criticisms, but also whether optimism as a philosophy has the resources to meet these challenges. I show that none of the criticisms considered has sufficient force to pose a threat to Leibniz’s version of optimism or to one modelled on it. INTRODUCTION Leibniz’s doctrine of optimism, which holds that our world is the best of all those possible, has undoubtedly been one of the most vilified in the history of western philosophy. Its eighteenth-century critics – like those of today – tended either to treat it dismissively, as if the doctrine was un- worthy of proper refutation, or to engage it with great passion. Many of the objections developed in the decades following Leibniz’s most public airing of the doctrine in his Theodicy (1710) are still made today, such is their perceived strength; to these, various other objections have been added over the years, and their number continues to swell due to the efforts of contemporary thinkers who find Leibniz’s views no less objectionable than did their philosophical forebears.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Clarity: a Guide for Grown-Up Idealists, by Susan Neiman." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 47.3 (2009) : 579-586
    Osgoode Hall Law Journal Article 5 Volume 47, Number 3 (Fall 2009) Book Review: Moral Clarity: A Guide For Grown- Up Idealists, by Susan Neiman Annalise Acorn Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj Book Review Citation Information Acorn, Annalise. "Book Review: Moral Clarity: A Guide For Grown-Up Idealists, by Susan Neiman." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 47.3 (2009) : 579-586. http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol47/iss3/5 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Osgoode Hall Law Journal by an authorized editor of Osgoode Digital Commons. 579 Book Review MORAL CLARITY: A GUIDE FOR GROWN-UP IDEALISTS, by Susan Neiman 1 ANNALISE ACORN 2 NOWHERE IS THE CALL TO "BE REALISTIC" more ubiquitous than in law schools and legal practice; nowhere is a commitment to ideals more at risk for being taken as a lapse of intelligence. Susan Neiman's book, Moral Clarity: A Guide for Grown-up Idealists,' should, therefore, be of considerable interest to those who want to resist the cynicism of legal culture and who believe that law is-and should be-about justice and changing the world for the better. The book provides solid intellectual backing for all who aspire to use their intellects and life energies to identify and close the gap between "is and ought," and this is no less so for lawyers who hope to enlist the law in that endeavor. Neiman masterfully takes on the champions of moral relativism-thinkers who have powerfully influenced not just philosophy and politics, but also the legal academy.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Nietzsche Studies
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies On the very idea of "justifying suffering" --Manuscript Draft-- Manuscript Number: Full Title: On the very idea of "justifying suffering" Article Type: Special Issue Article (by invitation only) Corresponding Author: Chris Janaway University of Southampton UNITED KINGDOM Corresponding Author E-Mail: [email protected] Abstract: Many commentators have said that Nietzsche is concerned, either in all or in some parts of his career, with providing a kind of "theodicy", or with justifying or finding meaning in suffering. This article examines these notions, questioning whether terms such as "theodicy" or "justifying suffering" are helpful in getting Nietzsche's views into focus, and exploring some unclarities concerning the way in which such terms themselves are understood. The article discusses the notion of "aesthetic justification" in The Birth of Tragedy, arguing that here "justification" is used in the very loose sense of "enabling a positive attitude toward." Nietzsche's retrospective "Attempt at a Self- Criticism" is then examined, and it is argued that here Nietzsche does not endorse his earlier notion of aesthetic justification, but rather praises The Birth of Tragedy for its refusal to find a moral meaning in existence. This negative virtue is presented in explicit contrast to Schopenhauer's claim that the world has a moral meaning that metaphysics can discover. Schopenhauer rejects the optimistic moral meaning provided by theism, but replaces it with a pessimistic meaning: the world is in itself such that its non-existence would have been better. This shows that there can be meaning in existence that does not correlate with affirmation.
    [Show full text]
  • Eichmann in Athens: Hannah Arendt and the New Problem of Evil
    1 An expanded version of a talk to be given at St. John’s College, Santa Fe, NM on Friday, April 18, 2008. Eichmann in Athens: Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the New Problem of Evil Lawrence Vogel Connecticut College I. Religious and Secular Theodicies: Providence and Progress Evil is a problem for its victims, to be sure, but that doesn’t make it a philosophical problem. If, like Sophie, you are invited to choose which child to save and which to have carted off to the gas chambers, or, like some Tutsi men in Rwanda, you are forced at gunpoint by the Hutu militia to bite off your father’s penis, and then your father is put in a similar position towards you, you have problems. But, as Nietzsche remarks, the philosophical problem arises not from suffering as such but from the apparent senselessness of so much suffering. We can bear torment if we believe it serves a greater purpose or higher meaning. In our Western philosophical tradition, the so-called “problem of evil” has been defined quite narrowly in terms of “theodicy”: the view that the world was created by an almighty, just God. Any reasonable believer must ask: why does God allow there to be evil – and so much of it – in the world? Theodicy solves the problem by holding that suffering, whether inflicted by “acts of God” or men, is “justified”: a rationally necessary means to an overall good end, an indispensable chapter in a larger, harmonious story. According to theodicy, whatever happens occurs “for a good reason.” Evil is not a positive reality, but a privation of the good: a “merely apparent” part of “the bigger 2 picture” that, if only we had access to it, would reveal even the most grotesque events to be for the best, all things considered.
    [Show full text]
  • Neiman, Susan
    Victims and Heroes SUSAN NEIMAN T T L H V Delivered at University of Michigan March , ¥ is the director of the Einstein Forum, an international interdisciplinary think tank in Berlin. Born in Atlanta, Georgia, Neiman studied philosophy at Harvard under the great twentieth-century phi- losopher John Rawls and at the Freie Universität in Berlin, before teach- ing philosophy at Yale and Tel Aviv Universities. She is the author of Slow Fire: Jewish Notes om Berlin ( ), e Unity of Reason: Rereading Kant ( ), Evil in Modern ought (), and Moral Clarity: A Guide for Grown-Up Idealists ( ). What leads a Kantian to think about heroes? ose who nd it puzzling may have read no further in Kant’s ethics than the Groundwork, which focuses on rules for deciding which actions are moral. In teaching moral- ity, however, Kant thinks heroes should stand at the fore. We learn to make moral judgments by examining the characters of men and women who act morally. e test of moral activity, as opposed to self-serving action that happens to coincide with it, is heroism. Learning to make moral judgments by examining heroic exemplars is so natural, and eec- tive, that Kant recommends it even for “businessmen, women, and ten year old children.” But the apparent odd coupling of Kant and the hero reects some- thing much deeper than textual ignorance. e belief that heroes are romantic, and the Enlightenment is not, is very widespread. Whether they view it as a reason for regret or relief, most people agree that the Enlightenment opened a postheroic age.
    [Show full text]
  • The Root of Heidegger's Concern for the Earth At
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 17, no. 1, 2021 EVIL AS A MODAL MISMATCH: ON HEGEL’S DISTINCTION BETWEEN WHAT IS AND WHAT OUGHT TO BE Jose L. Fernandez ABSTRACT: G.W.F. Hegel argues that a philosophy of history should engender comprehension of evil in the world. And yet some commentators have charged his philosophy with transcending mere explication by justifying the existence of these evils. In defense of his words, Hegel famously characterizes evil as a modal mismatch; namely, as the incompatibility between what is given and what ought to be the case. Unfortunately, some readers of Hegel’s grand narrative either continue to struggle with or overlook this fine distinction. Against such readings, I organize my paper into three sections that speak directly to these concerns. In §1, against the concern that Hegel’s view of the “actual world” justifies suffering, it is shown that his philosophy does not endorse the merely extant world, which is a whole world apart from the actual world. In §2, I articulate the premises of Hegel’s Doppelsatz to argue that the famous slogan is not, as some commentators take it, an endorsement of “things as they are.” And in §3, I expose a category error that mistakes an epistemological claim made by Hegel about contingency as a metaphysical assertion in support of evil. Ultimately, I argue that Hegel views evil as neither actual nor necessary nor justified. KEYWORDS: Hegel; Actuality; Contingency; Evil; History G.W.F. Hegel argues that a philosophy of history should engender comprehension of evil in the world.1 And yet some commentators, past and present, view his philosophy not as an explication but as an attempt to justify the existence of these evils.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Schopenhauer's Philosophy of Pessimism
    University of Southampton Research Repository ePrints Soton Copyright © and Moral Rights for this thesis are retained by the author and/or other copyright owners. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the copyright holder/s. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given e.g. AUTHOR (year of submission) "Full thesis title", University of Southampton, name of the University School or Department, PhD Thesis, pagination http://eprints.soton.ac.uk UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON FACULTY OF HUMANITIES Department of Philosophy Schopenhauer’s Pessimism by David Woods Thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy July 2014 i UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON ABSTRACT FACULTY OF HUMANITIES Philosophy Thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy SCHOPENHAUER’S PESSIMISM David Woods In this thesis I offer an interpretation of Arthur Schopenhauer’s pessimism. I argue against interpreting Schopenhauer’s pessimism as if it were merely a matter of temperament, and I resist the urge to find a single standard argument for pessimism in Schopenhauer’s work. Instead, I treat Schopenhauer’s pessimism as inherently variegated, composed of several distinct but interrelated pessimistic positions, each of which is supported by its own argument. I begin by examining Schopenhauer’s famous argument that willing necessitates suffering, which I defend against the misrepresentative interpretation advocated by Ivan Soll.
    [Show full text]
  • Susan Neiman, Potsdam Einstein Forum Am Neuen Markt 7 14467
    Chair: Susan Neiman, Potsdam Einstein Forum Am Neuen Markt 7 14467 Potsdam Tel.: 0331 271 78 0 Fax: 0331 271 78 27 http://www.einsteinforum.de [email protected] Participants Aleida Assmann, Konstanz “The Beauty of Truth is That It Cannot be Possessed” Reflections on Karl Jaspers and John Milton My lecture brings together two authors who lived 300 years apart. Coming from different nations, languages and cultural backgrounds, John Milton and Karl Jaspers emphatically defended truth in texts written in the 1640s and the 1940s, protecting it against political appropriation and its fusion with power. Both of them shared a strong commitment to truth but were convinced that truth had to be distanced from human reach. Bringing their texts and ideas together, I will present them as pluralistic thinkers who respected difference and discovered new similarities. Aleida Assmann is Professor Emerita of English Literature and Literary Theory at the University of Konstanz, Germany, where she taught from 1993–2014. She received an Honorary Degree from the University of Oslo (2008) and the Max Planck Research Award (2009). Her main areas of research are historical anthropology, history of media, history and theory of reading and writing, cultural memory, with special emphasis on Holocaust and trauma. Publications in English include Memory in a Global Age: Discourses, Practices, and Trajectories (ed. with Sebastian Conrad, 2010); Cultural Memory and Western Civilization: Functions, Media, Archives (2012); Memory and Political Change (ed. with Linda Shortt, 2012); Shadows of Trauma: Memory and the Politics of Postwar Identity (2016) and Empathy and its Limits (ed. with Ines Detmers, 2016).
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Kant from a Catholic Horizon: Ethics and the Anthropology of Grace
    Theological Studies 71 (2010) READING KANT FROM A CATHOLIC HORIZON: ETHICS AND THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF GRACE PHILIP J. ROSSI, S.J. For two centuries Catholic philosophers and theologians have gen- erally treated Immanuel Kant’s critical philosophy as incompatible with principles fundamental to Catholic accounts of the human condition in relation to God. This article argues that contemporary scholarship—particularly about the role of anthropological con- cerns in the critical project—indicates that Kant’s understanding of finite human freedom provides a basis for Catholic theology to engage his thinking positively in the articulation of a theology of grace for humanity’s postmodern context. HIS ARTICLE ARGUES FOR a renewed Catholic theological engagement Twith the critical philosophy of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804). It advances this argument within the context of a larger thesis about the theological presuppositions that function within Kant’s work, as well as within interpretations both friend and foe of his philosophy have given to his project of “critique.” This thesis is that key differences in the ways both philosophers and theologians have understood central elements of the critical philosophy frequently exhibit divergent “theological horizons” against which these interpreters have explicitly or, more often, implicitly framed their rendering of the issues, arguments, and concepts in Kant’s texts. Such theological horizons function, in the first instance, on Kant’s own part, inasmuch as the critical philosophy articulates its account of human finitude over against a robust sense of transcendence. For Kant, fundamental to the conceptual space of the human—i.e., to the articulation of an account of what distinctively constitutes our humanity—is the orien- PHILIP J.
    [Show full text]